Abstract
Children with severe intellectual disabilities face inequities in pain-related care, yet there is a relative lack of pain research in the population. A significant obstacle to pain research in this population is its ethical complexity. This article addresses ethical challenges to conducting pain research in children with severe intellectual disabilities. There are two central issues. First, some of the standard methods for assessing pain and pain sensitivity are not suitable for children (and adults) with severe ID, who are often non-verbal and unable to understand or follow directions. Second, children with severe ID cannot provide informed consent (or even assent) to participate in pain research, nor is it obvious that their dissent will be recognized as such. The International Association for the Study of Pain’s existing ethical guidelines for pain research provide helpful but only general guidance. Our article goes beyond those guidelines and uses a well-established framework for assessing the ethics of clinical research to highlight points relevant to designing, conducting, reviewing, or evaluating research involving children with severe ID, focusing on issues unaddressed in existing guidance.
Introduction
This viewpoint addresses ethical challenges to conducting pain research in children with severe intellectual disabilities. Following the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5) and the International Classification of Diseases, we understand “intellectual disability” (ID) as a set of disorders involving deficits in intellectual functions and adaptive functioning, with an onset during the developmental period, such that diagnosis and management during childhood is expected (1,2). ID is “severe” when conceptual development is limited and spoken language is either significantly limited or absent.i We focus on pain research involving children—since ID is identified and cared for in childhood—but our analysis is relevant for research involving individuals with ID across the lifespan.
Children with severe ID are disadvantaged: they are more likely to have limited movement or play abilities and have greater health needs and higher need for health-related services (3,4), making them particularly vulnerable to health disparities. While children with ID have more comorbidities and undergo medical interventions that can be painful as typically developing children do, they are seldom enrolled in clinical research. The resulting lack of population-specific knowledge could further contribute to health inequity in this vulnerable population (5). The experience of pain in children with severe ID is poorly understood. On the one hand, some conditions associated with severe ID are also associated with altered pain sensitivity, suggesting that children with these conditions may have increased pain tolerance (3,4). On the other, such children may be unable to communicate or self-report their pain, raising the possibility that their pain sensitivity is normal, but their expression of pain is atypical or unrecognized (6). Consider, for example, parents of children with Wilms tumor, aniridia, genitourinary (WAGR) Syndrome, who describe a child who does not react when he “got his toe caught in our gate and it ripped a big ½-inch gouge in it. It was bleeding heavily and the skin was just hanging off,” or a child who tried “to sit on a lunch table bench at school, missed, and hit her collar bone” ultimately breaking her clavicle “but since she hardly complained they let her finish out the day” (7,8). Further research is needed to understand whether such cases involve altered pain sensitivity or atypical pain expressions, or both.
An important obstacle to pain research in children with severe ID is its ethical complexity (5). Exploitation of individuals with ID is well-known in the history of clinical research misconduct. Examples like the Willowbrook State School for Children with Mental Retardation and the Jewish Chronic Disease Hospital make vivid the importance of taking extra ethical precaution when contemplating research with this vulnerable community (9,10). However, there is also a powerful ethical case for including those with severe ID in research, since systematic exclusion contributes to health inequities and effectively compounds their disadvantage by denying them access to potential benefits research might produce (5,11). Indeed, in the authors’ experience, parents and caretakers of children with severe ID are painfully aware of this inequity, understand this potential and advocate on behalf of their loved ones for this research.
Although the ethical imperative to involve individuals with severe ID in research to address the existing inequity in pain research is now better recognized (5,11–14), there are ethical challenges in its conduct. Standard experimental pain methods rely on subjects’ active participation and self-reports and so are not suitable for children with severe ID who are nonverbal or unable to understand or follow directions. Given the theoretical potential for pain research to cause unpleasant experiences, careful consideration must be given to the risks and potential benefits of developing and using alternative research methods. Further, children with severe ID cannot assent, and even their dissent may be difficult to decipher. Existing ethical guidelines for pain research from the International Association for the Study of Pain’s (IASP) are helpful but lack specific guidance for individuals with severe ID (15).
This article applies a well-established ethical framework for clinical research developed by Emanuel et al, which is a distillation of key research ethics guidelines worldwide (16,17). We present the resulting analysis in a way that is useful for those designing, conducting, reviewing, or evaluating much-needed pain research involving children with severe ID.
The Framework
Emanuel et al describes universally applicable principles grounded in widely-accepted bioethical values that synthesize guidance found in existing codes, regulations, and relevant research ethics literature. Ethical clinical research must reflect the following principles: collaborative partnership, social or scientific value, scientific validity, fair subject selection, favorable risk-benefit ratio, independent review, informed consent, and respect for subjects (see Table) (16,17). Our discussion focuses primarily on the ethical challenge generated by the possibility of altered pain sensitivity combined with the inability to communicate and self-report pain and the distinctive difficulties this raises for the development of alternative experimental methods appropriate for children with severe ID.
