Abstract
How do migration and acculturation (i.e. psychological or behavioral change resulting from migration) affect within- and between-group cultural variation? Here I address this question by drawing analogies between genetic and cultural evolution. Population genetic models show that migration rapidly breaks down between-group genetic structure. In cultural evolution, however, migrants or their descendants can acculturate to local behaviors via social learning processes such as conformity, potentially preventing migration from eliminating between-group cultural variation. An analysis of the empirical literature on migration suggests that acculturation is common, with second and subsequent migrant generations shifting, sometimes substantially, towards the cultural values of the adopted society. Yet there is little understanding of the individual-level dynamics that underlie these population-level shifts. To explore this formally, I present models quantifying the effect of migration and acculturation on between-group cultural variation, for both neutral and costly cooperative traits. In the models, between-group cultural variation, measured using F statistics, is eliminated by migration and maintained by conformist acculturation. The extent of acculturation is determined by the strength of conformist bias and the number of demonstrators from whom individuals learn. Acculturation is countered by assortation, the tendency for individuals to preferentially interact with culturally-similar others. Unlike neutral traits, cooperative traits can additionally be maintained by payoff-biased social learning, but only in the presence of strong sanctioning mechanisms (e.g. institutions). Overall, the models show that surprisingly little conformist acculturation is required to maintain realistic amounts of between-group cultural diversity. While these models provide insight into the potential dynamics of acculturation and migration in cultural evolution, they also highlight the need for more empirical research into the individual-level learning biases that underlie migrant acculturation.
Introduction
Humans exhibit extensive between-group cultural variation [1–3] as documented by anthropologists [4], psychologists [5] and economists [6] in domains such as languages, customs, marriage practices, cooperative norms, religious beliefs and social organization. While such traits certainly vary within societies, they typically characterize, and sometimes even define, entire social groups. At the same time, migration has been a constant fixture of our species for millennia [7]. Homo sapiens migrated out of Africa in multiple waves from 100kya [8], and migration continued within and between global areas throughout prehistory [9,10]. In the modern era, improved transportation technologies such as steamships allowed mass migration to transform the USA in the early 20th century [11], while international migration has increased in volume (number of migrants) and scope (diversity of destinations) in the last century [12].
In a sense, these two phenomena—extensive between-group cultural variation and frequent migration—are contradictory. It is well known in population genetics that even small amounts of migration can rapidly break down between-group genetic structure [13,14]. If migration acts on cultural variation in the same way as it acts on genetic variation, we would expect that our species’ frequent migration would rapidly destroy between-group cultural variation, resulting in a homogenous mass world culture. At the least, we would expect similar levels of between-group cultural variation as between-group genetic evolution, yet the former is more than an order of magnitude greater than the latter [3].
However, cultural evolution does not act in the same way as genetic evolution. Migrants are stuck with their genes, but they may change their cultural traits, and often do so within one or two generations. This process of acculturation, defined as psychological or behavioral change resulting from migration [15], could, in principle, maintain between-group cultural variation even in the face of frequent migration. Here I adapt population genetic models of migration to the cultural case to ask: (i) how strong does acculturation need to be, and what form should it take, in order to maintain different amounts of between-group cultural variation in the face of different levels of migration? (ii) are these levels of migration, acculturation and between-group cultural structure empirically plausible? I follow previous cultural evolution researchers [16,17] in adapting population genetic methods and concepts to analyze cultural change, given that genetic and cultural change are both systems of inherited variation [18]. While past models have examined the effect of migration on cultural diversity [16] and the effect of acculturation in specific communities [19] and on multiculturalism [20], no past research has explicitly linked migration and acculturation to the maintenance of between-group cultural variation using quantitative measures of the latter. And while migration is often studied in sociology [21], psychology [15] and cultural anthropology [22], much of this work focuses on the proximate level (e.g. the lived experiences of migrants) and does not formally link individual-level migration and acculturation processes to population-level cultural dynamics.
These questions have relevance beyond academia. Migration and acculturation have always been major factors in political and public discourse, and never more so than in today’s increasingly interconnected world. As noted above, economic migration is at record global levels [12]. The involuntary migration of refugees has also increased. The ‘European migrant crisis’ has seen unprecedented numbers of people crossing the Mediterranean from Syria and other conflict areas [23]. As migration increases, public opposition to immigration often also rises [24]. Much public opposition reflects beliefs that immigrants are incapable of acculturating, and that migration will consequently weaken or destroy existing cultural traditions in receiving countries. In the 2013 British Social Attitudes survey [25], 77% of respondents wanted immigration levels reduced, 45% said immigrants undermined Britain’s cultural life (versus 35% who said they enriched it), and half agreed that one cannot be “truly British” unless one has British ancestry (51% agree) and shares British customs and values (50% agree). Politicians often appeal to such fears surrounding supposedly non-acculturating immigrants. Marine Le Pen of the French Front national has said “Immigration is an organized replacement of our population. This threatens our very survival. We don’t have the means to integrate those who are already here.” [26]. Nigel Farage of the UK Independence Party has said “If we went to virtually every town up eastern England and spoke to people about how they felt their town or city had changed for the last 10 to 15 years, there is a deep level of discomfort. Because if you have immigration at these sort of levels, integration doesn’t happen” [27]. My aim here is not to take a stance on the normative and political issue of migration policy, only to scrutinize the logical and empirical claims inherent in such statements and policies, e.g. that immigrants can never acculturate (Le Pen), or that acculturation depends on the level of migration (Farage).
After reviewing the evidence for migrant acculturation, I then justify the use of conformist social learning as a candidate for an acculturation mechanism and explain how the present study differs from previous models of conformity and migration. Model 1 then explores how migration and conformist acculturation interact to maintain, reduce or eliminate between-group cultural variation in functionally-neutral cultural traits. Model 2 examines how migration and acculturation affect a non-neutral cooperative trait that is individually costly but group beneficial. Models presented are recursion-based simulations tracking the frequency of cultural traits over time, written in R [28] with code available at https://github.com/amesoudi/migrationmodels.
Evidence for migrant acculturation
There is a growing literature in economics, sociology and psychology that compares quantitative measures of behavioral or psychological traits across multiple generations of immigrants. Psychologists have tested migrants of non-Western heritage living in Western countries on measures that exhibit cross-cultural variation, such as collectivism, social attribution, self-enhancement and self-esteem [29–31]. Economists and political scientists have measured traits such as institutional trust via large-scale surveys in multiple generations of migrants [32–34]. This work aims to determine whether immigrants (or their descendants) retain the trait values of their country of birth or shift towards the trait values of their adopted country, in those cases where such values are different. If there is a shift, studies often determine its magnitude, how it varies with different combinations of adopted and birth countries, how it varies with age of migration (for first generation migrants), and how it persists over subsequent generations (second, third etc. generations). Using standard terminology, first generation migrants are defined as those born and raised in one country and who moved to another country after the age of 14, second generation migrants are children of first generation migrants, third generation are children of second generation, and so on.
