Short abstract
Assisted dying remains highly topical and debated, both in the public and medical arena. All practising physicians in the UK who care for dying patients should be aware of the proposed legislation and the potential effects on their clinical practice.
Keywords: assisted dying, assisted suicide, death, euthanasia, palliative care
Physician assisted death is a legal activity in certain parts of the world but not presently the UK (for example, the state of Oregon following the 1997 Death with Dignity Act and in the Netherlands under the 2001 Termination of Life on Request and Assisted Suicide Act).1 Surveys suggest around 56% of doctors and 82% of the general public favour assisted dying.2,3
If legalised, it is estimated that 13 000 deaths a year may result from physician assisted suicide in the UK.4 The debate regarding physician assisted death is complex involving many legal, ethical, medical, sociocultural, personal, and religious issues.
In this article we describe the important provisions of the proposed Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill in the UK and summarise the arguments for and against such legislation.
Assisted death: definition of terms
Before elaborating on the Bill and for and against arguments it is necessary to clarify terms relating to assisted death (table 1). “Assisted death” incorporates both physician assisted suicide and voluntary euthanasia, and the current version of the bill only relates to physician assisted suicide.
Table 1 Physician assisted suicide and euthanasia: definitions of terms1,5,6.
Physician assisted suicide | Making a means of suicide available to a patient with knowledge of the patient's intention to kill himself or herself. The final act resulting in death is undertaken by the patient (for example, taking pills provided by the physician). |
Euthanasia | Someone other than the patient performs an act (for example, administering a lethal injection) with the intent to end the patient's life. Euthanasia derives from the Greek words “Eu” (good) and “thanatos” (death): a good death. |
Voluntary active euthanasia: act of killing a person at his or her request | |
Involuntary active euthanasia: act of killing a person who, while competent opposes being killed | |
Non‐voluntary active euthanasia: act of killing a person who is incapable of making an informed request. |
It is also important to note the legal and ethical “distinction” between physician assisted death and other end of life issues such as withdrawing and withholding life prolonging treatment, do not attempt resuscitation orders, and the appropriate provision of medication to relieve pain that may (but not necessarily) incidentally hastens death (the doctrine of double effect7).1,8 Furthermore, while this distinction is made, it may be argued that morally these issues are indistinct from assisted death as all may hasten death.9
Proposed legislation for assisted dying in the UK
Background
In 2003 Lord Joffe introduced a bill (The Patient (Assisted Dying) Bill of 2003) to the House of Lords that, if enacted, would legalise assisted dying. The current version of the bill (the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill of 2004)10 is a revised version with a number of important amendments. In particular, the current proposed legislation would only legalise physician assisted suicide and not euthanasia and physicians who conscientiously object would not now be under an obligation to refer a patient requesting assisted suicide to another physician who would agree to do so.
The bill has been considered by a Select Committee of the House of Lords and debated in May 2006 at which time the majority of peers voted to delay the bill's second reading for six months.11
The Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill 2004
The purpose of the current proposed legislation is to “enable an adult who has capacity and who is suffering unbearably as a result of a terminal illness to receive medical assistance to die at his own considered and persistent request; and for connected purposes”. Terminal illness being one that is inevitably progressive, the effects of which cannot be reversed by treatment, and that will be likely to result in the patient's death within a few months.10
In summary, the proposed legislation would mean that10:
any patient considering assisted suicide would inform their physician in writing of their request
the patient must be fully informed of their medical diagnosis, their prognosis and the process of being assisted to die
the patient must also be informed (but not necessarily have experienced) of the alternatives to assisted dying “included, but not limited to palliative care, care in a hospice and the control of pain” by a palliative care doctor or nurse
the physician must be satisfied that the patient does not lack capacity, that they have a terminal illness, and are “suffering unbearably” as a result
The patient must also have been seen by a second “independent” physician who agrees these criteria are met
If there is doubt about capacity then an opinion from a psychiatrist or psychologist is also required.
If the above criteria are met the patient would then sign an independently witnessed declaration
A period of 14 days must pass before assistance to die is made during which time that patient may revoke their declaration
While this bill has been opposed by a number of key organisations and colleges (notably the Royal College of General Practitioners,12 the Association of Palliative Medicine,13 and the British Geriatrics Society14), others have expressed a neutral position (for example, the British Medical Association2,16). This reflects the division of opinion among the medical profession itself. The Royal College of Physicians has recently changed its position from “neutral” to “against” a change in legislation (a synopsis of the position statements of these organisations is shown in table 2).
