Abstract
The broad concept of emergence is instrumental in various of the most challenging open scientific questions—yet, few quantitative theories of what constitutes emergent phenomena have been proposed. This article introduces a formal theory of causal emergence in multivariate systems, which studies the relationship between the dynamics of parts of a system and macroscopic features of interest. Our theory provides a quantitative definition of downward causation, and introduces a complementary modality of emergent behaviour—which we refer to as causal decoupling. Moreover, the theory allows practical criteria that can be efficiently calculated in large systems, making our framework applicable in a range of scenarios of practical interest. We illustrate our findings in a number of case studies, including Conway’s Game of Life, Reynolds’ flocking model, and neural activity as measured by electrocorticography.
Author summary
Many scientific domains exhibit phenomena that seem to be “more than the sum of their parts”; for example, flocks seem to be more than a mere collection of birds, and consciousness seems more than electric impulses between neurons. But what does it mean for a physical system to exhibit emergence? The literature on this topic contains various conflicting approaches, many of which are unable to provide quantitative, falsifiable statements. Having a rigorous, quantitative theory of emergence could allow us to discover the exact conditions that allow a flock to be more than individual birds, and to better understand how the mind emerges from the brain. Here we provide exactly that: a formal theory of what constitutes causal emergence, how to measure it, and what different “types” of emergence exist. To do this, we leverage recent developments in information dynamics—the study of how information flows through and is modified by dynamical systems. As part of this framework, we provide a mathematical definition of causal emergence, and also practical formulae for analysing empirical data. Using these, we are able to confirm emergence in the iconic Conway’s Game of Life, in certain flocking patterns, and in representations of motor movements in the monkey’s brain.
Introduction
While most of our representations of the physical world are hierarchical, there is still no agreement on how the co-existing “layers” of this hierarchy interact. On the one hand, reductionism claims that all levels can always be explained based on sufficient knowledge of the lowest scale and, consequently—taking an intentionally extreme example—that a sufficiently accurate theory of elementary particles should be able to predict the existence of social phenomena like communism. On the other hand, emergentism argues that there can be autonomy between layers, i.e. that some phenomena at macroscopic layers might only be accountable in terms of other macroscopic phenomena. While emergentism might seem to better serve our intuition, it is not entirely clear how a rigorous theory of emergence could be formulated within our modern scientific worldview, which tends to be dominated by reductionist principles.
Emergent phenomena are usually characterised as either strong or weak [1]. Strong emergence corresponds to the somewhat paradoxical case of supervenient properties with irreducible causal power [2]; i.e. properties that are fully determined by microscopic levels but can nevertheless exert causal influences that are not entirely accountable from microscopic considerations (the case of strong emergence most commonly argued in the literature is the one of conscious experiences with respect to their corresponding physical substrate [3, 4]). Strong emergence has been as much a cause of wonder as a perennial source of philosophical headaches, being described as “uncomfortably like magic” while accused of being logically inconsistent [2] and sustained on illegitimate metaphysics [5]. Weak emergence has been proposed as a more docile alternative to strong emergence, where macroscopic features have irreducible causal power in practice but not in principle. A popular formulation of weak emergence is due to Bedau [5], and corresponds to properties generated by elements at microscopic levels in such complicated ways that they cannot be derived via explanatory shortcuts, but only by exhaustive simulation. While this formulation is usually accepted by the scientific community, it is not well-suited to address mereological questions about emergence in scenarios where parts-whole relationships are the primary interest.
Part of the difficulty in building a deeper understanding of strong emergence is the absence of simple but clear analytical models that can serve the community to guide discussions and mature theories. Efforts have been made to introduce quantitative metrics of weak emergence [6], which enable fine-grained data-driven alternatives to traditional all-or-none classifications. In this vein, an attractive alternative comes from the work on causal emergence introduced in Ref. [7] and later developed in Refs. [8, 9], which showed that macroscopic observables can sometimes exhibit more causal power (as understood within the framework of Pearl’s do-calculus [10]) than microscopic variables. However, this framework relies on strong assumptions that are rarely satisfied in practice, which severely hinders its applicability (this point is further elaborated in Section Relationship with other quantitative theories of emergence).
Inspired by Refs. [6, 7], here we introduce a practically useful and philosophically innocent framework to study causal emergence in multivariate data. Building on previous work [11], we take the perspective of an experimentalist who has no prior knowledge of the underlying phenomenon of interest, but has sufficient data of all relevant variables that allows an accurate statistical description of the phenomenon. In this context, we put forward a formal definition of causal emergence that doesn’t rely on coarse-graining functions as Ref. [7], but addresses the “paradoxical” properties of strong emergence based on the laws of information flow in multivariate systems.
The main contribution of this work is to enable a rigorous, quantitative definition of downward causation, and introduce a novel notion of causal decoupling as a complementary modality of causal emergence. Another contribution is to extend the domain of applicability of causal emergence analyses to include cases of observational data, in which case causality ought to be understood in the Granger sense, i.e. as predictive ability [12]. Furthermore, our framework yields practical criteria that can be effectively applied to large systems, bypassing prohibitive estimation issues that severely restrict previous approaches.
The rest of this paper is structured as follows. First, Section Fundamental intuitions discusses minimal examples of emergence. Then, Section A formal theory of causal emergence presents the core of our theory, and Section Measuring emergence discusses practical methods to quantify emergence from experimental data. Our framework is then illustrated on a number of case studies, presented in Section Case studies. Finally, the Section Discussion concludes the paper with a discussion of some of the implications of our findings.
Fundamental intuitions
To ground our intuitions, let us introduce minimal examples that embody a few key notions of causally emergent behaviour. Throughout this section, we consider systems composed of n parts described by a binary vector , which undergo Markovian stochastic dynamics following a transition probability . For simplicity, we assume that at time t the system is found in an entirely random configuration (i.e. ). From there, we consider three evolution rules.
Example 1. Consider a temporal evolution where the parity of Xt is preserved with probability γ ∈ (0, 1). Mathematically,
for all , where if is even and zero otherwise. Put simply: xt+1 is a random sample from the set of all strings with the same parity as xt with probability γ; and is a sample from the strings with opposite parity with probability 1 − γ.
This evolution rule has a number of interesting properties. First, the system has a non-trivial causal structure, since some properties of the future state (its parity) can be predicted from the past state. However, this structure is noticeable only at the collective level, as no individual variable has any predictive power over the evolution of itself or any other variable (see Fig 1). Furthermore, even the complete past of the system Xt has no predictive power over any individual future . This case shows an extreme kind of causal emergence that we call “causal decoupling,” in which the parity predicts its own evolution but no element (or subset of elements) predicts the evolution of any other element.