Table:
Specific considerations for pain research involving children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability
Explanation | Ethical challenges | Ethical imperatives | |
---|---|---|---|
| |||
Collaborative partnership | Protect vulnerable groups from exploitation and encourage trust in research by ensuring that group members contribute to identifying health needs and problems | Lessons learned from the history of research misconduct and exploitation of individuals with intellectual disability; individuals with severe intellectual disability are vulnerable, they are often non-verbal and therefore unable to participate in collaborative partnerships | Engaging people who have a detailed understanding of the health needs and problems of the vulnerable population (eg, parents, caretakers, health-care providers (eg, hospitals, clinics, and doctors), and support groups) who can advocate on behalf of individuals with severe intellectual disability |
Social or scientific value | Evaluation of a treatment, intervention, or theory that will improve health and wellbeing or increase knowledge | Individuals with severe intellectual disability encounter health inequities in both clinical research and care; improving understanding of their somatosensory function and pain experience might help prevent delayed diagnosis and pain undertreatment; genetic conditions associated with severe intellectual disability might also be associated with altered pain sensitivity | Identifying the unmet health needs of children and adults with severe intellectual disability and improving their clinical care as failure to do so increases their disadvantages and existing health inequities; increasing the enrolment of children and adolescents with intellectual disability in clinical pain research to enhance inclusiveness |
Scientific validity | Use of accepted scientific principles and methods to produce reliable and valid data | Standard experimental pain methods used in experimental pain studies should be modified as they require participants to have the ability to self-report so perception, intensity, and character of pain can be established | Increasing the use of pain assessment tools that do not rely on self-reporting in both clinical and experimental pain research; developing modified experimental pain methods that allow researchers to control the intensity of noxious stimuli, beginning with levels of intensity derived from normative data from typically developing children and children with mild to moderate intellectual disability; ensuring that modified experimental pain methods safely allow for repetitions of the same stimuli—which is important for the generalisability, reproducibility, and replicability of research findings—so the response to stimuli can be compared with that of typically developing children and adolescents or children and adolescents with mild intellectual disability |
Fair participant selection | Selection of participants so that vulnerable individuals are not targeted for risky research and the rich or powerful are not favoured for potentially beneficial research | Some scientific questions can be answered by studies enrolling children and adolescents with mild or moderate intellectual disability who can communicate and self-report, but the evaluation of somatosensory function in children with severe intellectual disability might require their enrolment | Explaining why the social and scientific value of a study requires including children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability and why sufficiently relevant data cannot be inferred from children and adolescents with mild or moderate intellectual disability; increasing enrolment of children and adolescents with intellectual disability in pain studies involving interventions associated with minimal risk, and which are known to benefit typically developing children and adolescents |
Favourable risk–benefit ratio | Minimisation of risks; enhancement of potential benefits | Current experimental pain research involving children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability has no direct benefit to participants and therefore should be judged to have minimal risk; pain research can cause unpleasant or frightening experiences | Minimising and justifying the number of repeated exposures, and the selection and justification of the maximum amount of noxious stimuli, if the generalisability, reproducibility, and replicability of a study requires the repeated application of noxious stimuli; recognising that somatosensory function and pain response in children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability might differ from children and adolescents with less severe intellectual disability such that studies in children and adolescents with mild or moderate intellectual disability can inform, but not replace, studies involving children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability |
Independent review | Review of the design of the research trial, its proposed participant population, and its risk–benefit ratio by individuals unaffiliated with the research | Independent review board members might lack the specialised knowledge necessary to accurately assess research involving highly vulnerable populations | Suggesting that independent review boards include an independent expert or an ad hoc member—potentially a collaborative partner or consultant with relevant expertise working with intellectual disability—in their review process; involving stakeholders, such as parents and caregivers, in protocol development and the review of proposed investigations |
Independent review | Review of the design of the research trial, its proposed participant population, and its risk–benefit ratio by individuals unaffiliated with the research | Independent review board members might lack the specialised knowledge necessary to accurately assess research involving highly vulnerable populations | Suggesting that independent review boards include an independent expert or an ad hoc member—potentially a collaborative partner or consultant with relevant expertise working with intellectual disability—in their review process; involving stakeholders, such as parents and caregivers, in protocol development and the review of proposed investigations |
Informed consent | Provision of information to participants, or their parents or guardians, about the purpose of the research, procedures, potential risks, benefits, and alternatives so that the individual understands and can make a voluntary decision whether to enrol and continue to participate | Children and adolescents with severe intellectual disability might be non-verbal and so unable to assent and their dissent could go unrecognised | Ensuring that the research team understands the requirements for informed consent to paediatric research; ensuring that research participants are closely monitored for signs of potential dissent or distress by including their caretakers to improve the recognition of resistance, distress, or dissent |
Collaborative Partnership
The principle of collaborative partnership is intended to address issues special to research in developing countries but is relevant whenever research involves especially vulnerable populations (Table). The principle requires that members of these populations have a say in identifying their health needs most in need of study. Collaborative partnerships also promote trust and guard against exploitation of vulnerable populations who may be distrustful of the research community (17).
In pain research involving children with severe ID, collaborative partnership obliges researchers to seek partnerships with those with intimate understanding of the population’s health needs and problems, including parents and caretakers, healthcare providers, and condition-specific support groups or online social communities (5,14,18). As we suggest, these partnerships also help ensure that other principles are satisfied.
Social or Scientific Value
Ethical research must have potential social or scientific value: to justify exposing participants to the risks of research, research should be expected to lead to improvements in health or well-being or increase knowledge or understanding of a condition (Table) (16). This guards against subjecting participants to risks without sufficient justification, and helps ensure the responsible use of scarce resources like research funding. Given the relative paucity of pain research in children with severe ID, there are various ways such research could produce great social and scientific value, in addition to addressing one of the many inequities that exist in pain research, as recognized by the IASP (5,12).