Table 2 Synopsis of position statements of some key UK medical colleges and organisations.
Royal College of Physicians (RCP) | Position: against |
Irrespective of whether the bill is enacted, it should be seen as a further signal to campaign for better care for dying patients including an extension of palliative care services and discussion of end of life issues in the face of changing values, ethnic diversity, and technological advance.15 | |
British Medical Association (BMA) | Position: neutral |
A neutral position entails a campaign for better palliative care, robust safeguards for patients, training for health professionals, and clear conscientious objection clauses.2 | |
Royal College of General Practitioners (RCGP) | Position: against With improvements in palliative care, good clinical care can be provided within existing legislation and patients can die with dignity.12 |
British Association of Palliative Medicine (APM) | Position: against Palliative care strives to enhance patient dignity and choice towards the end of life. We need to improve access and provision of good palliative care rather than change the law.13 |
British Geriatrics' Society (BGS) | Position: against |
Rather than defining the conditions under which physicians may become killers, our efforts should focus on improving all aspects of palliative care such that the debate becomes irrelevant.14 |
Arguments supporting assisted dying
Assisted dying and palliative care
Medical professionals supporting assisted dying suggest that even with the best palliative care, there will still be those terminally ill patients who make a rational request for euthanasia.15,16 Modern palliative care may greatly reduce terminal suffering but may not always provide total relief of distressing symptoms and it is these patients that requests for assisted death are more prevalent.17,18 In Oregon, 80%–89% of patients who have died by assisted suicide had received hospice care.1,3
There are concerns that legalisation of assisted dying would detract from the growing need for expanding palliative care services. However, the bill may have the opposite effect as all patients must have palliative care involvement before assisted dying taking place: similar requirements in the law in other countries (USA and Netherlands) where assisted dying is legal have lead to an improvement and greater development of palliative care services.5,15,19
In the state of Oregon, where the 1997 Death with Dignity Act legalised assisted dying, only 60% of people who get a “lethal” prescription actually use it.15 It is suggested that the knowledge that assisted dying is available may itself aid wellbeing and reassurance (of the facility to control death).15,19
Public opinion
Medical professionals supporting assisted dying often relate to the wider public opinion on this issue that seems to favour assisted dying.15
Safeguards of the proposed legislation
In response to the concerns of those opposing the bill, advocates for the bill highlight the mechanisms and safeguards that it would contain to protect patients who lack the capacity to understand the significance of their decisions (for example, the need for involvement of two physicians and the involvement of a psychiatrist/psychologist where there is a concern regarding a patient's capacity).15
Concerns that assisted dying could be “imposed” upon vulnerable people has not been found in Oregon: people who have chosen assisted dying are generally younger, with above average educational attainment, higher socioeconomic class, and are not motivated by poor social support.2,3,20 Equally the 14 day minimum period between the patients' decision and the act of assisted dying allows for changes in the patient's decision.
Ethical considerations
A comprehensive discussion of the ethical arguments for (and against) assisted dying is beyond the scope of this article. However, there are some key arguments that should be mentioned. Central to the argument supporting assisted dying is the ethical principle of respecting patient autonomy: that respect for a patient's wishes at the end of their life is paramount.15
Finally, a further concern of the medical profession has been the impact on the doctor‐patient relationship (and on wider society) that assisted dying would have, there does not seem to be any evidence of an adverse effect in this regard in countries where assisted dying is already legal.15,17,21 In addition, a recent survey of adults in the USA found that only one fifth would trust their doctor less if physician assisted death was legalised.22
Arguments against assisted dying
Assisted dying and palliative care
In contrast, it is argued that better terminal care and palliative care service development are what is needed rather than assisted dying: if patients have access to good quality palliative care at the end of life then assisted dying becomes unnecessary. Indeed, the Human Rights Act 1998 says that each person's life shall be protected by law and that society has a duty to prevent or alleviate the situation that they find intolerable.23 One Dutch doctor has been quoted as saying “we don't need palliative medicine, we practice euthanasia”.23
Logistical concerns regarding the proposed legislation
There are a number of concerns about logistical aspects of the proposed legislation such as: accurately estimating prognosis (particularly in non‐malignant diseases), allowing the patient adequate time to change their mind, the “independence” of the second physician (if they are selected by the first physician they will probably share the same opinion), and excluding depression in those requesting death (distinguishing depression from a natural reaction to terminal illness is often difficult5).14,15,23
