Skip to main content
Cognitive Neurodynamics logoLink to Cognitive Neurodynamics
. 2011 Sep 27;6(1):33–42. doi: 10.1007/s11571-011-9175-8

More discussions for granger causality and new causality measures

Sanqing Hu 1,, Yu Cao 2, Jianhai Zhang 1, Wanzeng Kong 1, Kun Yang 1, Yanbin Zhang 1, Xun Li 1
PMCID: PMC3253161  PMID: 23372618

Abstract

Granger causality (GC) has been widely applied in economics and neuroscience to reveal causality influence of time series. In our previous paper (Hu et al., in IEEE Trans on Neural Netw, 22(6), pp. 829–844, 2011), we proposed new causalities in time and frequency domains and particularly focused on new causality in frequency domain by pointing out the shortcomings/limitations of GC or Granger-alike causality metrics and the advantages of new causality. In this paper we continue our previous discussions and focus on new causality and GC or Granger-alike causality metrics in time domain. Although one strong motivation was introduced in our previous paper (Hu et al., in IEEE Trans on Neural Netw, 22(6), pp. 829–844, 2011) we here present additional motivation for the proposed new causality metric and restate the previous motivation for completeness. We point out one property of conditional GC in time domain and the shortcomings/limitations of conditional GC which cannot reveal the real strength of the directional causality among three time series. We also show the shortcomings/limitations of directed causality (DC) or normalize DC for multivariate time series and demonstrate it cannot reveal real causality at all. By calculating GC and new causality values for an example we demonstrate the influence of one of the time series on the other is linearly increased as the coupling strength is linearly increased. This fact further supports reasonability of new causality metric. We point out that larger instantaneous correlation does not necessarily mean larger true causality (e.g., GC and new causality), or vice versa. Finally we conduct analysis of statistical test for significance and asymptotic distribution property of new causality metric by illustrative examples.

Keywords: Granger causality, New causality, Linear regression model, Prediction

Introduction

Given a set of time series, the topic of how to define causality influence among them has kept philosophers busy for over two thousand years and has yet to be completely resolved. In the literature one of the most popular definitions for causality is Granger causality (GC). Due to its simplicity and easy implementation, GC has been widely used in economics and recently in neuroscience. The basic idea of GC was originally conceived (Wiener 1956) and later formalized by Granger in the form of linear regression model (Granger 1969; Geweke 1982). It can be simply stated as follows: if the variance Inline graphic of the prediction error for the first time series at the present time is not less than the variance Inline graphic of the prediction error by including past measurements from the second time series in the linear regression model, then the second time series can be said to have a causal (driving) influence on the first time series. Reversing the roles of the two time series one repeats the process to address the question of driving in the opposite direction. GC value of Inline graphic is defined to describe the strength of the causality which the second time series has on the first one (Freiwald et al. 1999; Hesse et al. 2003; Ding et al. 2006; Oya et al. 2007; Bressler and Anil 2010). From GC value, it is clear that (i) Inline graphic when there is no causal influence from the second time series to the first one and Inline graphic when there is. This GC definition was extended to frequency domain to show causal influence from one time series on the other one in different frequencies (Geweke 1982; Ding et al. 2006). Several GC or Granger-alike causality metrics in frequency domain have been developed such as spectral GC (Geweke 1982; Ding et al. 2006), PDC (Baccal and Sameshima 2001), RPC (Yamashita et al. 2005), and DTF (Kaminski et al. 2001). To show whether the influence is a direct component or mediated by the third time series, conditional GC is defined (Geweke 1984; Freiwald et al. 1999; Hesse et al. 2003; Ding et al. 2006; Oya et al. 2007; Bressler and Anil 2010). In recent years there has been significant interest to discuss causal interactions between brain areas which are highly complex neural networks in both time and frequency domains (Freiwald et al. 1999; Hesse et al. 2003; Roebroeck et al. 2005; Oya et al. 2007; Wang et al. 2007, 2008; Atmanspacher and Rotter 2008; Gow et al. 2008, 2009; Rajagovindan and Ding 2008; Seth 2008; Cadotte et al. 2009; Zhang et al. 2010).

Although there are wide applications of GC and Granger-alike causality metrics in both time and frequency domains, some shortcomings/limitations of these metrics were pointed out in our recent paper (Hu et al. 2011). To overcome these shortcomings/limitations, we proposed new causality metrics in time and frequency domains. In particular, we emphasized that GC or Granger-alike causality metrics in frequency domain cannot reveal real strength of causality at all and new causality metric in frequency domain has advantages over spectral GC or Granger-alike causality metrics.