S1 Table and S1 Fig present some example findings from the economics, sociology and psychology literatures, where mean values from multiple migrant generations are reported. It is necessarily selective, but broadly representative of other studies [19,33,34]. From S1 Table, and those other studies, we can make the following empirical generalizations which inform the models in the current study:
Complete one-generation assimilation is rare. It does not appear that first generation migrants typically acculturate/assimilate completely to their adopted country’s values. S1 Table shows several traits for which first generation migrants differ from non-migrants, often substantially, and in the direction predicted by the cross-cultural research mentioned above [2,6]. For example, one study [29] found that first generation British Bangladeshi migrants are more collectivistic and show more situational, and less dispositional, social attribution compared to White British non-migrants. This reflects findings in cross-cultural psychology that Western societies are less collectivistic, and show more dispositional and less situational attribution, than non-Western societies [35]. Another study [32] found that non-Western first-generation migrants to high trust countries such as Denmark, Norway and Sweden show much less trust, again in line with existing cross-cultural research. While there may be other traits not shown in S1 Table that do show complete within-generation assimilation, this seems rare. A wealth of literature shows that cultural history is important, and people are shaped by the values they acquire during childhood and early life [33,34].
Acculturation is common and occurs over multiple generations. While no trait in S1 Table shows complete, immediate, one-generation assimilation, most traits show some degree of gradual acculturation. First generation migrants often show a partial shift towards their adopted country’s values, and second and further generations show shifts that are as large or larger. In many cases this shift is quite substantial, with second generation migrants sometimes moving more than 50% of the way towards non-migrant values from their first-generation parents’ or heritage country’s values (see S1 Fig). For example, 2nd generation British Bangladeshis have shifted around 50% towards local non-migrant values of collectivism and social attribution from their 1st generation parents’ values [29]. In other cases, shifts are only evident after multiple generations. In a study of four generations of migrants living in the USA [33], 13 of 26 attitudes related to family, cooperation, morality, religion and government shifted of 50% or more towards adopted country values between the first and second generation, and 23 of 26 had shifted 50% or more by the fourth generation.
Acculturation rates vary across traits. In the same population, some traits can shift substantially while others show little change. For example, there is little difference between first and second generation British Bangladeshis in religiosity and family contact, but a substantial shift in psychological traits such as collectivism or attributional style [29]. Similarly, acculturation rates in US-born Tongan Americans (i.e. second-generation migrants) have been estimated at approximately zero for some traits (e.g. sibling adoption) and as high as 0.87 for others (e.g. ranking of family lines) [19], while another study [33] found that trust-related attitudes show stronger acculturation than family and moral values.
While this empirical literature confirms that acculturation occurs, and provides estimates of population-level acculturation rates, they do not examine the individual-level dynamics (i.e. how migrants learn from others) that drive these population-level acculturation patterns, nor do they extrapolate from observed acculturation rates to long-term impacts on between-group cultural variation, as addressed below.
Acculturation as conformist social learning
While acculturation as a population-level phenomenon certainly exists, there is no empirical research on the individual-level mechanisms by which an individual migrant alters their beliefs or practices as a result of learning from the wider community. The most plausible mechanism already modeled and tested in the cultural evolution literature is conformity [17,36–38], defined as an increased tendency to adopt the most common trait among a sample of other individuals (‘demonstrators’) relative to copying randomly. For example, if 70% of demonstrators are observed possessing trait A, then a conformist learner adopts trait A with a probability greater than 70%. An unbiased, non-conformist learner would adopt trait A with probability exactly 70%. Evolutionary models show that conformity is adaptive and thus likely to evolve in spatially variable environments connected by migration, and when individuals must choose between more than two traits [39], both features of the models implemented below. Both experimental [36,38,40] and real-world [41] evidence suggests that people are conformist. Conformity is also found in non-human species when naive individuals must acquire equally-rewarded cultural traits in a spatially heterogeneous environment with migration [42], again resembling the models used below, suggesting the general adaptiveness of a conformist social learning strategy.
Here I assume that conformity has already evolved (either genetically or culturally [43]) and explore its consequences for shaping between- and within-group cultural variation. Boyd and Richerson [17] and Henrich and Boyd [37] have previously shown that conformity can maintain between-group cultural variation. However, there are several limitations of those models for our understanding of conformity as an acculturation mechanism. First, there was no explicit measure of between-group cultural variation against which to compare model output to empirical data. No previous study has therefore asked or shown how much conformist acculturation is needed to maintain empirically plausible amounts of between-group cultural variation in the face of different levels of migration. Second, those models only featured two cultural traits and three demonstrators, which limits the scope for between-group cultural variation and the potency of conformity respectively. Subsequent models [39] have examined more than two traits, although using a different implementation with a conformity parameter that has an unclear individual level interpretation (see S1 Methods). Third, conformist social learning in those models occurs before migration and so does not affect new migrants. We are interested instead in how migrants potentially acculturate after entering a new population. Finally, I extend such models to the maintenance of cooperative cultural traits maintained by punishment, to compare how acculturation acts to maintain between-group variation in neutral and cooperative traits. This is particularly important given that many debates surrounding the impact of immigration focus on migrants’ contributions to public goods and adherence to cooperative social norms.
The novelty of this study therefore lies in:
linking conformity to a quantitative measure of between-group variation, FST, which has been used in the empirical literature, to ask how much conformist acculturation is needed to maintain plausible values of this measure in the face of migration, going beyond previous studies which have simply noted that conformity can maintain between-group variation
extending Boyd and Richerson’s [17] model of conformity to more than two cultural traits and more than three demonstrators, including cases of joint-majority traits that emerge in such cases, using an implementation that has an empirically interpretable conformity parameter
implementing conformist acculturation as occurring after migration, not before, such that new migrants can potentially acculturate
directly comparing neutral and cooperative traits on the above measures, given the focus of much acculturation research on cooperation-related cultural values such as trust and corruption
Model 1: Migration, acculturation and cultural diversity
I start with a simple model of migration borrowed from population genetics, Wright’s island model [13,14], to which I later add acculturation. Parameters are listed in Table 1. Assume a large population divided into s equally sized and partially isolated sub-populations. Consider a trait (originally an allele, but here a cultural trait) that has mean frequency across the entire population of . Every timestep, each individual migrates with probability m. Migration is random and simultaneous, such that a proportion m of individuals is randomly removed, and this pool of migrants is randomly allocated across all newly-vacant spots in the entire population. Hence a proportion m of individuals in each sub-population will be immigrants, taken from a pool with trait frequency .
Table 1. Parameters in Model 1.
Parameter | Definition |
---|---|
s | The number of sub-populations, and also the number of cultural traits. |
p | The frequency of a trait in a sub-population |
m | Migration rate: the probability in one timestep that an individual moves to a randomly chosen sub-population. Equivalently, the proportion of the population that moves in one timestep. |
n | The number of demonstrators from whom individuals learn during acculturation. |
a | Acculturation rate: the strength of conformist social learning, defined as the degree to which an individual is more likely to adopt the most-common trait among n demonstrators chosen from their sub-population, compared to unbiased, random copying. |
r | Assortation strength. With probability 1—r, the n demonstrators are chosen at random. With probability r, sets of demonstrators all have the same cultural trait. |
Consider a particular sub-population in which the frequency of the trait before and after migration is p and p′ respectively. For a randomly chosen trait in this sub-population, the trait either came from a non-migrant with probability 1—m, with the frequency among those non-migrants p, or from a migrant with probability m, with the frequency among those migrants being . The overall frequency after migration is therefore [13,14]:
(1) |
We are interested in how migration breaks down, and acculturation prevents the breakdown, of between-group cultural variation. Assume therefore that initially there is complete between-group cultural variation, and no within-group variation. Consequently, assume s cultural traits, and at time t = 0 all individuals in sub-population 1 have trait 1, all individuals in sub-population 2 have trait 2, and so on. To quantify the degree of population structure, I use Wright’s FST, a measure typically used to quantify the degree of between-group genetic variation [13,44], but recently used to quantify population structure in cultural traits [3]. As a statistical measure, FST is neutral to transmission mechanism, and simply measures the probability that two randomly-chosen individuals from the same sub-population carry the same trait, compared to two randomly-chosen individuals from the entire population (see S1 Methods for a mathematical definition). An FST of 1 indicates complete between-group variation and no within-group variation. An FST of 0 indicates no between-group variation, with all variation occurring within groups. Here, at time t = 0, FST = 1, and we are interested in when this is maintained and when it drops.