Example 2. Consider now a system where the parity of Xt determines (i.e. ), and for j ≠ 1 is a fair coin flip independent of Xt (see Fig 1). In this scenario Xt predicts with perfect accuracy, while it can be verified that for all i ∈ {1, …, n}. Therefore, under this evolution rule the whole system has a causal effect over a particular element, although this effect cannot be attributed to any individual part (for a related discussion, see Ref. [13]), being a minimal example of downward causation.
Example 3. Let us now study an evolution rule that includes the mechanisms of both Examples 1 and 2. Concretely, consider
As in Example 1, the parity of Xt is transfered to Xt+1 with probability γ; additionally, it is guaranteed that . Hence, in this case not only is there a macroscopic effect that cannot be explained from the parts, but at the same time there is another effect going from the whole to one of the parts. Importantly, both effects co-exist independently of each other.
The above are minimal examples of dynamical laws that cannot be traced from the interactions between their elementary components: Example 1 shows how a collective property can propagate without interacting with its underlying substrate; Example 2 how a collective property can influence the evolution of specific parts; and Example 3 how these two kinds of phenomena take place in the same system. All these issues are formalised by the theory developed in the next section.
A formal theory of causal emergence
This section presents the main body of our theory of causal emergence. To fix ideas, we consider a scientist measuring a system composed of n parts. The scientist is assumed to measure the system regularly over time, and the results of those measurements are denoted by , with corresponding to the state of the ith part at time with phase space . When referring to a collection of parts, we use the notation for α = {i1, …, iK}⊂{1, …, n}. We also use the shorthand notation [n] ≔ {1, …, n}.
Supervenience
Our analysis considers two time points of the evolution of the system, denoted as t and t′, with t < t′. The corresponding dynamics are encoded in the transition probability . We consider features generated via a conditional probability that are supervenient on the underlying system; i.e. that does not provide any predictive power for future states at times t′ > t if the complete state of the system at time t is known with perfect precision. We formalise this in the following definition.
Definition 1. A stochastic process Vt is said to be supervenient over Xt if Vt − Xt − Xt′′ form a Markov chain for all t′′ ≠ t.
The above condition is equivalent to require Vt to be statistically independent of Xt′′ when Xt is given. The relationship between supervenient features and the underlying system is illustrated in Fig 2.
This formalisation of supervenience characterises features Vt that are fully determined by the state of the system at a given time t, but also allows the feature to be noisy—which is not critical for our results, but is useful for extending their domain of applicability to practical scenarios. In effect, Definition 1 includes as particular cases deterministic functions such that Vt = F(Xt), as well as features calculated under observational noise—e.g. Vt = F(Xt) + νt, where νt is independent of Xt for all t. In contrast, features that are computed using the values of Xt at multiple timepoints (e.g. the Fourier transform of Xt) generally fail to be supervenient.
Partial information decomposition
Our theory is based on the Partial Information Decomposition (PID) framework [14], which provides powerful tools to reason about information in multivariate systems. In a nutshell, PID decomposes the information that n sources X = (X1, …, Xn) provide about a target variable Y in terms of information atoms as follows:
(1) |
with being the set of antichain collections [14]. Intuitively, for α = {α1, …, αL} represents the information that the collection of variables provide redundantly, but their sub-collections don’t. For example, for n = 2 source variables, α = {{1}{2}} corresponds to the information about Y that is provided by both of them, α = {{i}} to the information provided uniquely by Xi, and, most interestingly, α = {{12}} corresponds to the information provided by both sources jointly but not separately—commonly referred to as informational synergy.
One of the drawbacks of PID is that the number of atoms (i.e. the cardinality of ) grows super-exponentially with the number of sources, and hence it is useful to coarse-grain the decomposition according to specific criteria. Here we introduce the notion of kth-order synergy between n variables, which is calculated as
with . Intuitively,
Syn
(k)(X;Y) corresponds to the information about the target that is provided by the whole X but is not contained in any set of k or less parts when considered separately from the rest. Accordingly, only contains collections with groups of more than k sources.
Similarly, we introduce the unique information of Xβ with β ⊂ [n] with respect to sets of at most k other variables, which is calculated as
Above, , and X−β being all the variables in X whose indices are not in β. Put simply, represents the information carried by Xβ about Y that no group of k or less variables within X−β has on its own. Note that these coarse-grained terms can be used to build a general decomposition of I(X, Y) described in S1 Appendix (Section 1), the properties of which are proven in S1 Appendix (Section 2).
One peculiarity of PID is that it postulates the structure of information atoms and the relations between them, but it does not prescribe a particular functional form to compute . In fact, only one of the information atoms must be specified to determine the whole PID—usually the redundancy between all individual elements [14]. There have been multiple proposals for specific functional forms of in the PID literature; see e.g. Refs. [15–18]. A particular method for fully computing the information atoms based on a recent PID [19] is discussed in Section Measuring emergence via synergistic channels.
Conveniently, our theory doesn’t rely on a specific functional form of PID, but only on a few basic properties that are precisely formulated in S1 Appendix (Section 2). Therefore, the theory can be instantiated using any PID—as long as those properties are satisfied. Importantly, as shown in Section Practical criteria for large systems, the theory allows the derivation of practical metrics that are valid independently of the PID chosen.
Defining causal emergence
With the tools of PID at hand, now we introduce our formal definition of causal emergence.
Definition 2. For a system described by Xt, a supervenient feature Vt is said to exhibit causal emergence of order k if
(2) |
Accordingly, causal emergence takes place when a supervenient feature Vt has irreducible causal power, i.e. when it exerts causal influence that is not mediated by any of the parts of the system. In other words, Vt represents some emergent collective property of the system if: 1) contains information that is dynamically relevant (in the sense that it predicts the future evolution of the system); and 2) this information is beyond what is given by the groups of k parts in the system when considered separately.
To better understand the implications of this definition, let us study some of its basic properties.
Lemma 1. Consider a feature Vt that exhibits causal emergence of order 1 over Xt. Then,
The dimensionality of the system satisfies n ≥ 2.
There exists no deterministic function g(⋅) such that for any j = 1, …, n.
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 3.
These two properties establish causal emergence as a fundamentally collective phenomenon. In effect, property (i) states that causal emergence is a property of multivariate systems, and property (ii) that Vt cannot have emergent behaviour if it can be perfectly predicted from a single variable.