In this paper we will focus on time domain and show inherent shortcomings of conditional GC and DC or normalized DC. We will demonstrate that the proposed new causality metric better reveal directed real causality from one time series on the other one than conditional GC and DC or normalized DC. Thus, we must be caution in drawing any conclusion based on GC, conditional GC and DC or normalized DC by noting the shortcomings/limitations of GC (Hu et al. 2011). We will show the influence of one of the time series on the other is linearly increased as the coupling strength is linearly increased by computing GC and new causality values via an example. We will also discuss statistical test for significance and asymptotic distribution property of new causality metric.

Granger causality in time domain

In this section we introduce the well-known Granger causality and conditional Granger causality.

Given two stochastic process X1(t) and X2(t) which are assumed to be jointly stationary. Their autoregressive representations are described as

graphic file with name M6.gif 1

and their joint representations are described as

graphic file with name M7.gif 2

where Inline graphic the noise terms are uncorrelated over time, Inline graphic and ηi have zero means and variances of Inline graphic and Inline graphic The covariance between η1 and η2 is defined by Inline graphic

Now consider the first equalities in Eqs. 1 and 2. According to the original formulations (Wiener 1956; Granger 1969), if Inline graphic is less than Inline graphic in some suitable statistical sense, then X2 is said to have a causal influence on X1. In this case, the first equality in Eq. 2 is more accurate than that in Eq. 1 to estimate X1. Otherwise, if Inline graphic then X2 is said to have no causal influence on X1. In this case, the two equalities are almost same. Such kind of causal influence called Granger causality (GC) (Ding et al. 2006; Geweke 1982), can be defined by

graphic file with name M16.gif 3

Obviously, Inline graphic when there is no causal influence from X2 to X1 and Inline graphic when there is. Similarly, the causal influence from X1 to X2 is defined by

graphic file with name M19.gif 4

To show whether the interaction between two time series is direct or is mediated by another recorded time series, conditional Granger causality (Ding et al. 2006; Geweke 1984), was defined by

graphic file with name M20.gif 5

where Inline graphic and Inline graphic are variances of two noise terms, Inline graphic and η3, of the following two joint autoregressive representations:

graphic file with name M24.gif 6

and X1,t = 

graphic file with name M25.gif 7

According to this definition, Inline graphic means that no further improvement in the prediction of X1 can be expected by including past measurements of X2. On the other hand, when there is still a direct component from X2 to X1, the past measurements of X1X2X3 together result in better prediction of X1, leading to Inline graphic and Inline graphic

For conditional GC, we point out one important property as follows.

Property 1 Consider the following model

graphic file with name M29.gif 8

where 0 < ai1,1ai3,1 < 0.7, i = 1, 2, 3 and for simplicity η1, η2, η3 are assumed to be independent white noise processes with zero mean and variances Inline graphic Figure 1 shows Inline graphic for Model (8) under different parameters ai1,1 and ai3,1. When we calculate conditional GC it should be pointed out that for each specific Model (8) we generate a data set of 200 realizations of 10,000 time points. For each realization, we estimate AR models (joint representations Model (6) and Model (7)) with the order of 8 by using the least-squares method and calculate conditional GC where the order 8 fits well for all examples throughout the paper (see Fig. 1a and b from which one can see Inline graphic keeps steady when the order of the estimated models is >8). Then we obtain the average value across all realizations and get Inline graphic From Fig. 1 one can clearly see that Inline graphic has nothing to do with parameters ai1,1 and ai3,1i = 1, 2, 3 (of course, choices of parameters ai1,1 and ai3,1 are such that Model (8) does not diverge).

Fig. 1.