It is difficult to obtain reliable real-world estimates of cultural FST given the lack of quantitative data in fields such as cultural anthropology. Moreover, while group differences are often reported [4], within-population variation is seldom measured. Cultural evolution researchers have begun to address this, finding a mean cultural FST of 0.08 for World Values Survey items [3] and 0.09 for a folktale [45]. Another study lists FST values from 0.008 to 0.612 for various attitudes [46]. Clearly between-group cultural variation can vary greatly per trait and population(s), but FST = 0.1 is perhaps a reasonable benchmark.
What is a plausible value of m? Migration rates differ across time periods and geographical scales. If a timestep in the model is taken as a biological generation, as it typically is in population genetics, then m is the probability that an individual migrates from their natal community during their lifetime. Lifetime migration rates have been estimated for several human populations within nation states (e.g. !Kung villages, or villages in Oxfordshire) at 0.1–0.33 [47]. Another interpretation of m is the proportion of the population that are migrants. In the UK this has increased from 0.042 in 1951 [48] to 0.133 in 2015 [49]. The USA has similar figures of 0.069 in 1950 and 0.134 in 2015 [50]. Some countries, such as Switzerland and Australia, reach a foreign-born proportion of the population close to 0.3 [51]. In this case, timesteps might represent years or decades during which migration statistics are recorded. Either interpretation is valid, depending on the timescale (long-term historical or short-term sociological) in which one is interested. Either way, representative low, typical and high values of m might therefore be 0.01, 0.1 and 0.3 respectively.
Following migration there is acculturation. As justified above, acculturation is implemented here as conformist social learning. Conformist acculturation is added to the island model in each timestep following the completion of all migration. It is assumed to apply to all individuals, not just new migrants. This allows acculturation to occur over multiple generations, consistent with the evidence reviewed above: if a new migrant does not switch traits immediately after migrating, they may do so in subsequent generations. It also parsimoniously assumes that the same conformist bias applies to all individuals, rather than positing special learning mechanisms for migrants and non-migrants.
Conformist acculturation is implemented following Boyd and Richerson [17], by assuming that individuals adopt traits based on their frequency among n randomly chosen demonstrators from their sub-population, with parameter a increasing the probability of adoption of the most frequent trait among those n demonstrators. When a = 0, transmission is unbiased and non-conformist. When a = 1 there is 100% probability of adopting the most frequent trait among the demonstrators, if there is one. Boyd and Richerson [17] modeled the case when n = 3 (the minimum number of demonstrators needed for conformity to act) and there are two traits using binomial theorem. Here I extend their formulation to n > 3 and more than two traits using multinomial theorem (see S1 Methods for the n = 3 model and derivation of n > 3 extension).
If pi' is the frequency of trait i in the sub-population after migration (see Eq 1), then the frequency of trait i in that sub-population after conformist acculturation, pi'', with n demonstrators and s traits, is given by:
(2) |
The first part of Eq 2 gives the updated trait frequency arising from a fraction 1—r of the sub-population that picks demonstrators at random. The expression in the square brackets contains the multinomial theorem and gives, for each combination of s traits among n demonstrators, the probability of that combination randomly forming and giving rise to trait i. k1, k2…ks represent all combinations of s non-negative integers from 0 to s such that the sum of all k is n. For example, when s = 2 and n = 3, then there are two k values, k1 and k2, and four combinations of k1 and k2 that sum to n = 3: k1 = 3 and k2 = 0; k1 = 2 and k2 = 1; k1 = 1 and k2 = 2; and k1 = 0 and k2 = 3. Conceptually, kj represents the number of demonstrators who possess trait j. For example, in the combination {k1 = 2, k2 = 1}, two demonstrators possess trait 1 and one demonstrator possesses trait 2. The multinomial coefficient gives the number of ways in which demonstrators with that combination of traits can form. This is multiplied by the probability of that combination forming, with each trait frequency pj raised to the number of times that trait appears in the combination, kj, and Xi, which gives the probability of adopting trait i for that combination of demonstrators. If kmax is the maximum k in a combination (e.g. for {k1 = 2, k2 = 1}, kmax = k1 = 2), and π is the number of traits that have k = kmax (so when π = 1 there is a single most-common trait, and when π > 1 there is more than one joint-most-common traits), then:
(3) |
The conformity parameter a increases the probability with which the majority trait(s) is adopted, and decreases the probability with which minority traits are adopted.
To give a concrete example, imagine there are three traits (s = 3) and ten demonstrators (n = 10). Two demonstrators have trait 1, five have trait 2 and three have trait 3. Then, with unbiased, non-conformist transmission (a = 0), the probabilities of adoption of traits 1, 2 and 3 are 0.2, 0.5 and 0.3 respectively. Under weak conformity of a = 0.1, the probability of adopting trait 2 increases to 0.52 and the probabilities of adopting traits 1 and 3 drop to 0.19 and 0.29 respectively. Under maximum conformity (a = 1), the most common trait, trait 2, is adopted with probability 0.715, and traits 1 and 3 with probabilities 0.073 and 0.212 respectively. Increasing n also increases the effect of conformity; increasing n to 100 (with a = 1) increases the probability of adoption of the most-common trait 2 to 0.99, almost guaranteeing its adoption. Note that Eq 3 allows conformity to act on combinations where there is more than one most-common trait among the n demonstrators, by increasing all most-common traits’ frequencies equally and proportionally to a.
The final part of Eq 2 deals with non-random demonstrator formation. It is reasonable to assume that, in reality, people are more likely to interact with culturally similar others. This is analogous to assortative mating. In the context of migration, this typically means that migrants will interact only with other migrants, and non-migrants with other non-migrants, at least initially when migrants and non-migrants are culturally dissimilar. In the model, I assume that a fraction r of demonstrators form such that only sets of culturally homogenous demonstrators come together. These form with probability equal to the frequency of the trait they all exhibit, p'i (see S1 Methods for derivation). Assortation therefore leaves cultural trait frequencies unchanged, hence the term rpi.
The S1 Methods give an example of how Eqs 2 and 3 yield trait frequencies following conformist acculturation and assortation. The model was implemented using numerical simulation tracking trait frequencies in each sub-population over time. As an independent replication of the results, the model was also implemented as an individual-based model in which individuals and their traits are explicitly simulated, which gave almost-identical results (see S1 Results).
Results
Migration without acculturation eliminates between-group variation
Without acculturation, migration always eliminates between-group variation, just as in Wright’s original island model and specified by Eq 1. Fig 1 shows time series of FST for low (m = 0.01), typical (m = 0.1) and high (m = 0.3) migration rates. In all cases, the grey a = 0 lines fall to zero. Each trait in each population converges on the mean frequency of that trait across the whole population. Because each sub-population is equally sized, and each trait starts out at unity in one of these s sub-populations, this mean frequency = 1 / s for every trait. This can occur rapidly: for m = 0.01, the perfect between-group structure completely disappears within 300 timesteps, while for m = 0.1 it disappears within 30, and for m = 0.3 within 10.