In order to use Definition 2, one needs a candidate feature Vt to be tested. However, in some cases there are no obvious candidates for an emergent feature, for which Definition 2 might seem problematic. Our next result provides a criterion for the existence of emergent features based solely on the system’s dynamics.
Theorem 1. A system Xt has a causally emergent feature of order k if and only if
(3) |
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 2.
Corollary 1. The following bound holds for any supervenient feature Vt: .
This result shows that the capability of exhibiting emergence is closely related to how synergistic the system components are with respect to their future evolution. Importantly, this result enables us to determine whether or not the system admits any emergent features by just inspecting the synergy between its parts—without knowing what those features might be. Conversely, this result also allows us to discard the existence of causal emergence by checking a single condition: the lack of dynamical synergy. Furthermore, Corollary 1 implies that the quantity serves as a measure of the emergence capacity of the system, as it upper-bounds the unique information of all possible supervenient features.
Theorem 1 establishes a direct link between causal emergence and the system’s statistics, avoiding the need for the observer to propose a particular feature of interest. It is important to remark that the emergence capacity of a system depends on the system’s partition into microscopic elements—in fact, it is plausible that a system might have emergence capacity under one microscopic representation, but not with respect to another after a change of variables. Therefore, emergence in the context of our theory always refers to “emergence with respect to a given microscopic partition.”
A taxonomy of emergence
Our theory, so far, is able to detect whether there is emergence taking place; the next step is to be able to characterise which kind of emergence it is. For this purpose, we combine our feature-agnostic criterion of emergence presented in Theorem 1 with Integrated Information Decomposition, ΦID, a recent extension of PID to multi-target settings [20].
Using ΦID, one can decompose a PID atom as
(4) |
For example, if n = 2 then represents the information shared by both time series at both timesteps (for example, when are all copies of each other); and corresponds to the synergistic causes in Xt that have a unique effect on (for example, when ). More details and intuitions on ΦID can be found in Ref. [20].
With the fine-grained decomposition provided by ΦID one can discriminate between different kinds of synergies. In particular, we introduce the downward causation and causal decoupling indices of order k, denoted by and respectively, as
(5) |
(6) |
From these definitions and Eq (4), one can verify that
(7) |
Therefore, the emergence capacity of a system naturally decomposes in two different components: information about k-plets of future variables, and information about future collective properties beyond k-plets. The ΦID atoms that belong to these two terms are illustrated within the ΦID lattice for two time series in Fig 3. The rest of this section shows that and are natural metrics of downward causation and causal decoupling, respectively.
Downward causation
Intuitively, downward causation occurs when collective properties have irreducible causal power over individual parts. More formally:
Definition 3. A supervenient feature Vt exhibits downward causation of order k if, for some α with |α| = k:
(8) |
Note that, in contrast with Definition 2, downward causation requires the feature Vt to have unique predictive power over the evolution of specific subsets of the whole system. In particular, an emergent feature Vt that has predictive power over e.g. is said to exert downward causation, as it predicts something about that could not be predicted from any particular for i ∈ [n]. Put differently, in a system with downward causation the whole has an effect on the parts that cannot be reduced to low-level interactions. A minimal case of this is provided by Example 2 in Section Fundamental intuitions.
Our next result formally relates downward causation with the index introduced in Eq (5).
Theorem 2. A system Xt admits features that exert downward causation of order k iff .
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 3.
Causal decoupling
In addition to downward causation, causal decoupling takes place when collective properties have irreducible causal power over other collective properties. In technical terms:
Definition 4. A supervenient feature Vt is said to exhibit causal decoupling of order k if
(9) |
Furthermore, Vt is said to have pure causal decoupling if and for all α ⊂ [n] with |α| = k. Finally, a system is said to be perfectly decoupled if all the emergent features exhibit pure causal decoupling.
Above, the term refers to information that Vt and Vt′ share that cannot be found in any microscopic element, either at time t or t′ (note that is information shared between Vt and Vt′ that no combination of k or less variables from Xt or Xt′ has in its own).
Features that exhibit causal decoupling could still exert influence over the evolution of individual elements, while features that exhibit pure decoupling cannot. In effect, the condition implies that the high-order causal effect does not affect any particular part – only the system as a whole. Interestingly, a feature that exhibits pure causal decoupling can be thought of as having “a life of its own;” a sort of statistical ghost, that perpetuates itself over time without any individual part of the system influencing or being influenced by it. The system’s parity, in the first example of Section Fundamental intuitions, constitutes a simple example of perfect causal decoupling. Importantly, the case studies presented in Section Case studies show that causal decoupling can take place not only in toy models but also in diverse scenarios of practical relevance.
We close this section by formally establishing the connection between causal decoupling and the index introduced in Eq (6).
Theorem 3. A system possesses features that exhibit causal decoupling if and only if . Additionally, the system is perfectly decoupled if and .
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 3.
Measuring emergence
This section explores methods to operationalise the framework presented in the previous section. We discuss two approaches: first, Section Practical criteria for large systems introduces sufficiency criteria that are practical for use in large systems; then, Section Measuring emergence via synergistic channels illustrates how further considerations can be made if one adopts a specific method of computing ΦID atoms. The latter approach provides accurate discrimination at the cost of being data-intensive and hence only applicable to small systems; the former can be computed in large systems and its results hold independently of the chosen PID, but is vulnerable to misdetections (i.e. false negatives).
Practical criteria for large systems
While theoretically appealing, our proposed framework suffers from the challenge of estimating joint probability distributions over many random variables, and the computation of the ΦID atoms themselves. As an alternative, we consider approximation techniques that do not require the adoption of any particular PID or ΦID function and are data-efficient, since they are based on pairwise distributions only.
As practical criteria to measure causal emergence of order k, we introduce the quantities , , and . For simplicity, we write here the special case k = 1, and provide full formulae for arbitrary k and accompanying proofs in S1 Appendix, Section 4:
(10a) |
(10b) |
(10c) |
Our next result links these quantities with the formal definitions in Section A formal theory of causal emergence, showing their value as practical criteria to detect causal emergence.
Proposition 1. is a sufficient condition for Vt to be causally emergent. Similarly, is a sufficient condition for Vt to exhibit downward causation. Finally, and is sufficient for causal decoupling.
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 4.
Although calculating whether a system has emergent features via Proposition 1 may be computationally challenging, if one has a candidate feature V one believes may be emergent, one can compute the simple quantities in Eq (10) which depend only on standard mutual information and bivariate marginals, and scales linearly with system size (for k = 1). These quantities are easy to compute and test for significance using standard information-theoretic tools [21, 22]. Moreover, the outcome of these measures is valid for any choice of PID and ΦID that is compatible with the properties specified in S1 Appendix, Section 2.