Fig. 1

aInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a21,1 = a31,1 = 0.4, a13,1 = a23,1 = a33,1 = 0.2 and a11,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. bInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a11,1 = a31,1 = 0.4, a13,1 = a23,1 = a33,1 = 0.2 and a21,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. cInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a11,1 = a21,1 = 0.4, a13,1 = a23,1 = a33,1 = 0.2 and a31,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. dInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a11,1 = a21,1 = a31,1 = 0.4, a23,1 = a33,1 = 0.2 and a13,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. eInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a11,1 = a21,1 = a31,1 = 0.4, a13,1 = a33,1 = 0.2 and a23,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. fInline graphic as a function of the order of the estimated models for Model (8) when a11,1 = a21,1 = a31,1 = 0.4, a13,1 = a23,1 = 0.2 and a33,1 changes from 0.1 to 0.7. From af one can see that a) Inline graphic keeps steady and converges to 0.61 when the order p > 4. bInline graphic has nothing to do with parameters ai1,1 and ai3,1

By the conditional GC definition (5), we know that conditional GC Inline graphic explicitly measures the degree to which X2 predicts X1 over and above the degree to which X1 already predicts itself and X3 predicts X1, the influence of X1 on itself (i.e. the coefficients ai1,1) and X3 on X1 (i.e. the coefficients ai3,1) are factored out and quite correctly makes no difference to the result. So, according to the conditional GC definition (5) the above property is true.

In general GC is useful to show whether or not theoretically there is directional interaction between two neurons or among three neurons. When there exists causal influence, a question is arising: does GC value reveals the real strength of causality? to answer this question, let’s consider the following simple model

graphic file with name M44.gif 9

where η1 and η2 are two independent white noise processes with zero mean and a12,1a21,1 ≠ 0. From Model (9) one can get

graphic file with name M45.gif 10

So, GC value Inline graphic

graphic file with name M47.gif 11

Inline graphic or equivalently,

graphic file with name M49.gif 12

which is only related to the last two noise terms and has nothing to do with the first term. It is noted that all of three terms make contributions to current X1,t, and a12,1a21,1X1,t−2 must have causal influence on X1,t and must be considered to illustrate real causality. Especially, when Inline graphic we have X1,t = a12,1a21,1X1,t−2 + η1,t and Inline graphic Since a21,1X1,t−2 comes from X2,t−1 we can surely know that X2 has real nonzero causality on X1 due to a12,1a21,1 ≠ 0. Thus, GC value may not reveal real causality at all. As such, the definition has its inherent shortcomings and/or limitations to illustrate the real strength of causality. Please refer to Remark 1 (Hu et al. 2011) for the detailed discussions.

New causality

Due to the shortcomings and/or limitations of GC, we next give a new definition for causality anaylsis of multivariate time series. Let’s consider the following general model:

graphic file with name M52.gif 13

where Inline graphic are n time series, Inline graphic has zero mean and variance of Inline graphic and Inline graphic Based on Eq. 13, Fig. 2 clearly shows contributions to Xk,t, which includes Inline graphic and the noise term ηk,t where the influence from Inline graphic is causality from Xk’s own past values. Each contribution plays an important role in determining Xk,t. If Inline graphic occupies larger portion among all those contributions, then Xi has stronger causality on Xk, or vice versa. Thus, a good definition for causality from Xi to Xk in time domain should be able to describe what proportion Xi occupies among all these contributions. This is a general guideline for proposing any causality method (i.e., all contributions must be considered). For Eq. 10, let’s define

graphic file with name M60.gif 14

which is summation of two noise terms and each noise term makes contributions to Inline graphic To describe what proportion η2 occupies in Inline graphic we define

graphic file with name M63.gif 15

which is the same as GC defined in Eq. 12. Therefore, here in nature GC is actually defined based on the noise model (14) and follows the above guideline. Motivated by this idea, we can naturally extend the noise model (14) to the kth equation of Model (13) and define a new direct causality from Xi to Xk as follows:

graphic file with name M64.gif 16

When N is large enough,

graphic file with name M65.gif

Then, Eq. 16 can be approximated as

graphic file with name M66.gif 17

Throughout the paper, we always assume that N is large enough so that Inline graphic is always defined as Eq. 17.

Fig. 2.