Conformist acculturation can maintain between-group cultural variation
Fig 1 shows that as conformist acculturation increases in strength, between-group cultural variation is maintained (FST > 0) at equilibrium. When migration is low or moderate then complete acculturation (a = 0, red lines) causes FST to remain at 1, indicating the maintenance of complete between-group cultural variation. Values of a between 0 and 1 generate equilibrium values of FST between 0 and 1, at a level at which migration and acculturation balance out. That is, the decrease in a common trait’s frequency due to migration is equal to the amount by which conformist acculturation increases the common trait’s frequency after migration. At low migration rates, even small amounts of acculturation can restore FST to realistically high values. In Fig 1, when m = 0.01, then a = 0.1, or an extra 10% chance of adopting majority traits per timestep, maintains FST at approximately 0.87, which is already higher than the highest FST found by [46]. An FST of approximately 0.35 can be maintained with just a = 0.02. When m = 0.1, then higher acculturation rates are needed to maintain between-group structure, but an a of just 0.2 is needed to maintain FST at realistic levels of around 0.35. At high migration rates (m = 0.3), the maximum strength of conformist acculturation (a = 1) does not maintain complete between-group cultural variation, and higher values of a are needed to prevent the loss of all between-group cultural variation. Nevertheless, even with such high migration, conformist acculturation can still maintain plausible levels of between-group variation.
Fig 2 shows how the full range of conformist acculturation strength a affects FST, for three different migration rates and four different values of n. Fig 2 confirms that higher FST can be maintained with stronger acculturation (larger a) and lower migration (smaller m). For high migration rates (here, m = 0.1 and m = 0.3), equilibrium FST also increases with n. At low migration rates (m = 0.01), n = 3 is just as effective as larger values of n. This is because the migration rate is so low as to maintain homogeneity in demonstrators no matter how small the sample. When migration is high (m = 0.3), the minimum number of demonstrators that are required for conformity to work, n = 3, fails to maintain any between-group variation at any value of a. This shows that conformist acculturation crucially depends on n as well as a.
The top row of Fig 3 shows how FST varies across the full m and a parameter space, for two values of n. Higher values of FST are maintained with stronger acculturation (higher a) and lower migration (smaller m). Increasing n from n = 3 to n = 7 increases the parameter space in which FST is maintained above zero. This is as expected. When n = 3, there is little opportunity for conformity to act (only when two demonstrators exhibit one trait and one demonstrator exhibits another), while for n = 7 there are more opportunities (demonstrator trait ratios of 6:1, 5:2 and 4:3 all give majorities). For high migration rates of m > 0.5, no amount of acculturation can prevent the elimination of between-group cultural variation, although this level of migration is already unrealistically high. For plausible values of m around 0.1, a substantial range of a yields realistic FST s of 0.1 or more, especially when there are many demonstrators.
Assortation reduces the effect of acculturation
Assortation acts to restrict the parameter space within which FST is maintained, as shown in the lower two panels in Fig 3 where r = 0.5. This is as expected given Eq 2. Assortation counteracts the effect of conformity by reducing the likelihood that heterogeneous sets of demonstrators come together, which is required for conformity to operate.
Summary of Model 1
Model 1 affords the following insights. First, even small amounts of migration can rapidly break down between-group cultural variation. This is analogous to how migration in genetic evolution can rapidly break down between-group genetic variation, and is well known from population genetics. Second, as shown in previous cultural evolution models, the breakdown of between-group cultural variation by migration is prevented by conformist acculturation, via both the strength of this conformist bias, a (what might be considered a psychological factor), and the number of demonstrators from whom individuals learn, n (what might be considered a social or demographic factor). As both a and n increase, between-group cultural variation is more likely to be maintained. Third, at realistic and typical levels of migration, around m = 0.1, even small amounts of acculturation can counteract migration and maintain plausible amounts of between-group cultural variation. At m = 0.1, just a small increase in the probability of adopting majority traits (a = 0.2) among a small number of demonstrators (n = 5) can maintain plausible amounts of between-group cultural variation. Even the highest levels of migration currently seen in the real world, around m = 0.3, can still be prevented from breaking down between-group variation with moderately strong acculturation. Although there is a paucity of empirical data on the individual-level mechanism of acculturation, existing acculturation research (see S1 Table and S1 Fig) suggests that acculturation is easily strong enough to meet this criterion, although there is a need for more research along the lines of [19] that directly estimates a across multiple migrant generations, and tests whether acculturation really is conformist. Finally, assortation acts against acculturation: when individuals only learn from culturally homogenous sets of demonstrators, then acculturation is weaker. This reflects the common intuition that more integrated migrant minorities are more likely to acculturate than marginalized minorities.
Model 2: Migration, acculturation and cooperation
Model 1 examined the effects of migration and acculturation on neutral cultural variation. Traits were equally likely to be copied and did not affect individuals’ fitness. Migration was also random between groups. Much public concern over migration, however, centers on cooperative behavior and norms, for which neither of these assumptions are true. Think of concerns among some US citizens over Mexican immigration, and some Europeans over North African or Middle Eastern immigrants. In such cases, people are concerned that migrants coming from societies with less-cooperative norms (e.g. high crime, tax avoidance and corruption; military conflict; weak or corrupt institutions) who are moving to societies with more-cooperative norms (e.g. low crime, tax avoidance and corruption; strong institutions such as public health or education) will bring their less-cooperative norms with them, free-ride on the more-cooperative norms of their adopted society, and cause a break-down of cooperation in the adopted society. Migration is not random here, as it was in Model 1: people are more likely to move from less-cooperative to more-cooperative societies [52,53], which will exacerbate the degradation of cooperation in the latter.
This situation again concerns acculturation. The above scenario assumes that migrants bring and retain their non-cooperative norms with them, but in reality they may acculturate to the cooperative norms of the adopted country. But how much acculturation is enough to maintain cooperative norms? Dimant et al. [54] found that migration in general has no effect on a receiving country’s corruption level, suggesting that migrants acculturate to such an extent that between-group variation in corruption is maintained. However, when examining migration only from highly corrupt countries, there was a small positive effect on the receiving country’s corruption levels, although this effect attenuated over time. This indicates that corruption can be transmitted by migrants, but acculturation may counteract this over successive generations. This is consistent with the findings of [32] (see S1 Table), which found that second generation migrants in high-trust countries typically have institutional trust that is intermediate between their parents and their birth countries.
Human cooperation is also of major scientific interest, with much debate over how to explain the unusually high levels of non-kin-directed altruism in humans [46,55,56]. Typically, migration is seen as a force acting against cooperation because it breaks up groups of cooperators and spreads selfish free-riding behavior [55,57]. Theories of cultural group selection require stable between-group cultural variation in cooperative behavior and so need some acculturating mechanism to work against migration [46].
Model 2 therefore examines the effect of migration and acculturation on the maintenance of a cooperative cultural trait in the face of incoming migrants with non-cooperative norms. While this is an extreme case, it is useful for delineating the effect of different forces. Additional parameters in Model 2 are listed in Table 2.
Table 2. Additional parameters in Model 2.