In a broader context, and belong to the same whole-minus-sum family of measures as the interaction information [14, 23], the redundancy-synergy index [24] and, more recently, the O-information Ω [25]—which cannot measure synergy by itself, but only the balance between synergy and redundancy. In practice, this means that if there is redundancy in the system it will be harder to detect emergence, since redundancy will drive and more negative. Furthermore, by summing all marginal mutual informations (e.g. in the case of ), these measures effectively double-count redundancy up to n times, further penalising the criteria. This problem of double-counting can be avoided if one is willing to commit to a particular PID or ΦID function, as we show next.
It is worth noticing that the value of k can be tuned to explore emergence with respect to different “scales.” For example, k = 1 corresponds to emergence with respect to individual microscopic elements, while k = 2 refers to emergence with respect to all couples—i.e. individual elements and their pairwise interactions. Accordingly, the criteria in Proposition 1 are, in general, harder to satisfy for larger values of k. In addition, from a practical perspective, considering large values of k requires estimating information-theoretic quantities in high-dimensional distributions, which usually requires exponentially larger amounts of data.
Measuring emergence via synergistic channels
This section leverages recent work on information decomposition reported in Ref. [19], and presents a way of directly measuring the emergence capacity and the indices of downward causation and causal decoupling. The key takeaway of this section is that if one adopts a particular ΦID, then it is possible to evaluate and directly, providing a direct route to detect emergence without double-counting redundancy, as the methods introduced in Section Practical criteria for large systems do. Moreover, additional properties may become available due to the characteristics of the particular ΦID chosen.
Let us first introduce the notion of k-synergistic channels: mappings pV|X that convey information about X but not about any of the parts Xα for all |α| = k. The set of all k-synergistic channels is denoted by
(11) |
A variable V generated via a k-synergistic channel is said to be a k-synergistic observable.
With this definition, we can consider the kth-order synergy to be the maximum information extractable from a k-synergistic channel:
(12) |
This idea can be naturally extended to the case of causal decoupling by requiring synergistic channels at both sides, i.e.
(13) |
Finally, the downward causation index can be computed from the difference
(14) |
Note that , which is a direct consequence of the data processing inequality applied on V − Xt − Xt′ − U, and therefore .
By exploiting the properties of this specific way of measuring synergy, one can prove the following result. For this, let us say that a feature Vt is auto-correlated if I(Vt;Vt′)>0.
Proposition 2. If Xt is stationary, all auto-correlated k-synergistic observables are kth-order emergent.
Proof. See S1 Appendix, Section 4.
In summary, and provide data-driven tools to test—and possibly reject—hypotheses about emergence in scenarios of interest. Efficient algorithms to compute these quantities are discussed in Ref. [26]. Although current implementations allow only relatively small systems, this line of thinking shows that future advances in PID might make the computation of emergence indices more scalable, avoiding the limitations of Eq (10).
Case studies
Let us summarise our results so far. We began by formulating a rigorous definition of emergent features based on PID (Section Defining causal emergence), and then used ΦID to break down the emergence capacity into the causal decoupling and downward causation indices (Section A taxonomy of emergence). Although these are not straightforward to compute, the ΦID framework allows us to formulate readily computable sufficiency conditions (Section Practical criteria for large systems). This section illustrates the usage of those conditions in various case studies. Code to compute all emergence criteria in Eq (10) is provided in an online open-source repository (https://github.com/pmediano/ReconcilingEmergences).
Canonical examples of putative emergence
Here we present an evaluation of our practical criteria for emergence (Proposition 1) in two well-known systems: Conway’s Game of Life (GoL) [27], and Reynolds’ flocking boids model [28]. Both are widely regarded as paradigmatic examples of emergent behaviour, and have been thoughtfully studied in the complexity and artificial life literature [29]. Accordingly, we use these models as test cases for our methods. Technical details of the simulations are provided in S1 Appendix, Section 5.
Conway’s Game of Life
A well-known feature of GoL is the presence of particles: coherent, self-sustaining structures known to be responsible for information transfer and modification [30]. These particles have been the object of extensive study, and detailed taxonomies and classifications exist [29, 31].
To test the emergent properties of particles, we simulate the evolution of 15x15 square cell arrays, which we regard as a binary vector Xt ∈ {0, 1}n with n = 225. As initial condition, we consider configurations that correspond to a “particle collider” setting, with two particles of known type facing each other (Fig 4). In each trial, the system is randomised by changing the position, type, and relative displacement of the particles. After an intial configuration has been selected, the well-known GoL evolution rule [27] is applied 1000 times, leading to a final state Xt′. Simulations showed that this interval is enough for the system to settle in a stable state after the collision.
To use the criteria from Eq 10, we need to choose a candidate emergent feature Vt. In this case, we consider a symbolic, discrete-valued vector that encodes the type of particle(s) present in the board. Specifically, we consider , where iff there is a particle of type j at time t—regardless of its position or orientation.
With these variables, we compute the quantities in Eq 10 using Bayesian estimators of mutual information [32]. The result is that, as expected, the criterion for causal emergence is met with . Furthermore, we found that , which is orders of magnitude smaller than I(Vt;Vt′) = 0.99±0.02. Errors represent the standard deviation over surrogate data, as described in S1 Appendix, Section 5. Using Proposition 1, these two results suggest that particle dynamics in GoL may not only be emergent, but causally decoupled with respect to their substrate.
Reynolds’ flocking model
As a second test case, we consider Reynolds’ model of flocking behaviour. This model is composed by boids (bird-oid objects), with each boid represented by three numbers: its position in 2D space and its heading angle. As candidate feature for emergence, we use the 2D coordinates of the center of mass of the flock, following Seth [6].
In this model boids interact with one another following three rules, each regulated by a scalar parameter [6]:
aggregation (a1), as they fly towards the center of the flock;
avoidance (a2), as they fly away from their closest neighbour; and
alignment (a3), as they align their flight direction to that of their neighbours.
Following Ref. [6], we study small flocks of N = 10 boids with different parameter settings to showcase some properties of our practical criterion of emergence. Note that this study is meant as an illustration of the proposed theory, and not as a thorough exploration of the flocking model, for which a vast literature exists (see e.g. the work of Vicsek [33] and references therein).