Fig. 2

Contributions to Xk,t

New causality based on Eq. 10 can be written as Inline graphic

graphic file with name M69.gif 18

which describes what proportion X2 occupies among two contributions in X1 (see Eq. 10). Note that for (10) GC Inline graphic is proposed based on Model (14) and describes what proportion η2 occupies among two contributions in Inline graphic (see Eq. 15). Thus GC actually reveals causal influence from η2 to Inline graphic it does not reveal causal influence from X2 to X1 at all by noting that Inline graphic is only partial information of X1, i.e., the noise terms a12,1η2,t−1 + η1,t. One can see that new causality definition based on Eq. 10 is a natural extension of GC definition based on Eq. 14 as far as the concept of proportion is concerned (in this way, our new causality definition has a rather sound conceptual or theoretical basis). But, as said above, the equivalent GC describes what the proportion η2 occupies in Inline graphic of Eq. 14 and new causality describes what the proportion X2 occupies in X1 of Eq. 10. Thus, they are two totally different concepts, that is, the equivalent GC reveals causal influence from η2 to Inline graphic but new causality indeed reveals causal influence from X2 to X1. Obviously, one cannot use causal influence value from η2 to Inline graphic (involving partial information of X1, i.e., the noise terms a12,1η2,t−1 + η1,t) to express causality influence value from X2 to X1 (involving complete information, i.e.,the noise terms a12,1η2,t−1 + η1,t plus a12,1a21,1X1,t−2). Any causality definition (like traditional GC) only using partial information of X1 inevitably leads to misinterpretation result. In addition to some important points shown in Remark 2 (Hu et al. 2011), next we give some more comments for new causality in the following remark.

Remark 1 (1) Let the transfer function of Model (13) be H(f) = [Hij(f)]n × n. RPC (Yamashita et al. 2005) is used to reveal causality influence from Xj to Xi at frequency f and is defined as

graphic file with name M77.gif 19

where the power spectrum

graphic file with name M78.gif 20

Equation 20 indicates that the power spectrum of Xi,t at frequency f can be decomposed as to n terms Inline graphic each of which can be interpreted as the power contribution of the jth innovation ηj,t transferring to Xi,t via the transfer function Hij(f). RPC Inline graphic can be regarded as a ratio of the power contribution of the innovation ηj,t on the power spectrum of Xi,t to the power spectrum Inline graphic From this point of view, this ratio also provides a strong motivation (or theoretical basis) to define the proposed new causality metric Eq. 16 for multivariate time series. However, as pointed out in Remark 6 (Hu et al. 2011) RPC has inherent shortcomings/limitations and cannot reveal real causality influence at all.(2) Consider the following two models

graphic file with name M82.gif 21

and

graphic file with name M83.gif 22

where η1, η2 and η3 are three independent white noise processes with zero mean and variances Inline graphic and the initial conditions Inline graphic and Inline graphic From both of Models (21) and (22) it can be seen that there are no direct causality from X3 to X1, so, Inline graphic Moreover, based on Property 1, Inline graphic are same for both of Models (21) and (22). We can obtain Inline graphic for both of Models (21) and (22), Inline graphic for Model (21), and Inline graphic for Model (22). Figure 3 shows trajectories Inline graphic and η1 for one realization of Model (21) and Model (22). From Fig. 3a and c one can clearly see that amplitudes of −0.99X2 are much larger than that of η1 and the contribution from −0.99X2,t−1 occupies much larger portion compared to that from η1,t, as a result, the causal influence from X2 to X1 occupies a major portion compared to the influence from η1 and the real strength of causality from X2 to X1 should have higher value. This fact is real. Our causality value Inline graphic for Model (21) is consistent with this fact. Similarly, from Fig. 3b and c one can clearly see that amplitude of Inline graphic is much smaller than that of η1 and the contribution from Inline graphic occupies much smaller portion compared to that from η1,t, as a result, the causal influence from Inline graphic to Inline graphic occupies a rather small portion compared to the influence from η1 and the real strength of causality from Inline graphic to Inline graphic should have smaller value. This fact is also real. Our causality value Inline graphic for Model (22) is consistent with this fact. However, conditional GC always equals to 0.092 for both of Models (21) and Eq. 22 and does not reflect such kind of changes at all, and violates above two real facts. These results show that the conditional GC definition (5) does not reveal real strength of direct causality from X2 to X1 at all for Models (21) and (22), our new causality definition very reasonably reflects the real strength of the direct causality.(3) An alternate time-domain metric namely direct causality (DC) has been proposed earlier (Kaminski et al. 2001) which quantifies causality based on the AR coefficients

graphic file with name M106.gif

or the following normalized measure

graphic file with name M107.gif 23

Since the AR coefficients themselves represent the coupling strength, now a question is arising: would this normalized measure suffice to reveal the real causality of two time series? Unfortunately, the answer is no. Let’s take a look at the following model:

