Arguments Against |
Goal of research |
to generate generalizable knowledge, not provide individual care; there is no duty to return individual results27,29
|
Cost |
deviating from the goal of research to return individual results drains already limited research resources |
Minimize therapeutic misconception |
by returning clinically relevant findings researchers may promote the misconception that the research is being conducted for the therapeutic benefit of the participant30,31
|
Respect for Autonomy |
denying RoR is respectful of participants’ autonomy if researchers make it clear during the informed consent process that there will not be RoR and participants agree to these terms32
|
Difficult to obtain meaningful informed consent |
Genome-wide testing could generate a plethora of clinically relevant findings and it would be impractical to describe potential findings to obtain meaningful informed consent for RoR33
|
Difficult to determine the pathogenicity of variants |
it may be difficult for researchers to identify clinically relevant findings, particularly when they are not clinicians34 or if annotations are ambiguous |
Non-maleficence |
given the complexity of genomic information, participants may overestimate their risk, suffer needless emotional distress, and seek unnecessary treatments; this may be exacerbated in people with severe psychiatric disorders |
Lack of genetics training among clinicians |
Most internists35 and psychiatrists36–38 report inadequate understanding of genetics and the interpretation and management of genomic tests; this could lead to unnecessary tests and procedures that will increase health care costs, and could potentially harm patients |
Unknown impact of RoR on participants |
there is lack of research about the impact of RoR on individuals with a history of, currently suffering from, or at risk of developing a psychiatric disorder; it is conceivable that this could exacerbate suicidality or become part of a delusional scheme |
Arguments in Favor |
Beneficence |
genomics research can generate clinically relevant findings that, if known, could improve health outcomes;11,39,40 denying participants access to these findings is inconsistent with beneficence, a basic principle of ethical research advocated by the Belmont Report and others.39,41–44
|
Respect for Persons |
implies not using participants as just means to an end, thus, using participants to generate data but not offer certain clinically relevant findings generated in the course of research may be considered unethical.28, 45
|
Respect for Autonomy |
if researchers are in possession of clinically relevant findings—and it is feasible to make these available to participants—researchers should not decide for participants whether they should know this information, but allow participants or their legally authorized representative to make this determination39,45,46
|
Justice |
although this may change in the future, given the cost of genetic testing and usual lack of insurance coverage for these tests, participants may not be able to access this genomic information through other means |
Reciprocity |
should not withhold clinically relevant findings from participants who contributed and made study possible30,47–49
|
Participants want findings |
a large majority of individuals would like to know their genomic research results50–52
|
Many researchers and other stakeholders support return of certain clinically relevant findings |
in 2013, 95% of 234 genomic researchers surveyed in the US believed that highly penetrant and medically actionable findings should be offered;34,53 funding agencies, professional groups, and other stakeholders support the return of certain findings54–60
|