Fig 5 shows the results of a parameter sweep over the avoidance parameter, a2, while keeping a1 and a3 fixed. When there is no avoidance, boids orbit around a slowly-moving center of mass, in what could be called an ordered regime. Conversely, for high values of a2 neighbour repulsion is too strong for lasting flocks to form, and isolated boids spread across the space avoiding one another. For intermediate values, the center of mass traces a smooth trajectory, as flocks form and disintegrate. In line with the findings of Seth [6], our criterion indicates that the flock exhibits causally emergent behaviour in this intermediate range.
By studying separately the two terms that make up Ψ we found that the criterion of emergence fails for both low and high a2, but for different reasons (see Fig 5). In effect, for high a2 the self-predictability of the center of mass (i.e. I(Vt;Vt′)) is low; while for low a2 it is high, yet lower than the mutual information from individual boids (i.e. ). These results suggest that the low-avoidance scenario is dominated not by a reduction in synergy, but by an increase in redundancy, which effectively increases the synergy threshold needed to detect emergence. However, note that, due to the limitations of the criterion, the fact that is inconclusive and does not rule out the possibility of emergence. This is a common limitation of whole-minus-sum estimators like Ψ; further refinements may provide bounds that are less susceptible to these issues and perform accurately in these scenarios.
Mind from matter: Emergence, behaviour, and neural dynamics
A tantalising outcome of having a formal theory of emergence is the capability of bringing a quantitative angle to the archetype of emergence: the mind-matter relationship [35, 36]. As a first step in this direction, we conclude this section with an application of our emergence criteria to neurophysiological data.
We study simultaneous electrocorticogram (ECoG) and motion capture (MoCap) data of Japanese macaques performing a reaching task [34], obtained from the online Neurotycho database. Note that the MoCap data cannot be assumed to be a supervenient feature of the available ECoG data, since it doesn’t satisfy the conditional independence conditions required by our definition of supervenience (see Section A formal theory of causal emergence). This is likely to be the case, because the neural system is only partially observed—i.e. the ECoG does not capture every source of relevant activity in the macaque’s cortex. Note that non-supervenient features are of limited interest within our framework, as they can satisfy Proposition 1 in trivial ways (e.g. time series which are independent of the underlying system satisty Ψ > 0 if they are auto-correlated). Instead, we focus on the portion of neural activity encoded in the ECoG signal that is relevant to predict the macaque’s behaviour, and conjecture this information to be an emergent feature of the underlying neural activity (Fig 6).
To test this hypothesis, we take the neural activity (as measured by 64 ECoG channels distributed across the left hemisphere) to be the system of interest, and consider a memoryless predictor of the 3D coordinates of the macaque’s right wrist based on the ECoG signal. Therefore, in this scenario and . To build Vt, we used Partial Least Squares (PLS) and a Support Vector Machine (SVM) regressor, the details of which can be found in S1 Appendix, Section 6.
After training the decoder and evaluating on a held-out test set, results show that Ψ > 0, confirming our conjecture that the motor-related information is an emergent feature of the macaque’s cortical activity. For short timescales (t′ − t = 8 ms), we find , which is orders of magnitude smaller than , suggesting that the behaviour may have an important component decoupled from individual ECoG channels (errors are standard deviations estimated over time-shuffled data). Furthermore, the emergence criterion is met for multiple timescales t′ − t of up to ≈0.2s, beyond which the predictive power in Vt and individual electrodes decrease and become nearly identical.
As a control, we performed a surrogate data test to confirm the results in Fig 6 were not driven by the autocorrelation in the ECoG time series. To this end, we re-run the analysis (including training and testing the PLS-SVM) using the same ECoG data, but time-shuffling the wrist position—resulting in a Vt that does not extract any meaningful information from the ECoG, but has the same properties induced by autocorrelation, filtering and regularisation. As expected, the resulting surrogate is significantly lower than the one using the un-shuffled wrist position, confirming the measured is positive and higher than what would be expected from a similar, random projection of the ECoG (details in S1 Appendix, Section 6).
This analysis, while just a proof of concept, helps us quantify how and to what extent behaviour emerges from collective neural activity; and opens the door to further tests and quantitative empirical explorations of the mind-matter relationship.
Discussion
A large fraction of the modern scientific literature considers strong emergence to be impossible or ill-defined. This judgement is not fully unfounded: a property that is simultaneously supervenient (i.e. that can be computed from the state of the system) and that has irreducible causal power (i.e. that “tells us something” that the parts don’t) can indeed seem to be an oxymoron [5]. Nonetheless, by linking supervenience to static relationships and causal power to dynamical properties, our framework shows that these two phenomena are perfectly compatible within the—admittedly counterintuitive – laws of multivariate information dynamics [20], providing a tentative solution to this paradox.
Our theory of causal emergence is about predictive power, not “explicability” [3], and therefore is not related to views on strong emergence such as Chalmers’ [3]. Nevertheless, our framework embraces aspects that are commonly associated with strong emergence—such as downward causation—and renders them quantifiable. Our framework also does not satisfy conventional definitions of weak emergence (systems studied in Section Fundamental intuitions are not weakly emergent in the sense of Bedau [5], being simple and susceptible to explanatory shortcuts) but is compatible with more general notions of weak emergence, e.g. the one introduced by Seth (see Section Relationship with other quantitative theories of emergence). Hence, our theory can be seen as an attempt at reconciling these approaches [36], showing how “strong” a “weak” framework can be.
An important consequence of our theory is the fundamental connection established between causal emergence and statistical synergy: the system’s capacity to host emergent features was found to be determined by how synergistic its elements are with respect to their future evolution. Although previous ideas about synergy have been loosely linked to emergence in the past [37], this is (to the best of our knowledge) the first time such ideas have been formally laid out and quantified using recent advances in multivariate information theory.
Next, we examine a few caveats regarding the applicability of the proposed theory, its relation with prior work, and some open problems.
Scope of the theory
Our theory focuses on synchronic [38] aspects of emergence, analysing the interactions between the elements of dynamical systems and collective properties of them as they jointly evolve over time. As such, our theory directly applies to any system with well-defined dynamics, including systems described by deterministic dynamical systems with random initial conditions [11] and stochastic systems described by Fokker-Planck equations [39]. In contrast, the application of our theory to systems in thermodynamic equilibrium may not be straightforward, as their dynamics are often not uniquely specified by the corresponding Gibbs distributions (for an explicit example, when considering the Ising model, Kawasaki and Glauber dynamics are known to behave differently even when the system is in equilibrium [40]; and thus may provide quite different values of the measures described in Section Measuring emergence). Finding principled approaches to guide the application of our theory to those cases is an interesting challenge for future studies.