Children and adults with ID present co-occurring physical disabilities and medical conditions that render them vulnerable to pain (19,20). These include neuromotor disorders including decreased mobility, immobility, spasticity, sustained muscle contractions, and dyskinesia as well as skeletal abnormalities including scoliosis, osteopenia, pathological fractures, and hip subluxation (21–23). Additionally, many interventions needed to treat these disabilities are associated with acute pain. For example, surgery to repair severe scoliosis is associated with severe pain; however, after scoliosis surgery, children with ID receive significantly less analgesics than those without ID, indicating that pain may be undertreated in this population (24,25). While other sensory modalities, like taste, hearing, smell, and vision, are predominantly informative, pain is informative and protective: it often signals illness or tissue damage and is the most common reason why individuals seek medical care. But individuals with ID seen in emergency departments receive significantly fewer diagnoses associated with physical pain than typically developing individuals (19). Additionally, caregivers making decisions about when to seek medical care based on their child’s expression of pain, often do so later than optimal, which can lead to increased risk of complications related to delayed diagnosis (26,27). But poor understanding of their experience of pain makes it difficult to interpret and respond to these findings. To say with confidence that pain in children with severe ID is problematically underdiagnosed and undertreated requires a better grasp on whether and to what extent pain sensitivity of children with severe ID is altered. Thus, identification of altered somatosensory function can improve understanding of pain sensitivity and pain response, which might prevent delayed diagnoses and clinical complications, inform pain management in children with ID, and aid the development of improved analgesic approaches (8).
Recent discoveries and in-depth phenotyping of individuals with ID with identified genetic conditions suggest genotypic explanations of potential differences in pain sensitivity. Several genetic conditions associated with atypical pain responses include those with a preponderance of severe ID (28). These include WAGR Syndrome (7), Phelan-McDermid Syndrome (PMS) (29,30), Christianson Syndrome (31), and Rett Syndrome (8,32), among others. Some such conditions, like PMS and WAGR syndrome, can result from chromosomal deletions, which can include varying numbers of genes and are associated with significant interindividual variability and a broad spectrum of ID severity. For some conditions, studies of implicated genes (i.e. SHANK3, BDNF) point to alterations in neurobiological pathways resulting from the respective gene mutations, which may relate to differences in pain sensitivity (30,33). Yet despite the genotypic explanation of altered pain sensitivity and wide support from parents and healthcare providers, nearly all existing pain research on children with ID involves only those with mild to moderate ID (34–38). Pain research involving children with severe ID may corroborate these genetic explanations, account for the disparities illustrated above, and clarify whether conditions associated with severe ID are associated with increased pain tolerance or complete lack of pain sensation. Again, this information would have social and scientific value: since lack of pain sensation can be dangerous and contribute to delayed diagnoses and clinical complications, improving awareness of this possibility is worthwhile (39–41).
But pain research might instead reveal little to no differences in pain sensitivity, or even increased pain sensitivity, suggesting children with severe ID do not exhibit the vocalizations, facial expressions, and motor behaviors indicative of pain in typically developing children (7,8,35). This would also have significant social and scientific value. Besides corroborating that pain in children with severe ID is seriously underreported, underdiagnosed, and undertreated, such findings would motivate research to improve pain diagnostics and analgesics in this population and spur the development of better objective tools for pain assessment (19,42). This is significant because lacking these diagnostics, analgesics, and assessment tools leaves parents and caretakers in the psychologically difficult position of constantly worrying that their child (or later, adult) is in pain. This also leaves providers without evidence-based guidance on diagnosing and treating pain in a population with increased risk of polymedication, drug interactions, and adverse side effects (43).
Both the United States Association of the Study of Pain (13) and the IASP (12) recognize the inequities faced by individuals with ID and provide guidance to enhance inclusiveness in pain research. Increasing enrollment of children and adults with severe ID could produce significant social and scientific value, by ensuring that this disadvantaged and underrepresented population equitably benefits from pain research.
Scientific Validity
Research with social or scientific value is ethical only if it uses rigorous methods to produce scientifically reliable and valid results (Table) (16). Rigorous methods must be practically feasible, have a clear scientific objective, be designed using accepted principles and reliable practices, and have sufficient power to test the research question. Poorly designed research yields scientifically unreliable and invalid results and is therefore unjustified because it exposes participants to risks for no purpose (16). Applied to pain research in children with severe ID, the challenge is how to obtain valid scientific data, given participants’ inability to communicate about their pain, self-report, and understand or follow directions. Modifying standard pain research methods is necessary to overcome this challenge and enable answering the research questions of given pain studies. But problematically there are no established standards for modifying these methods in a way that balances the safe use of experimental stimuli with the generation of valid data in individuals with severe ID—developing these standards may itself have significant scientific value (44).
How can standard methods be ethically modified, or new methods developed, without unduly compromising validity and rigor? Consider quantitative sensory tests (QST) commonly used in pain research involving typically developing children and adults (45,46) and individuals with mild to moderate ID (7,38). QSTs allow researchers to control the intensity of stimuli and require subjects’ active participation. Applying heat, cold, mechanical, or electrical stimuli of varying intensities to various parts of the body, researchers rely on participants to determine the level at which they first perceive the stimuli (the “innocuous” threshold) and the level at which they first perceive the stimuli as painful (the “noxious” threshold), and to use rating-scales to characterize the character and intensity of pain. QST studies can predict pain intensity, subsequent disability, and pain-related negative affect, suggesting that responses measured by QSTs correlate with clinical pain (6,8,28). However, since QST depends on subject participation, its use as a pain assessment or diagnostic tool is strongly discouraged in conditions associated with clinically relevant cognitive deficits (47). Recently, pain researchers have begun to modify standard QSTs and have shown the feasibility of using modified QSTs to study pain response in adults with dementia-associated cognitive impairment and adults with mild to moderate ID (34,37,48–51).