An additional practical concern is how the system will be regulated. In the Netherlands for example, there is evidence that euthanasia and assisted suicide are underreported by physicians despite the legal requirement to do so1,4,15 and non‐reporting seems to be associated with a lack of consultation with a second doctor.24 A survey of medical practitioners in the UK has found that voluntary euthanasia and ending life without the explicit request of the patient does already occur, albeit very rarely.6
There is also little information about frequency of complications or unsuccessful assisted suicide and should either occur there is the potential to diminish the quality of end of life care, not improve it.25,26
Protection of vulnerable people and the “slippery slope”
Perhaps the greatest concern is the protection of vulnerable people (for example, the elderly, disabled, and mentally incompetent),14,23,24 and the potential for such legislation to reinforce in society the attitude that “suffering should not be a part of life, that interdependency is a burden, that the lives of disabled people are not worth living”.23
While it is true that white, educated, richer, and younger patients are more likely to engage in physician assisted suicide, it is the most vulnerable members of the population (for example, older people, minorities and those with physical and mental disability) that feel this sort of legislation would compromise their trust in the medical profession.22 These concerns build to the “slippery slope” argument whereby voluntary requests for assisted death may evolve into involuntary euthanasia of vulnerable people.17
Physicians with conscientious objection
There would undoubtedly be physicians who conscientiously object to assisted suicide should it be legalised. While the original draft of the bill did not put a physician under obligation to assist death, it did require those objecting to refer the patient to another physician “without delay”. This was met by significant objection from those opposing the bill (an obligation to refer the patient to a physician who is prepared to assist their death being complicity in killing)8 and the current version has removed this obligation.10
Ethical considerations
Central to the argument for assisted dying is respect for patients' autonomy, but how far does patient autonomy go in modern society—if assisted dying is legalised could a non‐terminal patient autonomously request assisted death?15 Equally, the argument of patient autonomy has to be balanced against a respect for human dignity and the reverence for life.1
A further important concern of those opposing the legislation is the potential impact on the doctor‐patient relationship and the relationship between the medical profession and British society in general 14,17: particularly given the British media's attention and criticism in recent years.15
Conclusion
An entitlement to a “good death” has been given importance in most cultures and principles of a good death have been defined.27,28 However, where a person perceives physician assisted death to be a component of their good death this must be balanced against wider implications for society as a whole.
Holistic palliative care addresses bio‐psycho‐social and spiritual issues at the end of life. However, some would argue that relief of all suffering at the end of life is not always possible thereby defining a role for physician assisted death.
Physician assisted death is controversial on the balance of a variety of arguments: legal, medical, ethical, and religious. Both proponents and opposers of assisted death are able to use fundamental bioethical principles to support their argument (Beauchamp and Childress's four principles of biomedical ethics is one approach to summarising these arguments (table 3)).
Table 3 Assisted death: ethical arguments1,9,14,15,16,19.
Ethical principle | Argument supporting assisted dying | Argument against assisted dying |
---|---|---|
Respect for autonomy (that is, respect for individual choice) | Respecting patient free choice in decision making. A professional responsibility to respect patients' wishes. | The sanctity of life overrides individual autonomy |
Beneficence (that is, doing good) | Doing good by ultimate relief of suffering and permitting the patient control in decision making at the end of life (compassion by the medical profession) | Assisted death constitutes abandonment by the medical profession |
Non‐maleficence (that is, doing no harm) | Refusal/inability to relieve suffering and address patients requests is harmful to the doctor patient relationship | Assisted dying is harmful to the doctor‐patient relationship and the integrity of the medical profession in society |
Justice (that is, societal implications) | Regulatory safeguards ensure that vulnerable members of society are not harmed by assisted dying | Vulnerable groups in society may be compelled to request assisted death |
The medical profession and wider society as a whole remains divided as to whether physician assisted death should be legalised in the United Kingdom.
Key points
Legislation is currently under proposal in the UK to legalise physician assisted dying.
The debate regarding physician assisted death is complex involving many legal, ethical, medical, sociocultural, personal, and religious issues.