In addition, given the breadth of the concept of “emergence,” there are a number of other theories leaning more towards philosophy that are orthogonal to our framework. This includes, for example, theories of emergence as radical novelty (in the sense of features not previously observed in the system) [41], most prominently encapsulated in the aphorism “more is different” by Anderson—see Refs. [42, 43], particularly his approach to emergence in biology (note that some of Anderson’s views, particularly the ones related to rigidity, are nevertheless closely related to the approach developed by our framework), and also articulated in the work of Kauffman [44, 45]. Also, contextual emergence emphasises a role for macro-level contexts that cannot be described at the micro-level, but which impose constraints on the micro-level for the emergence of the macro [46, 47]. These are valuable philosophical positions, which have been studied from a statistical mechanics perspective in Ref. [46, 48]. Future work shall attempt to unify these other approaches with our proposed framework.
Causality
The de facto way to assess the causal structure of a system is to analyse its response to controlled interventions or to build intervention models (causal graphs) based on expert knowledge, which leads to the well-known do-calculus spearheaded by Judea Pearl [10]. This approach is, unfortunately, not applicable in many scenarios of interest, as interventions may incur prohibitive costs or even be impossible, and expert knowledge may not be available. These scenarios can still be assessed via the Wiener-Granger theory of statistical causation, which studies the blueprint of predictive power across the system of interest by accounting non-mediated correlations between past and future events [12]. Both frameworks provide similar results when all the relevant variables have been measured, but can neverthelss differ radically when there are unobserved interacting variables [10]. The debate between the Wiener-Granger and the Pearl schools has been discussed in other related contexts—see e.g. Refs. [49, 50] for a discussion regarding Integrated Information Theory (IIT), and Ref. [51] for a discussion about effective and functional connectivity in the context of neuroimaging time series analysis (in a nutshell, effective connectivity aims to uncover the minimal physical causal mechanism underlying the observed data, while functional connectivity describes directed or undirected statistical dependences [51]).
In our theory, the main object of analysis is Shannon’s mutual information, I(Xt;Xt′), which depends on the joint probability distribution . The origin of this distribution (whether it was obtained by passive observation or by active intervention) will change the interpretation of the quantities presented above, and will speak differently to the Pearl and the Wiener-Granger schools of thought; some of the implications of these differences are addressed when discussing Ref. [7] below. Nonetheless, since both methods of obtaining allow synergy to take place, our results are in principle applicable in both frameworks—which allows us to formulate our theory of causal emergence without taking a rigid stance on a theory of causality itself.
Relationship with other quantitative theories of emergence
This work is part of a broader movement towards formalising theories of complexity through information theory. In particular, our framework is most directly inspired by the work of Seth [6] and Hoel et al. [7], and also related to recent work by Chang et al. [52]. This section gives a brief account of these theories, and discusses how they differ from our proposal.
Seth [6] proposes that a process Vt is Granger-emergent (or G-emergent) with respect to Xt if two conditions are met: (i) Vt is autonomous with respect to Xt (i.e. I(Vt;Vt′|Xt)>0), and (ii) Vt is G-caused by Xt (i.e. I(Xt;Vt′|Vt)>0). The latter condition is employed to guarantee a relationship between Xt and Vt; in our framework an equivalent role is taken by the requirement of supervenience. The condition of autonomy is certainly related with our notion of causal decoupling. However, as shown in Ref. [14], the conditional mutual information conflates unique and synergistic information, which can give rise to undesirable situations: for example, it could be that I(Vt;Vt′|Xt)>0 while, at the same time, I(V;Vt′) = 0, meaning that the dynamics of the feature Vt are only visible when considering it together with the full system Xt, but not on its own. Our framework avoids this problem by refining this criterion via PID, and uses only the unique information for the definition of emergence.
Our work is also strongly influenced by the framework put forward by Hoel and colleagues in Ref. [7]. Their approach is based on a coarse-graining function F(⋅) relating a feature of interest to the system, Vt = F(Xt), which is a particular case of our more general definition of supervenience. Emergence is declared when the dependency between Vt and Vt′ is “stronger” than the one between Xt and Xt′. Note that Vt − Xt − Xt′ − Vt′ is a Markov chain, and hence I(Vt;Vt′)≤I(Xt;Xt′) due to the data processing inequality; therefore, a direct usage of Shannon’s mutual information would make the above criterion impossible to fulfill. Instead, this framework focuses on the transition probabilities and , and hence the mutual information terms are computed using maximum entropy distributions instead of the stationary marginals. By doing this, Hoel et al. account not for what the system actually does, but for all the potential transitions the system could do. However, in our view this approach is not well-suited to assess dynamical systems, as it might account for transitions that are never actually explored. The difference between stationary and maximum entropy distributions can be particularly dramatic in non-ergodic systems with multiple attractors—for a related discussion in the context of Integrated Information Theory, see Ref. [50]. Additionally, this framework relies on having exact knowledge about the microscopic transitions as encoded by , which is not possible to obtain in most applications.
Finally, Chang et al. [4] consider supervenient variables that are “non-trivially informationally closed” (NTIC) to their corresponding microscopic substrate. NTIC is based on a division of Xt into a subsystem of interest, , and its “environment” given by . Interestingly, a system being NTIC requires Vt to be supervenient only with respect to (i.e. ), as well as information flow from the environment to the feature (i.e. ) mediated by the feature itself, so that Xt − Vt − Vt′ is a Markov chain. Hence, NTIC requires features that are sufficient statistics for their own dynamics, which is akin to our concept of causal decoupling but focused on the interaction between a macroscopic feature, an agent, and its environment. Extending our framework to agent-environment systems involved in active inference is part of our future work.
Limitations and open problems
The framework presented in this paper focuses on features from fully observable systems with Markovian dynamics. These assumptions, however, often do not hold when dealing with experimental data—especially in biological and social systems. As an important extension, future work should investigate the effect of unobserved variables on our measures. This could be done, for example, leveraging Takens’ embedding theorem [53–55] or other methods [56].
An interesting feature of our framework is that, although it depends on the choice of PID and ΦID, its practical application via the criteria discussed in Section Practical criteria for large systems is agnostic to those choices. However, they incur the cost of a limited sensitivity to detect emergence due to an overestimation of the microscopic redundancy; so they can detect emergence when it is substantial, but might miss it in more subtle cases. Additionally, these criteria are unable to rule out emergence, as they are sufficient but not necessary conditions. Therefore, another avenue of future work should search for improved practical criteria for detecting emergence from data. One interesting line of research is providing scalable approximations for and as introduced in Section Measuring emergence via synergistic channels, which could be computed in large systems.