Given the significant unknowns about the experience of pain in children with severe ID, and their inability to communicate how painful the stimulus is or understand and follow directions, when modifying QSTs, researchers should be sensitive to the possibility that the range of stimuli tolerated by typically developing children may not be appropriate for those with severe ID, and modify their methods accordingly. One option is to rely on measures that do not require the ability to self-report pain or to use methods that can increase communication ability otherwise. For example, many behavior observational scales not relying on verbal self-report are used to assess clinical pain and guide its treatment, those could be adapted for investigations of pain response behavior (24,50,52–55). Researchers can also use assistive technology and methods like acoustic analysis of spontaneous vocalization to evaluate pain response (56,57). Other objective surrogate measures to evaluate stimuli response that do not require the ability to self-report pain include electroencephalography, near-infrared spectroscopy, functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), and other physiological measures (e.g., behavioral reactivity, heart rate variability, blood pressure, galvanic skin response, pupillary response). These measures do not provide the determination of perception or pain thresholds, but do provide a way of comparing the physiological response to a range of stimuli in a standardized way across typically developing children and those with mild, moderate, or severe ID that has relevance to understanding sensory function or dysfunction in this population (7,34,35,48).
Although it is theoretically possible to avoid the intentional application of noxious stimuli by using these objective measures to track response to stimuli known to be noxious in clinical care (e.g., a venipuncture), considerations of scientific validity and methodological rigor still favor their controlled and intentional application. This is for two reasons. First, QSTs allow researchers to control the intensity of stimuli using low levels of noxious stimuli. Experimental pain studies using QST are feasible and tolerated by typically developing children and children with moderate ID (38). Since studies have determined normative values for innocuous and noxious thresholds in both of these groups (7,36,38,58,59), those values can inform the design of QSTs suitable for children with severe ID. There may be reasons to worry about the relevance and validity of this data for this group, but it at least provides a baseline to help minimize risk by eliminating the possibility of inflicting severe pain. Second, QST technically allows for repetitions of the same stimuli, which is important for researchers tracking objective surrogate measures of response to sensory stimulation in lieu of self-reports. Since studies involving individuals with severe ID typically have small sample sizes, this is relevant for the generalizability, reproducibility, and replicability of research findings.
Fair Subject Selection
Ethical research must engage in fair subject selection: the primary basis for determining who is recruited or enrolled in a study must be the scientific goals of the study, and not vulnerability, privilege, or other factors unrelated to the purposes of the research (16). Fair subject selection guards against the exploitation of vulnerable populations and is therefore particularly salient for research involving children with severe ID, who should be involved only if relevant data cannot be gathered without them.
To satisfy the principle of fair subject selection, researchers should clarify why the social and scientific value of a study requires including children with severe ID who cannot communicate about their pain, understand or follow directions, or provide assent, and why the same data cannot be obtained by generalizing from similar research involving less vulnerable individuals. In other words, researchers should explain why sufficiently relevant data cannot be inferred from children with mild or moderate ID, who are more likely to be capable of communicating about their pain. One reason already noted is that severe ID is common in genetic conditions known to cause altered pain sensitivity (PMS, WAGR, and Rett Syndrome) (8,60–62). There is no way to study the effects of such conditions on pain without enrolling individuals with severe ID, nor, for that matter, can we study the interaction between severe ID itself and pain without their enrollment. Fair subject selection may therefore require that we include individuals with severe ID in relevant pain studies; indeed, it may be unfair to exclude them.
Favorable Risk-Benefit Profile
Ethical research exposes participants only to risks and burdens necessary to obtain the relevant scientific data (Table). Risks should be minimized consistent with the study’s scientific goals and justified by both the expected benefits to participants and the study’s social or scientific value (16). The risk-benefit profile of pain research in children with severe ID will vary across studies, but currently, most experimental pain research offers no direct benefit to participants. Thus, given significant unknowns about the experience of pain in children with severe ID and their vulnerability, researchers must design “minimal risk” studies, meaning the probability and magnitude of expected harm is equivalent to or less than the risks of daily life or routine examinations (63). Given the widespread practice of excluding persons with ID from research (5), it is unsurprising that even studies of minimal risk interventions like distraction techniques for children undergoing procedures seldom enroll children with severe ID (64). Someday there may be clinical trials of promising interventions that specifically target pain management in children with severe ID which could provide participants a prospect of direct benefit (e.g., functional improvement), and therefore would involve assessing whether a minor increase over minimal risk is permissible. The point is simply that ethical research must have a favorable risk-benefit ratio, and the paucity of pain research enrolling children with ID makes the assessment of the risk-benefit ratio rather challenging.
Even if a pain study involves minimal risk, researchers have reasons to be cautious: even among typically developing individuals, pain thresholds vary and researchers cannot rely on those with severe ID to say “stop!” if and when the discomfort is too much. Further, children with severe ID might find some stimuli or methods of studying pain response (i.e., fMRI) more uncomfortable or anxiety-inducing than might typically developing children, especially since the inability to understand what is happening and the purpose of research involving even mild noxious stimuli might induce fear.
To ensure that risks to participants are sufficiently low, researchers might incorporate the following considerations into their study design. If the generalizability, reproducibility, and replicability of a study necessitates repeated application of noxious stimuli, care should be taken to minimize and justify the number of exposures. For example, researchers should explain why their chosen method requires x rounds of noxious stimulation at y seconds each (rather than some lower values), and the procedures in place to minimize the potential risks of repeated application. Similar attention should be given to the selection and justification of the maximum level of noxious stimuli. For example, researchers using QSTs might establish a safe maximum level of stimulation by choosing the 50th percentile of innocuous and noxious thresholds in typically developing children and children with mild to moderate ID reported for age category and sex, thereby ensuring that stimuli are known to be well-tolerated by those subjects and mild enough to preclude tissue damage (7,38,62).
Researchers should consider additional safeguards to minimize potential risks, especially if the study involves more than minimal risk (supposing the study’s potential benefits justify this minor increase). For example, to observe for stress, anxiety, and perceived but nonverbally communicated dissent (more below), researchers might consider including an independent monitor and the consenting parent or caretaker in the room for the duration of the study. During the informed consent process, researchers should ensure that the consenting individual understands how to withdraw consent, and that they may do so at any point. Researchers should continuously monitor whether the planned number of rounds of noxious stimuli are tolerated by participants and necessary to answer their research questions, and be prepared to modify their experimental design if they are not. Additionally, researchers should consider the other risk-minimizing procedures outlined in the IASP’s guidelines, like those regarding the availability of effective, accepted pain relief (15).