Parameter | Definition |
---|---|
N | Fixed number of individuals in the focal sub-population |
p | Proportion of individuals in the focal sub-population who are cooperators |
b | Benefit to the sub-population from each cooperator |
c | Cost of cooperation borne by each cooperator |
u | Cost of punishment borne by each cooperator, weighted by the proportion of defectors in the sub-population |
v | Punishment penalty borne by each defector, weighted by the proportion of cooperators in the sub-population |
L | Strength of payoff-biased social learning within the sub-population |
Individuals are either cooperators or defectors, and are in sub-populations of constant and equal size N. We are interested in the maintenance of cooperation in a sub-population where cooperation is common yet faces migrants coming from sub-populations where defection is common. Assume for simplicity a single focal sub-population initially composed entirely of cooperators (p = 1, where p is the proportion of cooperators), surrounded by a larger meta-population that supplies defecting migrants and which is so large as to have a fixed p = 0.
Within the focal sub-population, in each timestep each cooperator pays a cost c (c > 0) to benefit the entire sub-population by an amount b, where b > c. Defectors pay no cost and give no benefit. The total group benefit in the sub-population, bNp, is divided equally among all N sub-population members. Cooperators in the sub-population therefore have fitness wc = 1 + bp − c and defectors have fitness wd = 1 + bp, where 1 is baseline fitness.
Defectors will always have higher fitness than cooperators for c > 0 and always go to fixation, assuming some selective force such as payoff-biased social learning (see below) or natural selection. As soon as mutation, errors or migration introduce defectors into the cooperating group, cooperation will disappear. This is unrealistic for most human groups and makes the present model uninteresting. I therefore introduce a mechanism to maintain cooperation: coordinated altruistic (i.e. costly) punishment. Punishment is a common strategy for maintaining cooperation and may arise via trial-and-error to create institutions [58], between-group selection [55] or other mechanisms. I am not concerned here with these processes and assume that punishment has already evolved.
Hence, assume each cooperator pays a cost u/N per defector to reduce the payoff of each defector by v/N, where v > u [55]. There are Np cooperators who punish each defector, so defectors now have overall fitness of wd = 1 + bp − vp. Each cooperator punishes N(1—p) defectors, so cooperators have fitness wc = 1 + bp − c − u(1 − p). Cooperators and defectors will have equal fitness when wd = wc, or when p = p*, where
(4) |
Defectors will invade a population of cooperators when p < p*. That is, cooperation is maintained when cooperators are common enough that the punishment costs to defectors outweigh the costs to cooperators of cooperating. When c > v, cooperation is never maintained. Note that non-punishing cooperators could invade a population of punishing cooperators because the former would not pay the cost u. I assume that this second-order free-riding problem is already solved (e.g. by the mechanisms above) and non-punishing cooperators are not included in the model. I also assume that a sub-population entirely composed of defectors (p = 0) always has lower fitness than a sub-population with any cooperators (p > 0). See S1 Methods for details.
As in Model 1, the first timestep event is migration determined by migration rate m, but this is now payoff-biased. Individuals move to sub-populations with higher mean fitness than their own at a rate proportional to the mean fitness difference between their own sub-population and the meta-population [52]. By assumption, in Model 2 this will always involve defectors coming into the sub-population and replacing cooperators (who are assumed to die or migrate away) at a rate proportional to W—1, where W is the mean fitness of the focal sub-population and 1 is the mean fitness of the meta-population where p = 0. The frequency of cooperators in the sub-population after migration, p', is therefore
(5) |
The constant μ ensures that mμ(W − 1) never exceeds m, so that m is always the maximum migration rate. Eq 5 resembles Eq 1, but with m now a function of relative sub-population fitness, and = 0.
Following migration there is acculturation, identical to Model 1. With probability a, each individual adopts the most common strategy (cooperate or defect) among n demonstrators in their sub-population according to Eq 2 (with s = 2, given two traits, cooperate and defect). This occurs after all migration has finished.
Finally, there is payoff-biased social learning within each sub-population. With probability L, individuals switch strategies in proportion to the fitness payoff difference within their sub-population between the alternative strategy and their current strategy. If p'' is the frequency of cooperators after migration and conformist acculturation (see Eq 2), then the frequency after payoff-biased social learning, p‴, is given by:
(6) |
where γ is a constant that scales L according to the maximum possible fitness difference. Payoff-biased social learning creates a selective force within the sub-population favoring whichever strategy gives the highest payoff, which in turn depends on Eq 4.
Model 2 comprises cycles of Eqs 5, 2 and 6 (payoff-biased migration, conformist acculturation and payoff-biased social learning). As we are interested in the maintenance of cooperation, we track the proportion of cooperators p over time in the focal sub-population which initially comprises all cooperators.
Results
Payoff-biased migration alone eliminates cooperation
In the absence of acculturation (a = 0) and payoff-biased social learning (L = 0), payoff-biased migration (m > 0) causes defectors to flow from the all-defect meta-population into the initially all-cooperate sub-population to eliminate cooperation entirely (Fig 4A). Because the strength of payoff-biased migration is a function of the mean population fitness relative to the mean fitness of the metapopulation, the rate of decline is initially fast due to the high initial mean fitness of the cooperative sub-population, and slows as cooperators leave and mean fitness drops.
Conformist acculturation can maintain cooperation
As in Model 1, when conformist acculturation is sufficiently strong (i.e. a and n are sufficiently large), then the decline in cooperation is halted and cooperation is maintained at a point where acculturation and migration balance out (Fig 4B). This can also be seen in Fig 5A, which shows a similar relationship between a and m as in Model 1: cooperation is most likely to be maintained when a is high, and m is low.
Two points are worth noting. First, when acculturation is not strong enough to maintain cooperation, it actually speeds up the decline. Compare the several thousand timesteps it takes for cooperation to drop to approximately p = 0 in Fig 4A for a = 0 to the 100 timesteps it takes to reach p = 0 in Fig 4B for a = 0.1. Conformity favors the majority trait, which when p < 0.5 is defection, speeding up the convergence on p = 0.
Second, unlike in Model 1, we see an interesting dynamic at values of a that are not strong enough to maintain cooperation (e.g. a = 0.3 in Fig 4B). An initial rapid decline in cooperation when p = 1 slows as p declines, then increases again. This can be understood in terms of the relative strengths of payoff-biased migration and conformist acculturation. Payoff-biased migration is strongest at p = 1 and weakens as it approaches its stable equilibrium at p = 0. Conformist acculturation has an unstable equilibrium at p = 0.5 where the two traits are equal in frequency, and increases in strength as the frequency approaches the two stable equilibria at p = 0 and p = 1. In Fig 4B when a = 0.3, the initial rapid decline is due to strong payoff-biased migration near p = 1. As p decreases, payoff-biased migration weakens, and conformist acculturation slows the decline. As we approach p = 0.5 conformity weakens, allowing payoff-biased migration to take over and increase the rate of decline. When p drops below 0.5, conformity starts to work with payoff-biased migration to increase the rate of decline further.
This dynamic means that there are fewer values of a in Model 2 at which p is maintained at intermediate values, compared to Model 1. This can be seen in Fig 5A: final frequencies are typically either p = 0 (dark blue) or p > 0.8 (yellow / light green), with little in between. Contrast this to Model 1 in Fig 3, which has more intermediate frequencies.