Another open question is how the emergence capacity is affected by changes in the microscopic partition of the system (c.f. Section Defining causal emergence). Interesting applications of this includes scenarios where elements of interest have been subject to a mixing process, such as the case of electroencephalography where each electrode detects a mixture of brain sources. Other interesting questions include studying systems with non-zero emergence capacity for all reasonable microscopic partitions, which may correspond to a stronger type of emergence.
Conclusion
This paper introduces a quantitative definition of causal emergence, which addresses the apparent paradox of supervenient macroscopic features with irreducible causal power using principles of multivariate statistics. We provide a formal, quantitative theory that embodies many of the principles attributed to strong emergence, while being measurable and compatible with the established scientific worldview. Perhaps the most important contribution of this work is to bring the discussion of emergence closer to the realm of quantitative, empirical scientific investigation, complementing the ongoing philosophical inquiries on the subject.
Mathematically, the theory is based on the Partial Information Decomposition (PID) framework [14], and on a recent extension, Integrated Information Decomposition (ΦID) [20]. The theory allows the derivation of sufficiency criteria for the detection of emergence that are scalable, easy to compute from data, and based only on Shannon’s mutual information. We illustrated the use of these practical criteria in three case studies, and concluded that: i) particle collisions are an emergent feature in Conway’s Game of Life, ii) flock dynamics are an emergent feature of simulated birds; and iii) the representation of motor behaviour in the cortex is emergent from neural activity. Our theory, together with these practical criteria, enables novel data-driven tools for scientifically addressing conjectures about emergence in a wide range of systems of interest.
Our original aim in developing this theory, beyond the contribution to complexity theory, is to help bridge the gap between the mental and the physical, and ultimately understand how mind emerges from matter. This paper provides formal principles to explore the idea that psychological phenomena could emerge from collective neural patterns, and interact with each other dynamically in a causally decoupled fashion—perhaps akin to the “statistical ghosts” mentioned in Section Causal decoupling. Put simply: just as particles in the Game of Life have their own collision rules, we wonder if thought patterns could have their own emergent dynamical laws, operating at a larger scale with respect to their underlying neural substrate (similar ideas have been recently explored by Kent [57]). Importantly, the theory presented in this paper not only provides conceptual tools to frame this conjecture rigorously, but also provides practical tools to test it from data. The exploration of this conjecture is left as an exciting avenue for future research.
Supporting information
Acknowledgments
The authors thank Martin Biehl, Shamil Chandaria, Acer Chang, and Matthew Crosby for insightful discussions, the creators of the Neurotycho database for opening to the public such a valuable resource, and Yike Guo for supporting this research. F.R. is supported by the Ad Astra Chandaria foundation. P.M. and D.B. are funded by the Wellcome Trust (grant no. 210920/Z/18/Z). A.K.S. and A.B.B. are grateful to the Dr. Mortimer and Theresa Sackler Foundation, which supports the Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science. R.C-H. is supported by Ad Astra Trust, Tim Ferriss, The Nikean Foundation, and The Tamas Family.
Data Availability
All relevant data are within the manuscript and its Supporting information files.
Funding Statement
F.R. is supported by the Ad Astra Chandaria foundation. P.M. and D.B. are funded by the 887 Wellcome Trust (grant no. 210920/Z/18/Z). A.K.S. and A.B.B. are grateful to the Dr. Mortimer and Theresa Sackler Foundation, which supports the Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science. The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
References
- 1. Gibb S, Findlay RH, Lancaster T. The Routledge Handbook of Emergence. Routledge; 2019. [Google Scholar]
- 2. Bedau M. Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology. 2002;6(1):5–50. [Google Scholar]
- 3. Chalmers DJ. Strong and Weak Emergence. Oxford University Press; 2006. p. 244–256. [Google Scholar]
- 4.Chang AY, Biehl M, Yu Y, Kanai R. Information Closure Theory of Consciousness. arXiv preprint arXiv:190913045. 2019;. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- 5. Bedau MA. Weak emergence. Noûs. 1997;31:375–399. [Google Scholar]
- 6. Seth AK. Measuring autonomy and emergence via Granger causality. Artificial Life. 2010;16(2):179–196. 10.1162/artl.2010.16.2.16204 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7. Hoel EP, Albantakis L, Tononi G. Quantifying causal emergence shows that macro can beat micro. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2013;110(49):19790–19795. 10.1073/pnas.1314922110 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. Hoel EP. When the map is better than the territory. Entropy. 2017;19(5):188 10.3390/e19050188 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 9. Klein B, Hoel E. The emergence of informative higher scales in complex networks. Complexity. 2020;2020 10.1155/2020/8932526 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 10. Pearl J. Causality: Models, Reasoning and Inference. Cambridge University Press; 2000. [Google Scholar]
- 11. Rosas F, Mediano PAM, Ugarte M, Jensen HJ. An information-theoretic approach to self-organisation: Emergence of complex interdependencies in coupled dynamical systems. Entropy. 2018;20(10). 10.3390/e20100793 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12. Bressler SL, Seth AK. Wiener–Granger causality: A well established methodology. Neuroimage. 2011;58(2):323–329. 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2010.02.059 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.James RG, Ayala BDM, Zakirov B, Crutchfield JP. Modes of information flow. arXiv preprint arXiv:180806723. 2018;.
- 14.Williams PL, Beer RD. Nonnegative decomposition of multivariate information. arXiv preprint arXiv:10042515. 2010;.
- 15.Ay N, Polani D, Virgo N. Information decomposition based on cooperative game theory. arXiv preprint arXiv:191005979. 2019;.
- 16. Lizier JT, Bertschinger N, Jost J, Wibral M. Information decomposition of target effects from multi-source interactions: Perspectives on previous, current and future work. Entropy. 2018;20(4). 10.3390/e20040307 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17. James R, Emenheiser J, Crutchfield J. Unique information via dependency constraints. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical. 2018;. [Google Scholar]
- 18. Ince RA. Measuring multivariate redundant information with pointwise common change in surprisal. Entropy. 2017;19(7):318 10.3390/e19070318 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Rosas F, Mediano P, Rassouli B, Barrett A. An operational information decomposition via synergistic disclosure. arXiv preprint arXiv:200110387. 2020;.