Lastly, researchers should consider piloting techniques with closely-related but less severely-affected populations. For instance, when studying PMS, researchers might pilot their modified QST methods on verbal children with milder ID, as a way to inform the design and methods to be used in children with severe ID (65). However, given that unique technical modifications will likely be required for this population, such pilot studies can only inform rather than replace studies involving children with severe ID. Ultimately this cohort must be included, if researchers are to learn about their specific pain sensitivity and response.
Independent Review
Ethical research always involves independent review (16). Besides ensuring rigorous, scientifically valid methodology and a favorable risk-benefit profile, independent review guards against conflicts of interest that might unwittingly shape the design, conduct, and analysis of research (Table) (16). Are there special considerations for independently reviewing pain research involving children with severe ID? In studies that have unusual risk considerations (e.g., if reasonable people might disagree about whether the study involves minimal risk), then given the importance of accurately assessing risks and benefits, committees might consider including an ad hoc member—perhaps a collaborative partner or consultant with relevant expertise, including lived experience, or experience working with ID. Additionally, if committees are reviewing research involving unfamiliar or especially vulnerable populations, researchers may need to play an educational role, or perhaps recommend an independent expert who can do so.
Informed Consent and the Role of Parents/Guardians and Legally Authorized Representatives
Once a protocol is determined to be valuable, valid, and acceptable with respect to risks, benefits, and subject selection, individuals are recruited and asked to provide informed consent. The aim of informed consent is to protect autonomy (Table) (16). To provide it, a participant (or surrogate) must be an adult who is accurately informed of the purpose, methods, risks, benefits, and alternatives to research, understands this information and its bearing on their clinical situation and, on that basis, makes a voluntary decision whether to participate (16).
Although the requirements for informed consent vary across jurisdictions, we illustrate using the United States’ standard regulatory framework for pediatric research (66). The informed consent process includes parental (or guardian) permission and child assent, where “assent” means an affirmative agreement to participate and not mere failure to object (66). Minimal risk research typically requires permission from one parent and “adequate provisions” for soliciting child assent such as visual aids or age-appropriate explanations of the purpose and methods of research (63). (Additional provisions are necessary when research involves greater than minimal risk but presents the prospect of direct benefit or a minor increase over minimal risk with no prospect of direct benefit (66).)
Children with severe ID cannot assent, but they may show signs of resistance, distress, or dissent. Most bioethicists and research institutions recognize the importance of these reactions, but there is no settled guidance regarding them. Some bioethicists interpret “dissent” as exhibiting a meaningful request, such that children with severe ID cannot dissent. Nevertheless, these individuals may still show signs of resistance, distress, or discomfort. If these differ from typical behaviors, they should be interpreted as burdens of the research: they should figure into evaluations of overall research risks to ensure that participants’ aversive experiences do not exceed the anticipated risks and burdens that were justified by the overall ethical assessment of the protocol (67). Finally, just as with pain, children with severe ID may express or communicate dissent in atypical or unfamiliar ways. To increase the likelihood that their dissent is recognized, children with severe ID should be monitored by parents or other caretakers who know them well and can best represent their interests.
It may be necessary or scientifically desirable to include adults with severe ID along with children, and their inclusion raises different questions about informed consent. Federal regulations in the United States refer to the rightful surrogate as the legally authorized representative (LAR), though they generally defer to local and state laws in defining the term. Absent applicable local or state laws regarding LAR consent procedures, at least for federal regulatory purposes, researchers may rely on institutional (e.g., hospital) policies (63). Federal regulations do not stratify the authority of LAR by risk category, but most institutions follow an approach like the regulations for pediatric research. (See for example the National Institutes of Health’s Policy 403 “Research With Adults Who Lack Decision-Making Capacity to Consent” (68).)
Conclusion
Although pain research involving children with severe ID has the potential to yield significant social and scientific value, it raises difficult questions. The inability of children with severe ID to communicate about their pain creates challenging and possibly harmful clinical situations, but also raises ethical and methodological challenges. However, it is possible to expand on the IASP’s existing ethical guidelines for pain research by applying a well-established ethical framework for assessing clinical research. Such expanded ethical guidance, we hope, will aid in designing, conducting, reviewing, or evaluating pain research involving children with severe ID. For children and adults with severe ID whose disabilities often involve impairment of the peripheral and central nervous systems, and who must rely on others to advocate on their behalf, such research is an ethical imperative.
Key Messages Panel.
Children (and adults) with severe intellectual disabilities present with co-occurring physical disabilities and medical conditions that render them especially vulnerable to pain, yet they face inequities in pain research and care.
Pain research involving this vulnerable population is urgently needed but ethically and methodologically challenging, as individuals with severe ID are often non-verbal and unable to understand and follow directions or assent to participate.
These obstacles can be overcome by applying an ethical framework for clinical research, giving particular attention to, among other things: the social value of pain research involving individuals with severe ID; involving stakeholders with intimate understanding of this population; ensuring fair selection of subjects; maintaining scientific validity in adapting standard experimental pain research methods; and ensuring a favorable risk-benefit ratio.
Systematically excluding individuals with severe ID from participating in research that will improve understanding of their somatosensory function and pain experience compounds existing health-related inequities.