graphic file with name M108.gif 24

where η1, η2 and η3 are three independent white noise processes with zero mean and variances Inline graphic For Models (24) we can obtain Inline graphic and Inline graphic Figure 4 shows trajectories of X1,t, 0.9(− X2,t−1 + X2,t−2 − X2,t−3 + X2,t−4), 0.9X3,t, and η1,t for one realization of Model (24). From Fig. 4a–d one can clearly see that amplitudes of 0.9X3 are much larger than that of η1,t and 0.9(− X2,t−1 + X2,t−2 − X2,t−3 + X2,t−4), and the contribution from 0.9X3 occupies much larger portion compared to that from η1,t and 0.9(− X2,t−1 + X2,t−2 − X2,t−3 + X2,t−4). As a result, the causal influence from X2 to X1 occupies a small portion compared to the influence from 0.9X3 and the real strength of causality from X2 to X1 should have smaller value. This fact is real. Our causality value Inline graphic for Model (24) is consistent with this fact. However, Inline graphic for Model (24) violates the real fact. These results show that the direct causality definition (23) does not reveal real strength of direct causality from X2 to X1 at all for Model (24), our new causality definition reflects the real strength of the direct causality very reasonably.(4) It should be noted that the influence of one of the time series on the other is linearly increased as the coupling strength is linearly increased. Let’s consider the following bivariate AR process with 5 levels of coupling strength:

graphic file with name M114.gif 25

where η1 and η2 are two independent white noise processes with zero mean and variances Inline graphic From Eq. 25 one can see that the coupling strength of X2 on X1 is linearly increased as the parameter c increases. The true causality of X2 on X1 should increase as the parameter c increases. The estimated causality measures (new causality and GC) against the parameter c are shown in Fig. 5a and b, respectively, from which one can clearly see that both of two metrics indicate the increasing true causality as the true coupling strength (i.e., the parameter c) increases.(5) Figure 5c shows the increasing instantaneous correlation (i.e., zero-lag influence) of two time series as the parameter c increases. Combining Fig. 5a and b with c we can conclude that the increasing instantaneous correlation leads to the reasonable increasing new causality and GC. However, in general this conclusion may not be true. It is well known that in general there may be no relationship between true causality and correlation. In other words, larger correlation does not necessarily mean larger true causality, or vice versa. Therefore, it is meaningless to discuss whether new causality or GC will be affected by correlation.

Fig. 3.

Fig. 3

For one realization of Model (21) and Model (22) where Inline graphic and Inline graphic trajectories for Inline graphic and η1,t are plotted: a −0.99X2,t’s trajectory for Model (21). bInline graphic’s trajectory for Model (22). c η1,t’s or Inline graphic’s trajectory

Fig. 4.

Fig. 4

For one realization of Model (24), trajectories for X1,t, 0.9(− X2,t−1 + X2,t−2 − X2,t−3 + X2,t−4), 0.9X3,t, and η1,t are plotted: a Trajectory for X1,t. b Trajectory for 0.9(− X2,t−1 + X2,t−2 − X2,t−3 + X2,t−4). c Trajectory for 0.9X3,t. d Trajectory for η1,t

Fig. 5.

Fig. 5

Causality (or correlation) vs the parameter c for Model (25). a New causality of X2 on X1 vs the coupling strength (i.e., the parameter c). b GC of X2 on X1 vs the coupling strength (i.e., the parameter c). c Correlation of X2 and X1 vs. the coupling strength (i.e., the parameter c)

Statistical test for significance

Since new causality metric has a highly nonlinear relation to the time series data, it makes tests of significance difficult to perform. In this section, we use the same technology (Kaminski et al. 2001) to deal with this problem; that is, we first create a surrogate data set (Theiler et al. 1992) for each channel, we then fit a model to this surrogate data set and calculate new causality metric. Repeating this process many time, we can obtain an empirical distribution for the metric. Based on this distribution we can then evaluate the significance of the causal metric derived from the actual data. We use the following model to illustrate the process.

graphic file with name M116.gif 26

where η1 and η2 are two independent white noise processes with standard normal distribution. For a simulated data of a realization of Model (26), we produce surrogate data (i.e., perform random and independent shuffling of X1 and X2). We then estimate a joint regression model (2) with m = 6 to fit the shuffled data and calculate new causality value. Carrying out the procedure for 1,000 such independently shuffled data sets we can construct an empirical distribution for the new causality values. Since the shuffling procedure destroys all the temporal structure in the data, this empirical distribution gives the variability for the new causality values when the null hypothesis of no causal influence is true.