- 20.Mediano PA, Rosas F, Carhart-Harris RL, Seth AK, Barrett AB. Beyond integrated information: A taxonomy of information dynamics phenomena. arXiv preprint arXiv:190902297. 2019;.
- 21. Kraskov A, Stögbauer H, Grassberger P. Estimating mutual information. Physical Review E. 2004;69(6):066138 10.1103/PhysRevE.69.066138 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22. Lizier JT. JIDT: An information-theoretic toolkit for studying the dynamics of complex systems. Frontiers in Robotics and AI. 2014;1:37 10.3389/frobt.2014.00011 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 23. McGill WJ. Multivariate information transmission. Psychometrika. 1954;19(2):97–116. 10.1007/BF02289159 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 24. Timme N, Alford W, Flecker B, Beggs JM. Synergy, redundancy, and multivariate information measures: An experimentalist’s perspective. Journal of Computational Neuroscience. 2014;36(2):119–140. 10.1007/s10827-013-0458-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25. Rosas FE, Mediano PAM, Gastpar M, Jensen HJ. Quantifying high-order interdependencies via multivariate extensions of the mutual information. Physical Review E. 2019;100:032305 10.1103/PhysRevE.100.032305 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26. Rassouli B, Rosas FE, Gündüz D. Data Disclosure under Perfect Sample Privacy IEEE Transactions on Information Forensics and Security. 2019;. [Google Scholar]
- 27. Conway J. The game of life. Scientific American. 1970;223(4):4. [Google Scholar]
- 28. Reynolds CW. Flocks, Herds and Schools: A Distributed Behavioral Model. vol. 21 ACM; 1987. [Google Scholar]
- 29. Adamatzky A, Durand-Lose J. Collision-based computing. Springer; 2012. [Google Scholar]
- 30. Lizier J. The local information dynamics of distributed computation in complex systems. University of Sydney; 2010. [Google Scholar]
- 31. Wolfram S. A new kind of science. Wolfram Media; 2002. [Google Scholar]
- 32. Archer E, Park I, Pillow J. Bayesian and quasi-Bayesian estimators for mutual information from discrete data. Entropy. 2013;15(5):1738–1755. 10.3390/e15051738 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Vicsek T. Universal patterns of collective motion from minimal models of flocking. In: 2008 IEEE Conference on Self-Adaptive and Self-Organizing Systems. IEEE; 2008. p. 3–11.
- 34. Chao Z, Nagasaka Y, Fujii N. Long-term asynchronous decoding of arm motion using electrocorticographic signals in monkey. Frontiers in Neuroengineering. 2010;3:3 10.3389/fneng.2010.00003 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35. Dehaene S. Consciousness and the brain: Deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. Penguin; 2014. [Google Scholar]
- 36. Turkheimer FE, Hellyer P, Kehagia AA, Expert P, Lord LD, Vohryzek J, et al. Conflicting emergences. Weak vs. strong emergence for the modelling of brain function. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews. 2019;99:3–10. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.01.023 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37. Corning PA. The synergism hypothesis: On the concept of synergy and its role in the evolution of complex systems. Journal of Social and Evolutionary Systems. 1998;21(2):133–172. 10.1016/S1061-7361(00)80003-X [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 38. Rueger A. Physical emergence, diachronic and synchronic. Synthese. 2000;124(3):297–322. 10.1023/A:1005249907425 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 39. Breuer HP, Petruccione F, et al. The Theory of Open Quantum Systems. Oxford University Press; 2002. [Google Scholar]
- 40. Smith TH, Vasilyev O, Abraham DB, Maciołek A, Schmidt M. Interfaces in confined Ising models: Kawasaki, Glauber and sheared dynamics. Journal of Physics: Condensed Matter. 2008;20(49):494237. [Google Scholar]
- 41. Corning PA. The re-emergence of “emergence”: A venerable concept in search of a theory. Complexity. 2002;7(6):18–30. 10.1002/cplx.10043 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 42. Anderson PW. More is different. Science. 1972;177(4047):393–396. 10.1126/science.177.4047.393 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43. Anderson PW. Basic notions of condensed matter physics. CRC Press; 2018. [Google Scholar]
- 44. Kauffman S, Clayton P. On emergence, agency, and organization. Biology and Philosophy. 2006;21(4):501–521. 10.1007/s10539-005-9003-9 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 45. Kauffman SA. A World Beyond Physics: The Emergence and Evolution of Life. Oxford University Press; 2019. [Google Scholar]
- 46. Bishop RC, Atmanspacher H. Contextual emergence in the description of properties. Foundations of Physics. 2006;36(12):1753–1777. 10.1007/s10701-006-9082-8 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 47. Atmanspacher H, beim Graben P. Contextual emergence. Scholarpedia. 2009;4(3):7997 10.4249/scholarpedia.7997 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48. Jensen HJ, Pazuki RH, Pruessner G, Tempesta P. Statistical mechanics of exploding phase spaces: Ontic open systems. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical. 2018;51(37):375002 10.1088/1751-8121/aad57b [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 49. Mediano PAM, Seth AK, Barrett AB. Measuring Integrated Information: Comparison of Candidate Measures in Theory and Simulation. Entropy. 2018;21(1). 10.3390/e21010017 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50. Barrett A, Mediano P. The Phi measure of integrated information is not well-defined for general physical systems. Journal of Consciousness Studies. 2019;26(1-2):11–20. [Google Scholar]
- 51. Seth AK, Barrett AB, Barnett L. Granger causality analysis in neuroscience and neuroimaging. Journal of Neuroscience. 2015;35(8):3293–3297. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4399-14.2015 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52. Chang AYC, Biehl M, Yu Y, Kanai R. Information closure theory of consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology. 2020;11:1504 10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01504 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53. Takens F. Detecting strange attractors in turbulence In: Dynamical Systems and Turbulence. Springer; 1981. p. 366–381. [Google Scholar]
- 54. Cliff OM, Prokopenko M, Fitch R. An information criterion for inferring coupling of distributed dynamical systems. Frontiers in Robotics and AI. 2016;3:71 10.3389/frobt.2016.00071 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 55. Tajima S, Kanai R. Integrated information and dimensionality in continuous attractor dynamics. Neuroscience of consciousness. 2017;2017(1):nix011 10.1093/nc/nix011 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56. Wilting J, Priesemann V. Inferring collective dynamical states from widely unobserved systems. Nature Communications. 2018;9(1):1–7. 10.1038/s41467-018-04725-4 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Kent A. Toy Models of Top Down Causation. arXiv preprint arXiv:190912739. 2019;.