Payoff-biased social learning acts like an acculturating mechanism
Fig 4C shows a strikingly similar dynamic for payoff-biased social learning (L) as for conformist acculturation. When L is large, cooperation is maintained. When L is small, cooperation declines to zero, with a similar-shaped curve for intermediate values of L. Payoff-biased social learning therefore acts as an acculturating mechanism, like conformity. It does this because cooperation is favored when common, and disfavored when less common, similar to conformity (see S1 Methods). Fig 4B shows how L increases the parameter space in which a maintains cooperation in the face of migration, showing how they work in the same manner.
Whereas conformist acculturation has an unstable equilibrium at p = 0.5 (given that there are two traits), payoff-biased social learning has an unstable equilibrium at p*. In Fig 4C, p* = 0.5, so there is little difference to Fig 4B. However, at different values of p*, there will be different dynamics (see S1 Methods). Fig 6A–6C shows how changing the basin of attraction for cooperation via the punishment penalty for defectors, v, and therefore p* (via Eq 4), alters the effect of L. When v is small, p* is large, cooperation has a smaller basin of attraction, and L mostly favors defectors. When v is large, p* is small, cooperation has a larger basin of attraction, and L largely favors cooperators. Conformist acculturation, by contrast, does not vary with v or any other fitness parameter, as it solely works on the basis of trait frequency (Fig 6D–6F).
Summary of Model 2
Like Model 1, Model 2 shows that conformist acculturation works to maintain cultural traditions in the face of migration. Rather than neutral cultural variation, here the tradition involves cooperative behavior that is lost due to payoff-biased migration bringing non-cooperators from low-payoff to high-payoff sub-populations. The evidence reviewed above and in S1 Table includes cases of acculturation of cooperative behavior, with migrants from low-trust or high-corruption countries acculturating to the high-trust or low-corruption norms of their adopted country within a few generations [32,54]. More empirical work is required to accurately specify acculturation rates across a broader range of societies and norms, and test whether it is conformist. However, we can apply the same insight here as from Model 1: surprisingly little acculturation is needed to maintain cooperation in the face of realistic levels of migration. Figs 4B and 5A, for example, show that for m = 0.1, an a of around 0.4 (with n = 5) is sufficient to maintain cooperation. On the other hand, where migration is strong enough to allow non-cooperating migrants to increase in frequency, conformity speeds up the loss of cooperation when cooperation becomes a minority trait. There are also fewer intermediate cases: cooperation is typically either maintained at a high level or lost completely.
Finally, within-group payoff-biased social learning plus punishment acts like an acculturating process, also maintaining cooperation in the face of migration. This is because cooperation is frequency dependent, with cooperators having high fitness when common due to punishment of noncooperators. Unlike conformity, the acculturating power of payoff-biased social learning depends on the fitness functions and the strength of punishment. The real-world correlate of the latter might be the strength of sanctioning institutions. When punishment of defectors is more effective via higher v (stronger sanctioning institutions), then payoff-biased social learning more effectively prevents migration from eliminating cooperation.
Discussion
Public debates concerning migration often proceed with little empirical basis. Academic research into migration is voluminous but seldom seeks to formally link individual-level learning, interaction and acculturation to population-level patterns of cultural diversity and change. I have attempted here to formalize the processes that contribute to the maintenance and loss of cultural diversity in the face of migration, drawing on and extending previous models of cultural evolution. Migration itself (m) breaks down between-group cultural variation and homogenizes behavior. Acculturation, here assumed to be conformist, prevents this breakdown. This acculturation effect increases with both the strength of the conformist learning bias, a, and the number of individuals from whom one learns, n, but weakens when individuals interact assortatively with culturally similar others, via r. The learning bias strength might be considered a psychological factor, while the number of demonstrators and assortation might be considered social or demographic factors. Model 1 found that surprisingly little acculturation is needed to maintain between-group variation in functionally neutral cultural traits given plausible rates of migration. Model 2 found similar results for a cooperative cultural trait, which is additionally subject to fitness costs and benefits. Even though payoff-biased migration acts to reduce cooperation, conformist acculturation and/or payoff-biased social learning (the latter working together with sanctioning institutions that punish non-cooperators) can preserve cooperation.
How do these insights relate to the empirical data concerning migration and acculturation? The evidence regarding the strength of acculturation reviewed above (see also S1 Table and S1 Fig) suggests that migrants often shift around 50% towards the values of their adopted society every generation, although this varies across traits and societies. In the context of the models, we can tentatively conclude that these acculturation rates are easily strong enough to maintain cultural traditions in the face of migration. The models suggest that values of a much less than 0.5 can preserve variation for realistic values of m. If this is the case, then common fears that migration will inevitably destroy existing cultural traditions may be exaggerated or unfounded. Yet this is only a very loose comparison. There is little quantitative work that tries to measure acculturation rates in a way comparable to acculturation as modeled here. We do not know how migrants integrate social information from multiple sources, whether they do this in a conformist manner, the size and diversity of their social networks, or how this changes with successive generations who experience different social environments compared to their parents. Perhaps demonstrator-based biases, where people preferentially learn from certain sources such as parents, teachers or celebrities [17], are more appropriate learning mechanisms. We also do not know whether acculturation of cooperative norms is driven by conformist or payoff-biased social learning, both of which have similar acculturating effects but for different reasons.
While the models here might counter extreme politically conservative claims that any level of migration is detrimental for the maintenance of cultural traditions, they also count against extreme liberal claims that migration can never be too high. For very high rates of migration (e.g. m > 0.5) then between-group cultural variation is typically eroded completely. While such levels exceed modern-day migration rates, such a situation might resemble past colonization events. The colonization of the New World, for example, led to the elimination or attenuation of much pre-contact cultural variation and replacement with European cultural values such as religious beliefs. Further models might integrate such power-based dynamics into the framework developed in the present study.
The models presented here comprise many simplifying assumptions and omissions that could be explored or incorporated in future models. The present models failed to incorporate any benefits of migration, such as when migrants bring beneficial new skills and knowledge into a society and recombine them with existing skills and knowledge. The assumption of Model 2 that migrants always possess non-cooperative norms is obviously an unrealistic extreme case. Future models might examine the two-way exchange of cooperative behavior between multiple sub-populations, and the consequences for between-group competition by allowing N to vary as a function of mean sub-population fitness [52]. The present models only allowed individuals to hold one trait at a time. Future models might examine the simultaneous acculturation of different traits at different rates, as found empirically [19], and the consequences for multi-dimensional cultural diversity. Finally, the traits here are discrete whereas many cross-cultural measures are continuous, which may gradually shift over time due to averaging across different demonstrators [17].
Note that acculturation as considered in the models in the current study is considered in the restricted sense of the extent to which migrants become more similar to the adopted population, or retain their heritage values, on a single quantitative dimension. This is only one possible acculturation dynamic. In Berry’s [15] classification of acculturation styles, this is the assimilation vs separation dimension, the former involving shifts in migrants towards host values, the latter involving retention of heritage values. Berry [15] also highlights the possibility of integration, which entails maintaining heritage traits and adopting host society traits and possibly merging the two; and marginalization, which entails the rejection of both heritage and host society traits. Similarly, political scientists categorize modern nation state policies on migration as exclusionary, assimilationist or multicultural [53]. The integration and multicultural dynamics in these schemes serve to highlight how migrants can contribute to and shape their adopted country’s culture. Migration is a complex phenomenon, and the empirical literature reviewed here, and the models in this study, represent an attempt to understand one particular simplified aspect of this complex reality.