Figure 6 shows Histogram of new causality values based on the original simulated data and 1000 surrogate data. One can see that the new causality value (=0.275) based on the original simulated data is statistically significant (P < 0.001).

Fig. 6.

Fig. 6

Histogram of new causality values resulting from 1,000 surrogate data sets

Asymptotic distribution property

It is well known that the asymptotic distribution of GC metric under the null hypothesis of zero causality is known (it is a χ 2-distribution) (Geweke 1982). Now a question is arising: what is asymptotic distribution for new causality metric under the null hypothesis of zero causality? For new causality metric can we derive the similar asymptotic distribution property as GC metric? In general it is difficult to discuss this issue because of complexity of new causality definition. But in the following example we find that new causality metric has χ2(1)-distribution as GC metric.

graphic file with name M117.gif 27

where η1 and η2 are two independent white noise processes with standard normal distribution, Inline graphic (i.e., N = 10,000). For each realization of Model (27) we set m = 1 to estimate the autoregression Model (1) and the joint regression Model (2), then based on the two estimated models we calculate new causalty Inline graphic and GC Inline graphic This process is repeated by N = 10,000 times. Finally we plot large-sample distributions for Inline graphic and Inline graphic in Fig. 7a and b, respectively. One can see probability density functions for both new causality and GC follow χ2(1)-distribution. In general, as for whether or not Inline graphic follows a χ2-distribution under the null hypothesis of zero causality keeps unknown and is left for further study in near future.

Fig. 7.

Fig. 7

Probability distribution functions (PDF). a PDF for new causality metric. b PDF for GC metric

Conclusions

In this paper, we further make more discussions for GC or Granger-alike causality and new causality metrics by following our previous paper (Hu et al. 2011) and focus on time domain. In addition to the previous motivation for introducing new causality metric in time domain, we provide additional strong motivation (or theoretical basis) to the proposed metric for multivariate time series. After introducing one property for conditional GC, we point out the inherent shortcomings/limitations of conditional GC and demonstrate that it cannot reveal directed causal influence from one time series to the other one among three time series. We also point out the shortcomings/limitations of Granger-alike causality, i.e., DC or normalized DC metric and show that it cannot disclose directed causality influence at all for multivariate time series. Furthermore, all these shortcomings/limitations demonstrate reasonability and advantages of new causality metric. Therefore, researchers must be caution in drawing any conclusion based on DC (or normalized DC) value and conditional GC value. By calculating GC and new causality values for an example we show the influence of one of the time series on the other is linearly increased as the coupling strength is linearly increased. Finally for new causality metric in time domain we analyze statistical test for significance and show significance level for a simulated data, meanwhile we conduct analysis for asymptotic distribution property by an examples in which both GC and new causality metrics follow χ2(1)-distribution. However, in general, as for whether or not new causality metric follows a χ2-distribution under the null hypothesis of zero causality keeps unknown and is left for further study in near future. Thus our proposed new causality metrics in time and frequency domains may have wide applications in economics and neuroscience.

Acknowledgments

This work was supported in part by the National Natural Science Foundation of China under Grant 61070127, and the International Cooperation Project of Zhejiang Province, China, under Grant 2009C14013, Qianjiang Project of Zhejiang Province, China, under Grant 2011R10063, U.S. National Science Foundation (NSF) under Grant 0821820, and Tennessee Higher Education Commission, the State of Tennessee, USA.

Contributor Information

Sanqing Hu, Email: sqhu2000@yahoo.com.

Yu Cao, Email: yu-cao@utc.edu.