Both proponents and opposers of assisted death are able to use fundamental bioethical principles to support their argument: autonomy, beneficence, non‐maleficence, and justice
The medical profession and wider society as a whole remains divided as to whether physician assisted death should be legalised in the UK
Addendum
After this editorial went to press the British Medical Association also announced that it was changing its position from one of “neutrality” to “against” the proposed legislation (after a vote of members at its annual conference). The BMA opposes PAS and euthanasia “as alien to the moral focus of medicine”. It argues that legalisation would change the doctor‐patient relationship and put pressure on sick people.
Footnotes
Conflicts of interest: none.
References
- 1.Ersek M. The continuing challenge of assisted death. Journal of Hospice and Palliative Nursing 2004646–59. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Sommerville A. Changes in BMA policy on assisted dying. BMJ 2005331686–688. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Braithwaite M A. Taking the final step: changing the law on euthanasia and physician assisted suicide. BMJ 2005331681–683.16179704 [Google Scholar]
- 4.George R J D, Finlay I, Jeffrey D. Legalised euthanasia will violate the rights of vulnerable patients. BMJ 2005331681–682. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Watson M, Lucas C, Hoy A.et alOxford handbook of palliative care. Oxford: Oxford University Medical Press, 2005
- 6.Seale C. National survey of end‐of‐life decisions made by UK medical practitioners. Palliat Med 2006203–10. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Quill T E, Dresser R, Brock D W. The rule of double effect—a critique of its role in end‐of‐life decision making. NEJM 19973371768–1771. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Saunders J. Assisted dying: considerations in the continuing debate. Clin Med 20055543–547. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Tannsjo T. Moral dimensions. BMJ 2005331689–690. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.House of Lords Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill. House of Lords, 2005. http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld200506/ldbills/036/2006036.pdf (accessed 15 Feb 2006)
- 11.House of Lords Select Committee on Assisted Dying for the Terminally ill Bill Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill—First Report. http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld200405/ldselect/ldasdy/86/8602 (accessed 8 Apr 2006)
- 12.Royal College of General Practitioners RCGP statement on assisted dying. London: Royal College of General Practitioners, 2005
- 13.Association for Palliative Medicine Draft response of the Ethics Committee of the Association for Palliative Medicine of Great Britain and Ireland to the Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill 2005. London: Association for Palliative Medicine, 2006
- 14.British Geriatrics Society Assisted dying for the terminally ill bill—BGS response to the House of Lords. London: British Geriatrics Society, 2004
- 15.Tallis R, Saunders J. The Assisted Dying for the Terminally Ill Bill, 2004. Clin Med 20044534–540. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15a.Royal College of Physicians College Statements—Assisted Dying for the Terminal Ill Bill: a consultation. RCP May 2006. http://www.rcplondon.ac.uk/college/statements/statements_assisted_dying_02.htm (accessed 20 Jun 2006)
- 16.British Medical Association Assisted dying. London: British Medical Association, 2005
- 17.Hoffenberg R. Assisted dying. Clin Med 2006672–74. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Georges J J, Onwuteaka‐Philipsen B D, van der Wal G.et al Differences between terminally ill cancer patients who died after euthanasia had been performed and terminally ill cancer patients who did not request euthanasia. Palliat Med 200519578–586. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Reagan P, Hurst R, Cook L.et al Physician‐assisted death: dying with dignity? Lancet Neurology 20042637–643. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Ganzini L, Nelson H D, Schimdt T A.et al Physicians experiences with the Oregon Death and Dignity Act. NEJM 2000342557–563. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Van der Heide A, Deliene L, Faisst K.et al End‐of‐life decision‐making in six European countries: descriptive study. Lancet 2003362345–350. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Hall M, Trachtenberg F, Dugan E. The impact on patient trust of legalising physician aid in dying. J Med Ethics 200531693–697. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Her Majesty's Stationery office Schedule 1, Article 2.1. Human Rights Act, 1998. http://ww.hmso.gov.uk/acts/acts1998/80042‐d.htm#sch1 (accessed 15 Feb 2006)
- 24.Onwuteaka‐Philipsen B D, van der Heide A, Muller M T.et al Dutch experience of monitoring euthanasia. BMJ 2005331691–693. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Nuland S B. Physician‐assisted suicide and euthanasia in practice. NEJM 2000342583–584. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Horton R. Euthanasia and assisted suicide: what does the Dutch vote mean? Lancet 20013571221–1222. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Smith R. A good death. BMJ 2000320129–130. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Clark C. Patient centred death. BMJ 2003327174–175. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]