Acknowledgments:
The authors thank Jacob Barrett, Naomi Knoble, David Wendler, and the editor and two anonymous reviewers for this journal for valuable feedback. This work was supported in part by the Intramural Research Program of the National Institutes of Health Clinical Center and National Institute Mental Health, National Institutes of Health (Grant numbers 1ZIACL090052-05, 1ZIACL090053-05, and1ZIACL090054-05).
Footnotes
Disclaimer: The views expressed here are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the policies of the National Institutes of Health or the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services.
Conflict of Interest: The authors declared no conflicts of interest.
Severe ID here includes individuals diagnosed with both severe and profound intellectual disability.
Publisher's Disclaimer: This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
References
- 1.American Psychiatric Association, American Psychiatric Association, editors. Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders: DSM-5. 5th ed. Washington, D.C: American Psychiatric Association; 2013. 947 p. [Google Scholar]
- 2.ICD-11 for Mortality and Morbidity Statistics [Internet]. [cited 2022 Jul 4]. Available from: https://icd.who.int/browse11/l-m/en#/http://id.who.int/icd/entity/605267007/mms/unspecified
- 3.Cogswell ME, Coil E, Tian LH, Tinker SC, Ryerson AB, Maenner MJ, et al. Health Needs and Use of Services Among Children with Developmental Disabilities — United States, 2014–2018. MMWR Morb Mortal Wkly Rep. 2022. Mar 25;71(12):453–8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Zablotsky B, Black LI, Maenner MJ, Schieve LA, Danielson ML, Bitsko RH, et al. Prevalence and Trends of Developmental Disabilities among Children in the United States: 2009–2017. Pediatrics. 2019. Oct;144(4):e20190811. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Feldman MA, Bosett J, Collet C, Burnham-Riosa P. Where are persons with intellectual disabilities in medical research? A survey of published clinical trials: Where are persons with intellectual disabilities? J Intellect Disabil Res. 2014. Sep;58(9):800–9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Dubois A, Capdevila X, Bringuier S, Pry R. Pain expression in children with an intellectual disability. Eur J Pain Lond Engl. 2010. Jul;14(6):654–60. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Sapio MR, Iadarola MJ, LaPaglia DM, Lehky T, Thurm AE, Danley KM, et al. Haploinsufficiency of the brain-derived neurotrophic factor gene is associated with reduced pain sensitivity. Pain. 2019. May;160(5):1070–81. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Downs J, Géranton SM, Bebbington A, Jacoby P, Bahi-Buisson N, Ravine D, et al. Linking MECP2 and pain sensitivity: the example of Rett syndrome. Am J Med Genet A. 2010. May;152A(5):1197–205. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Krugman S. The Willowbrook hepatitis studies revisited: ethical aspects. Rev Infect Dis. 1986. Feb;8(1):157–62. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.The Oxford Textbook of Clinical Research Ethics. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press; 2011. 848 p. (Oxford Textbook). [Google Scholar]
- 11.Mietola R, Miettinen S, Vehmas S. Voiceless subjects? Research ethics and persons with profound intellectual disabilities. Int J Soc Res Methodol. 2017. May 4;20(3):263–74. [Google Scholar]
- 12.Morais C, Moyano J, Belton J, Moyo N . Global Inequities in Pain Treatment: How Future Research Can Address This Better--IASP Fact Sheet [Internet]. [cited 2022 Nov 4]. Available from: https://www.iasp-pain.org/resources/fact-sheets/global-inequities-in-pain-treatmenthow-future-research-can-address-this-better/
- 13.Janevic MR, Mathur VA, Booker SQ, Morais C, Meints SM, Yeager KA, et al. Making Pain Research More Inclusive: Why and How. J Pain. 2022. May;23(5):707–28. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Spong CY, Bianchi DW. Improving Public Health Requires Inclusion of Underrepresented Populations in Research. JAMA. 2018. Jan 23;319(4):337. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Ethical Guidelines for Pain Research in Humans [Internet]. International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP). [cited 2022 Jul 4]. Available from: https://www.iasppain.org/resources/guidelines/ethical-guidelines-for-pain-research-in-humans/
- 16.Emanuel EJ. What Makes Clinical Research Ethical? JAMA. 2000. May 24;283(20):2701. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Emanuel EJ, Wendler D, Killen J, Grady C. What Makes Clinical Research in Developing Countries Ethical? The Benchmarks of Ethical Research. J Infect Dis. 2004. Mar;189(5):930–7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Raiter AM, Burkitt CC, Merbler A, Lykken L, Symons FJ. Caregiver-Reported Pain Management Practices for Individuals With Cerebral Palsy. Arch Rehabil Res Clin Transl. 2021. Mar;3(1):100105. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Amor-Salamanca A, Menchon JM. Pain underreporting associated with profound intellectual disability in emergency departments. J Intellect Disabil Res JIDR. 2017. Apr;61(4):341–7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Hsieh K, Rimmer J, Heller T. Prevalence of Falls and Risk Factors in Adults with Intellectual Disability. Am J Intellect Dev Disabil. 2012. Nov 1;117(6):442–54. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Kinnear D, Morrison J, Allan L, Henderson A, Smiley E, Cooper SA. Prevalence of physical conditions and multimorbidity in a cohort of adults with intellectual disabilities with and without Down syndrome: cross-sectional study. BMJ Open. 2018. Feb 5;8(2):e018292. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Krahn GL, Hammond L, Turner A. A cascade of disparities: health and health care access for people with intellectual disabilities. Ment Retard Dev Disabil Res Rev. 2006;12(1):70–82. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Berkvens JJL, Mergler S, Beerhorst K, Verschuure P, Tan IY, Majoie HJM, et al. Bone mineral density and fractures in institutionalised children with epilepsy and intellectual disability. J Intellect Disabil Res JIDR. 2021. Nov;65(11):962–70. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Malviya S, Voepel-Lewis T, Tait AR, Merkel S, Lauer A, Munro H, et al. Pain management in children with and without cognitive impairment following spine fusion surgery. Paediatr Anaesth. 2001. Jul;11(4):453–8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Barney CC, Merbler AM, Quest K, Byiers BJ, Wilcox GL, Schwantes S, et al. A case-controlled comparison of postoperative analgesic dosing between girls with Rett syndrome and girls with and without developmental disability undergoing spinal fusion surgery. Paediatr Anaesth. 2017. Mar;27(3):290–9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Tajima H, Ogawa J, Nose I, Pawankar R, Maeda M, Momota Y, et al. Effect of Childhood Disease on Hospital Presentation: A Survey of Pediatricians. J Nippon Med Sch. 2022;89(2):190–5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Reeves PT, Susi A, Hisle-Gorman E, Gorman GH, Nylund C. Brief Report: Association of Complicated Appendicitis in Children with Autism Spectrum Disorders. J Autism Dev Disord. 2020. Dec 1;50(12):4535–40. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Bruel AL, Vitobello A, Tran Mau-Them F, Nambot S, Sorlin A, Denommé-Pichon AS, et al. Next-generation sequencing approaches and challenges in the diagnosis of developmental anomalies and intellectual disability. Clin Genet. 2020. Nov;98(5):433–44. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Samogy-Costa CI, Varella-Branco E, Monfardini F, Ferraz H, Fock RA, Barbosa RHA, et al. A Brazilian cohort of individuals with Phelan-McDermid syndrome: genotype-phenotype correlation and identification of an atypical case. J Neurodev Disord. 2019. Jul 18;11(1):13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Xu N, Lv H, Yang T, Du X, Sun Y, Xiao B, et al. A 29 Mainland Chinese cohort of patients with Phelan-McDermid syndrome: genotype-phenotype correlations and the role of SHANK3 haploinsufficiency in the important phenotypes. Orphanet J Rare Dis. 2020. Nov 30;15(1):335. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Pescosolido MF, Stein DM, Schmidt M, El Achkar CM, Sabbagh M, Rogg JM, et al. Genetic and phenotypic diversity of NHE6 mutations in Christianson syndrome. Ann Neurol. 2014. Oct;76(4):581–93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Merbler AM, Byiers BJ, Hoch J, Dimian AC, Barney CC, Feyma TJ, et al. Preliminary Evidence That Resting State Heart Rate Variability Predicts Reactivity to Tactile Stimuli in Rett Syndrome. J Child Neurol. 2020. Jan;35(1):42–8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Huang M, Pu S, Jiang W, Worley PF, Xu T. Deficiency of SHANK3 isoforms impairs thermal hyperalgesia and dysregulates the expression of postsynaptic proteins in the spinal cord. Neurosci Res. 2021. Feb;163:26–33. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Benromano T, Pick CG, Granovsky Y, Defrin R. Increased Evoked Potentials and Behavioral Indices in Response to Pain Among Individuals with Intellectual Disability. Pain Med Malden Mass. 2017. Sep 1;18(9):1715–30. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Defrin R, Pick CG, Peretz C, Carmeli E. A quantitative somatosensory testing of pain threshold in individuals with mental retardation. Pain. 2004. Mar;108(1–2):58–66. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Priano L, Miscio G, Grugni G, Milano E, Baudo S, Sellitti L, et al. On the origin of sensory impairment and altered pain perception in Prader-Willi syndrome: a neurophysiological study. Eur J Pain Lond Engl. 2009. Sep;13(8):829–35. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Barney CC, Merbler AM, Simone DA, Walk D, Symons FJ. Investigating the Feasibility of a Modified Quantitative Sensory Testing Approach to Profile Sensory Function and Predict Pain Outcomes Following Intrathecal Baclofen Implant Surgery in Cerebral Palsy. Pain Med Malden Mass. 2020. Jan 1;21(1):109–17. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Valkenburg AJ, Tibboel D, van Dijk M. Pain sensitivity of children with Down syndrome and their siblings: quantitative sensory testing versus parental reports. Dev Med Child Neurol. 2015. Nov;57(11):1049–55. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Patja K, Eero P, Iivanainen M. Cancer incidence among people with intellectual disability. J Intellect Disabil Res JIDR. 2001. Aug;45(Pt 4):300–7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Millard SK, de Knegt NC. Cancer Pain in People With Intellectual Disabilities: Systematic Review and Survey of Health Care Professionals. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2019. Dec;58(6):1081–1099.e3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Motil KJ, Lane JB, Barrish JO, Annese F, Geerts S, McNair L, et al. Biliary Tract Disease in Girls and Young Women With Rett Syndrome. J Pediatr Gastroenterol Nutr. 2019. Jun;68(6):799–805. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Hauer J, Houtrow AJ. Pain Assessment and Treatment in Children With Significant Impairment of the Central Nervous System. Pediatrics. 2017. Jun;139(6):e20171002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Lonchampt S, Gerber F, Aubry JM, Desmeules J, Kosel M, Besson M. Pain interventions in adults with intellectual disability: A scoping review and pharmacological considerations. Eur J Pain Lond Engl. 2020. May;24(5):875–85. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Barney CC, Andersen RD, Defrin R, Genik LM, McGuire BE, Symons FJ. Challenges in pain assessment and management among individuals with intellectual and developmental disabilities. Pain Rep. 2020. Jun 16;5(4):e821. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Edwards RR, Sarlani E, Wesselmann U, Fillingim RB. Quantitative assessment of experimental pain perception: multiple domains of clinical relevance. Pain. 2005. Apr;114(3):315–9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Georgopoulos V, Akin-Akinyosoye K, Zhang W, McWilliams DF, Hendrick P, Walsh DA. Quantitative sensory testing and predicting outcomes for musculoskeletal pain, disability, and negative affect: a systematic review and meta-analysis. Pain. 2019. Sep;160(9):1920–32. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Backonja MM, Attal N, Baron R, Bouhassira D, Drangholt M, Dyck PJ, et al. Value of quantitative sensory testing in neurological and pain disorders: NeuPSIG consensus. Pain. 2013. Sep;154(9):1807–19. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Symons FJ, Harper V, Shinde SK, Clary J, Bodfish JW. Evaluating a Sham-Controlled Sensory-Testing Protocol for Nonverbal Adults With Neurodevelopmental Disorders: Self-Injury and Gender Effects. J Pain. 2010. Aug;11(8):773–81. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Defrin R, Benromano T, Pick CG. Specific Behavioral Responses Rather Than Autonomic Responses Can Indicate and Quantify Acute Pain among Individuals with Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities. Brain Sci. 2021. Feb 18;11(2):253. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Defrin R, Beshara H, Benromano T, Hssien K, Pick CG, Kunz M. Pain Behavior of People with Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities Coded with the New PAIC-15 and Validation of Its Arabic Translation. Brain Sci. 2021. Sep 22;11(10):1254. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Kunz M, Waal MWM, Achterberg WP, Gimenez‐Llort L, Lobbezoo F, Sampson EL, et al. The Pain Assessment in Impaired Cognition scale (PAIC15): A multidisciplinary and international approach to develop and test a meta‐tool for pain assessment in impaired cognition, especially dementia. Eur J Pain. 2020. Jan;24(1):192–208. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Breivik H, Borchgrevink PC, Allen SM, Rosseland LA, Romundstad L, Breivik Hals EK, et al. Assessment of pain. Br J Anaesth. 2008. Jul;101(1):17–24. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Breau LM, Finley GA, McGrath PJ, Camfield CS. Validation of the Non-communicating Children’s Pain Checklist–Postoperative Version. Anesthesiology. 2002. Mar 1;96(3):528–35. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Cascella M, Bimonte S, Saettini F, Muzio MR. The challenge of pain assessment in children with cognitive disabilities: Features and clinical applicability of different observational tools. J Paediatr Child Health. 2019. Feb;55(2):129–35. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Pizzinato A, Liguoro I, Pusiol A, Cogo P, Palese A, Vidal E. Detection and assessment of postoperative pain in children with cognitive impairment: A systematic literature review and meta‐analysis. Eur J Pain. 2022. May;26(5):965–79. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Icht M, Wiznitser Ressis-tal H, Lotan M. Can the Vocal Expression of Intellectually Disabled Individuals Be Used as a Pain Indicator? Initial Findings Supporting a Possible Novice Assessment Method. Front Psychol. 2021. Jul 22;12:655202. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Fitzpatrick R, McGuire BE, Lydon HK. Improving pain‐related communication in children with autism spectrum disorder and intellectual disability. Paediatr Neonatal Pain. 2022. Mar;4(1):22–32. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Blankenburg M, Boekens H, Hechler T, Maier C, Krumova E, Scherens A, et al. Reference values for quantitative sensory testing in children and adolescents: developmental and gender differences of somatosensory perception. Pain. 2010. Apr;149(1):76–88. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Hennequin M, Morin C, Feine J. Pain expression and stimulus localisation in individuals with Down’s syndrome. The Lancet. 2000. Dec;356(9245):1882–7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.De Rubeis S, Siper PM, Durkin A, Weissman J, Muratet F, Halpern D, et al. Delineation of the genetic and clinical spectrum of Phelan-McDermid syndrome caused by SHANK3 point mutations. Mol Autism. 2018;9:31. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Han Q, Kim YH, Wang X, Liu D, Zhang ZJ, Bey AL, et al. SHANK3 Deficiency Impairs Heat Hyperalgesia and TRPV1 Signaling in Primary Sensory Neurons. Neuron. 2016. Dec 21;92(6):1279–93. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Magerl W, Krumova EK, Baron R, Tölle T, Treede RD, Maier C. Reference data for quantitative sensory testing (QST): refined stratification for age and a novel method for statistical comparison of group data. Pain. 2010. Dec;151(3):598–605. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.Protections (OHRP) O for HR. 2018 Requirements (2018 Common Rule) [Internet]. HHS.gov. 2017 [cited 2022 Jul 11]. Available from: https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-andpolicy/regulations/45-cfr-46/revised-common-rule-regulatory-text/index.html [Google Scholar]
- 64.Koller D, Goldman RD. Distraction Techniques for Children Undergoing Procedures: A Critical Review of Pediatric Research. J Pediatr Nurs. 2012. Dec;27(6):652–81. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Brignell A, Gu C, Holm A, Carrigg B, Sheppard DA, Amor DJ, et al. Speech and language phenotype in Phelan-McDermid (22q13.3) syndrome. Eur J Hum Genet EJHG. 2021. Apr;29(4):564–74. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 66.Protections (OHRP) O for HR. Subpart D — Additional Protections for Children Involved as Subjects in Research [Internet]. HHS.gov. 2021. [cited 2022 Jul 4]. Available from: https://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/regulations-and-policy/regulations/45-cfr-46/common-rulesubpart-d/index.html [Google Scholar]
- 67.Bos W, Westra A, de Beaufort I, van de Vathorst S. To stop or not to stop: dissent and undue burden as reasons to stop participation in paediatric research. J Med Ethics. 2017. Aug;43(8):519–23. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.NIH Human Research Protection Program (HRPP) O of HSP. 3014–403 - Research Involving Adults Who Lack Decision-making Capacity to Consent to Research Participation [Internet]. [cited 2022 Jul 12]. Available from: https://policymanual.nih.gov/3014-403