One recent paper presents similar models of acculturation and migration [20], drawing on Berry’s [15] classification of acculturation styles. In that model, acculturation was implemented as a probability of switching to another individual’s cultural trait given the probability of those two individuals interacting plus the individuals’ relative cultural conservatism. This is an alternative to the conformity modeled here; one key difference is that in [20] residents and immigrants have different levels of conservatism, whereas here residents and migrants have identical conformist biases. That study also only modeled a single focal population, rather than multiple sub-populations and traits as in Model 1 here (although similar to my Model 2). The focus there was on when “multicultural” societies emerge; here it is on when between-group diversity persists. Nevertheless, broadly similar findings can be observed: there, resident traits disappear when migration is high, acculturation is weak (i.e. residents and immigrants are similarly conservative) and assortation is high, which is also when between-group diversity disappears in my models. Another recent model [59] examined the maintenance of between-group cultural variation when groups differ in power, finding that variation is maintained when inter-group borders allow members of the less powerful minority group to cross but not members of the more powerful majority, or when the minority inhabit a region that the majority does not visit. In [59], however, inter-group interactions do not take the form of permanent migration, and again only two groups and two traits are considered. I anticipate a class of models such as these with different assumptions against which empirical data can be compared.
The focus here is on humans, but the same principles likely also apply to non-human culture. Between-group cultural variation has been demonstrated in numerous species [60], and conformity in at least one [42]. Field experiments have demonstrated how migrant vervet monkeys switch to locally common food choices [61], an instance of non-human acculturation. Integrating human migration research with this non-human research, which often has far better individual-level behavioral data [42], will be beneficial to each.
If conformity is the mechanism underlying migrant acculturation, it is instructive to consider how conformity itself might vary between individuals and societies. Evidence suggests that social learning biases such as conformity vary not only individually but also culturally [43]. Classic social psychology research suggests that East Asian societies are more conformist than Western societies [62] (albeit using a different sense of conformity to that implemented here). If that is indeed the case, then perhaps East Asian migrants with a conformist heritage would more effectively acculturate into Western society than vice versa. This might suggest that the acculturation literature, which is biased towards Asian American samples (see S1 Table), is not representative of acculturation in general. On the other hand, perhaps conformity within East Asian societies does not translate to conformity among East Asian migrants living in Western societies. Or, perhaps conformity is itself a trait that is subject to acculturation, and second generation East Asian migrants become less conformist by conforming to Western non-conformity. This ‘social learning of social learning strategies’ deserves further modelling (e.g. [63]) and empirical study [43].
Migration is one of the fundamental drivers of genetic evolutionary change, along with selection, mutation and drift. Migration is surely also a fundamental factor driving cultural evolution, yet works differently due to the often-rapid acculturation of migrants to local behavior. A major scientific and applied challenge for cultural evolution research is to explore the role of migration and acculturation in shaping human cultural diversity both past and present. The models here provide a step towards this goal, but also highlight major gaps in our empirical knowledge regarding how acculturation operates at the individual level, which is crucial for anticipating the population-level consequences of migration on cultural change and variation.
Supporting information
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Ruan Kilroy for locating some of the studies in S1 Table and devising the measure of acculturation used in S1 Fig.
Data Availability
All code for the models is available at: https://github.com/amesoudi/migrationmodels.
Funding Statement
This work was supported by an Economic and Social Research Council (ESRC) research grant ES/J01916X/1. The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
References
- 1.Pagel M, Mace R. The cultural wealth of nations. Nature. 2004;428: 275–278. 10.1038/428275a [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Henrich J, Heine SJ, Norenzayan A. The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2010;33: 61–135. 10.1017/S0140525X0999152X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Bell AV, Richerson PJ, McElreath R. Culture rather than genes provides greater scope for the evolution of large-scale human prosociality. PNAS. 2009;106: 17671–17674. 10.1073/pnas.0903232106 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Kirby KR, Gray RD, Greenhill SJ, Jordan FM, Gomes-Ng S, Bibiko H-J, et al. D-PLACE: A global database of cultural, linguistic and environmental diversity. PLOS ONE. 2016;11: e0158391 10.1371/journal.pone.0158391 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Kitayama S, Uskul AK. Culture, mind, and the brain: Current evidence and future directions. Annual Review of Psychology. 2011;62: 419–449. 10.1146/annurev-psych-120709-145357 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Gächter S, Herrmann B, Thöni C. Culture and cooperation. Phil Trans R Soc B. 2010;365: 2651–2661. 10.1098/rstb.2010.0135 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Reich D. Who we are and how we got here: Ancient DNA and the new science of the human past Oxford University Press; 2018. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Timmermann A, Friedrich T. Late pleistocene climate drivers of early human migration. Nature. 2016;538: 92–95. 10.1038/nature19365 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Crawford MH, Campbell BC. Causes and consequences of human migration: An evolutionary perspective Cambridge University Press; 2012. [Google Scholar]
- 10.Loog L, Lahr MM, Kovacevic M, Manica A, Eriksson A, Thomas MG. Estimating mobility using sparse data: Application to human genetic variation. PNAS. 2017; 201703642. 10.1073/pnas.1703642114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Hatton TJ, Williamson JG. The age of mass migration: Causes and economic impact Oxford University Press; 1998. [Google Scholar]
- 12.Davis KF, D’Odorico P, Laio F, Ridolfi L. Global spatio-temporal patterns in human migration: A complex network perspective. PLOS ONE. 2013;8: e53723 10.1371/journal.pone.0053723 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Hartl D, Clark A. Principles of population genetics Sunderland, MA: Sinauer; 1997. [Google Scholar]
- 14.Wright S. Evolution in mendelian populations. Genetics. 1931;16: 97–159. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Berry JW. A psychology of immigration. Journal of Social Issues. 2001;57: 615–631. 10.1111/0022-4537.00231 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Cavalli-Sforza LL, Feldman MW. Cultural transmission and evolution. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press; 1981. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Boyd R, Richerson PJ. Culture and the evolutionary process Chicago, IL: Univ. Chicago Press; 1985. [Google Scholar]
- 18.Mesoudi A. Pursuing Darwin’s curious parallel: Prospects for a science of cultural evolution. PNAS. 2017;114: 7853–7860. 10.1073/pnas.1620741114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Bell AV. The dynamics of culture lost and conserved: Demic migration as a force in new diaspora communities. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2013;34: 23–28. 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2012.08.002 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Erten EY, Berg P van den, Weissing FJ. Acculturation orientations affect the evolution of a multicultural society. Nature Communications. 2018;9: 58 10.1038/s41467-017-02513-0 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Massey DS, Arango J, Hugo G, Kouaouci A, Pellegrino A, Taylor JE. Theories of international migration: A review and appraisal. Population and Development Review. 1993;19: 431–466. 10.2307/2938462 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Kearney M. The local and the global: The anthropology of globalization and transnationalism. Annual Review of Anthropology. 1995;24: 547–565. 10.1146/annurev.an.24.100195.002555 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Eurostat. Record number of over 1.2 million first time asylum seekers registered in 2015 [Internet]. Luxembourg: European Commission; 2016. Available: ec.europa.eu/eurostat/ [Google Scholar]