References

  1. Atmanspacher H, Rotter S. Interpreting neurodynamics: concepts and facts. Cogn Neurodyn. 2008;2:297–318. doi: 10.1007/s11571-008-9067-8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  2. Baccal LA, Sameshima K. Partial directed coherence: a new concept in neural structure determination. Biol Cybern. 2001;84(6):463–474. doi: 10.1007/PL00007990. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Bressler SL, Anil KS (2010) Wiener-Granger causality: a well established methodology. NeuroImage (in press) [DOI] [PubMed]
  4. Cadotte AJ, Mareci TH, DeMarse TB, et al. Temporal lobe epilepsy: anatomical and effective connectivity. IEEE Trans Neural Syst Rehabil Eng. 2009;17(3):214–223. doi: 10.1109/TNSRE.2008.2006220. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Ding M, Chen Y, Bressler SL. Granger causality: basic theory and applications to neuroscience. In: Schelter B, Winterhalder M, Timmer J, editors. Handbook of time series analysis. Weinheim: Wiley; 2006. pp. 437–460. [Google Scholar]
  6. Freiwald WA, Valdes P, Bosch J, et al. Testing non-linearity and directedness of interactions between neural groups in the macaque inferotemporal cortex. J Neurosci Methods. 1999;94(1):105–119. doi: 10.1016/S0165-0270(99)00129-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Geweke J. Measurement of linear-dependence and feedback between multiple time series. J Am Stat Assoc. 1982;77(378):304–313. doi: 10.2307/2287238. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  8. Geweke J. Measures of conditional linear dependence and feedback between time series. J Am Stat Assoc. 1984;79(388):907–915. doi: 10.2307/2288723. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  9. Granger CWJ. Investigating causal relations by econometric models and cross-spectral methods. Econometrica. 1969;37(4):424–438. doi: 10.2307/1912791. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  10. Gow DW, Segawa JA, Alfhors S, et al. Lexical influences on speech perception: a Granger causality analysis of MEG and EEG source estimates. Neuroimage. 2008;43(3):614–623. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.07.027. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Gow DW, Keller CJ, Eskandar E, et al. Parallel versus serial processing dependencies in the perisylvian speech network: a Granger analysis of intracranial EEG data. Brain Lang. 2009;110(1):43–48. doi: 10.1016/j.bandl.2009.02.004. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  12. Hesse W, Oller M, Arnold M, et al. The use of time-variant EEG Granger causality for inspecting directed interdependencies of neural assemblies. J Neurosci Methods. 2003;124(1):27–44. doi: 10.1016/S0165-0270(02)00366-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Hu S, Dai G, Worrell GA, et al. Causality analysis of neural connectivity: critical examination of existing methods and advances of new methods. IEEE Trans on Neural Netw. 2011;22(6):829–844. doi: 10.1109/TNN.2011.2123917. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  14. Kaminski M, Ding M, Truccolo-Filho W, et al. Evaluating causal relations in neural systems: Granger causality, directed transfer function and statistical assessment of significance. Biol Cybern. 2001;85:145–157. doi: 10.1007/s004220000235. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Oya H, Poon PWF, Brugge JF, et al. Functional connections between auditory cortical fields in humans revealed by Granger causality analysis of intra-cranial evoked potentials to sounds: comparison of two methods. Biosystems. 2007;89:198–207. doi: 10.1016/j.biosystems.2006.05.018. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  16. Rajagovindan R, Ding M. Decomposing neural synchrony: toward an explanation for near-zero phase-lag in cortical oscillatory networks. Plos one. 2008;3(11):e3649. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0003649. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Roebroeck A, Formisano E, Goebel R. Mapping directed influence over the brain using Granger causality and fMRI. Neuroimage. 2005;25(1):230–242. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.11.017. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Seth AK. Causal networks in simulated neural systems. Cogn Neurodyn. 2008;2:49–64. doi: 10.1007/s11571-007-9031-z. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Wiener N. The theory of prediction. In: Beckenbach EF, editor. Modern mathematics for engineers, Chap. 8. New York: McGraw-Hill; 1956. [Google Scholar]
  20. Wang X, Chen Y, Ding M. Estimating Granger causality after stimulus onset: a cautionary note. Neuroimage. 2008;41(3):767–776. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2008.03.025. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  21. Wang X, Chen Y, Bressler SL, et al. Granger causality between multiple interdependent neurobiological time series: blockwise versus pairwise methods. Int J Neural Syst. 2007;17(2):71–78. doi: 10.1142/S0129065707000944. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Zhang L, Zhong G, Wu Y, et al. Using granger-geweke causality model to evaluate the effective connectivity of primary motor cortex, supplementary motor area and cerebellum. J Biomed Sci Eng. 2010;3:848–860. doi: 10.4236/jbise.2010.39115. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  23. Yamashita O, Sadato N, Okada T, et al. Evaluating frequency-wise directed connectivity of BOLD signals applying relative power contribution with the linear multivariate time-series models. Neuroimage. 2005;25(2):478–490. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2004.11.042. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Cognitive Neurodynamics are provided here courtesy of Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

RESOURCES