- 24.Wike R, Stokes B, Simmons K. Europeans fear wave of refugees will mean more terrorism, fewer jobs [Internet]. Pew Research Center; 2016 Jul. Available: http://www.pewglobal.org/2016/07/11/europeans-fear-wave-of-refugees-will-mean-more-terrorism-fewer-jobs/
- 25.Ormston R., Curtice J., editors. British social attitudes: The 32nd report London, UK: NatCen Social Research; 2015. [Google Scholar]
- 26.RT International. I want to free france from EU straitjacket–far-right party leader. RT international [Internet]. [cited 29 Dec 2017]. Available: https://www.rt.com/news/france-eu-immigrants-pen/
- 27.Mason R. Nigel farage: Immigration has left Britain almost unrecognisable. The Guardian. 2015; Available: http://www.theguardian.com/politics/2015/mar/31/nigel-farage-ukip-immigration-britain-unrecognisable-general-election-poster
- 28.R Core Team. R: A language and environment for statistical computing [Internet]. Vienna, Austria: R Foundation for Statistical Computing; 2017. Available: www.R-project.org [Google Scholar]
- 29.Mesoudi A, Magid K, Hussain D. How do people become W.E.I.R.D.? Migration reveals the cultural transmission mechanisms underlying variation in psychological processes. PLOS ONE. 2016;11: e0147162 10.1371/journal.pone.0147162 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Endo Y, Heine SJ, Lehman DR. Culture and positive illusions in close relationships: How my relationships are better than yours. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2000;26: 1571–1586. 10.1177/01461672002612011 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Spencer-Rodgers J, Peng K, Wang L, Hou Y. Dialectical self-esteem and east-west differences in psychological well-being. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2004;30: 1416–1432. 10.1177/0146167204264243 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Dinesen PT, Hooghe M. When in Rome, do as the Romans do: The acculturation of generalized trust among immigrants in Western Europe. International Migration Review. 2010;44: 697–727. 10.1111/j.1747-7379.2010.00822.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Giavazzi F, Petkov I, Schiantarelli F. Culture: Persistence and evolution. NBER Working Paper No 20174. 2014; 10.3386/w20174 [DOI]
- 34.Alesina A, Giuliano P. Culture and institutions. Journal of Economic Literature. 2015;53: 898–944. 10.1257/jel.53.4.898 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Heine SJ. Cultural psychology New York: WW Norton; 2011. [Google Scholar]
- 36.Efferson C, Lalive R, Richerson PJ, McElreath R, Lubell M. Conformists and mavericks: The empirics of frequency-dependent cultural transmission. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2008;29: 56–64. 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2007.08.003 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Henrich J, Boyd R. The evolution of conformist transmission and the emergence of between-group differences. Evolution and Human Behavior. 1998;19: 215–241. 10.1016/S1090-5138(98)00018-X [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Muthukrishna M, Morgan TJH, Henrich J. The when and who of social learning and conformist transmission. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2016;37: 10–20. 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.05.004 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Nakahashi W, Wakano JY, Henrich J. Adaptive social learning strategies in temporally and spatially varying environments. Human Nature. 2012;23: 386–418. 10.1007/s12110-012-9151-y [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Glowacki L, Molleman L. Subsistence styles shape human social learning strategies. Nature Human Behaviour. 2017;1: 0098 10.1038/s41562-017-0098 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Howard JA, Gibson MA. Frequency-dependent female genital cutting behaviour confers evolutionary fitness benefits. Nature Ecology & Evolution. 2017;1: 0049 10.1038/s41559-016-0049 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Aplin LM, Farine DR, Morand-Ferron J, Cockburn A, Thornton A, Sheldon BC. Experimentally induced innovations lead to persistent culture via conformity in wild birds. Nature. 2015;518: 538–541. 10.1038/nature13998 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Mesoudi A, Chang L, Dall SRX, Thornton A. The evolution of individual and cultural variation in social learning. Trends in Ecology & Evolution. 2016;31: 215–225. 10.1016/j.tree.2015.12.012 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Wright S. Isolation by distance. Genetics. 1943;28: 114–138. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Ross RM, Greenhill SJ, Atkinson QD. Population structure and cultural geography of a folktale in Europe. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B. 2013;280: 20123065 10.1098/rspb.2012.3065 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Richerson P, Baldini R, Bell AV, Demps K, Frost K, Hillis V, et al. Cultural group selection plays an essential role in explaining human cooperation: A sketch of the evidence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2016;39 10.1017/S0140525X1400106X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Rogers AR, Harpending HC. Migration and genetic drift in human populations. Evolution. 1986;40: 1312–1327. 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1986.tb05754.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Rendall M, Salt J. The foreign-born population Focus on people and migration. Palgrave Macmillan, London; 2005. pp. 131–151. 10.1007/978-1-349-75096-2_8 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Office for National Statistics. Population of the UK by country of birth and nationality: 2015 [Internet]. 2016. Available: https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/populationandmigration/internationalmigration/bulletins/ukpopulationbycountryofbirthandnationality/august2016
- 50.Singer A. Contemporary immigrant gateways in historical perspective. Daedalus. 2013;142: 76–91. 10.1162/DAED_a_00220 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Trends in international migrant stock: The 2015 revision [Internet]. United Nations, Department of Economic; Social Affairs, Population Division; 2015. Available: https://www.un.org/en/development/desa/population/migration/data/estimates2/estimates15.shtml
- 52.Boyd R, Richerson PJ. Voting with your feet: Payoff biased migration and the evolution of group beneficial behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 2009;257: 331–339. 10.1016/j.jtbi.2008.12.007 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Castles S, Miller MJ. The age of migration Guilford Press; 2003. [Google Scholar]
- 54.Dimant E, Krieger T, Redlin M. A crook is a crook … but is he still a crook abroad? On the effect of immigration on destination-country corruption. German Economic Review. 2014;16: 464–489. 10.1111/geer.12064 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Boyd R, Gintis H, Bowles S, Richerson PJ. The evolution of altruistic punishment. PNAS. 2003;100: 3531–3535. 10.1073/pnas.0630443100 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Kurzban R, Burton-Chellew MN, West SA. The evolution of altruism in humans. Annual Review of Psychology. 2015;66: 575–599. 10.1146/annurev-psych-010814-015355 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Aoki K. A condition for group selection to prevail over counteracting individual selection. Evolution. 1982;36: 832–842. 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1982.tb05449.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Ostrom E. Governing the commons Cambridge University Press; 1990. [Google Scholar]
- 59.Bunce JA, McElreath R. Sustainability of minority culture when inter-ethnic interaction is profitable. Nature Human Behaviour. 2018;2: 205–212. 10.1038/s41562-018-0306-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Whiten A. Culture extends the scope of evolutionary biology in the great apes. PNAS. 2017;114: 7790–7797. 10.1073/pnas.1620733114 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Waal E van de, Borgeaud C, Whiten A. Potent social learning and conformity shape a wild primate’s foraging decisions. Science. 2013;340: 483–485. 10.1126/science.1232769 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Bond R, Smith P. Culture and conformity: A meta-analysis of studies using Asch’s line judgment task. Psychological Bulletin. 1996;119: 111–137. [Google Scholar]
- 63.Ghirlanda S, Enquist M, Nakamaru M. Cultural evolution develops its own rules: The rise of conservatism and persuasion. Current Anthropology. 2006;47: 1027–1034. 10.1086/508696 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Supplementary Materials
Data Availability Statement
All code for the models is available at: https://github.com/amesoudi/migrationmodels.