Skip to main content
Elsevier - PMC COVID-19 Collection logoLink to Elsevier - PMC COVID-19 Collection
letter
. 2023 Apr 13. Online ahead of print. doi: 10.1016/j.jemermed.2023.03.066

ETHICS BETWEEN INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS AND SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITIES

Al O Giwa ⁎,§,1, Melissa Myers , Alfredo Urdaneta
PMCID: PMC10101544  PMID: 37391319

To the Editor:

In responding to the “Letter to the Editor” from Dr. Wolfgang Lederer, we will not reargue the ethics of the COVID vaccine mandate in health care professionals. We believe we were very explicit in our paper, “An Ethical Analysis of the Arguments Both for and Against COVID-19 Vaccine Mandates for Healthcare Workers.” We made it clear that we were not debating Centers for Disease Control and Prevention guidelines, Food and Drug Administration approval processes, or politics that dominated and continue to dominate discussions on the mandate. However, we will now seek to further examine the ethical arguments between individual rights and social responsibilities.

Modern just societies, which we will define as societies that respect the rights of individuals and ensure basic liberties to all members of its society, must balance the needs of individuals in the protection of a “public good.” This battle of individual rights vs. doing the best for society remains an ongoing struggle since the birth of democracies. Long before philosopher Jeremy Bentham brought the concept of utility to the forefront of intellectual debate in the 1780s, the ancient Greek philosophers Aristotle, Plato, and Socrates were deliberating such concepts (1).

In the case of health care, we accept the importance of individuals’ freedoms and rights to choose or decline services, and reference that this has been largely found and upheld from the 14th Amendment's Due Process Clause in the United States Constitution. The requirement to obtain informed consent from a patient is codified in American law as far back as 1852 (2). However, it has also been determined, as far back as 1905 in Jacobson v Massachusetts, that society (via the “state”) must protect the health of all, over the individual liberties of some (3). Although we take great pride in our individual freedoms in the United States and other modern democracies, we oftentimes forget that no right is absolute. This is both just and appropriate ethically because society would fall into chaos if every individual's rights were separately held as de facto and supreme. Health care is no exception, especially as it concerns its practitioners and their fiduciary duties to society.

Public health laws are similarly balanced to generally respect the rights of individuals while ensuring that the overall health and well-being of society at large is maintained. Generally speaking, individuals have the right to refuse all manners and degrees of care for themselves only if there is minimal impact to the well-being of society (4). Additionally, most bioethicists and appellate courts have upheld public health laws over individual liberties to impose restrictions on individuals in the cases of certain infectious diseases that have the potential to harm other members of society (5). Examples include infectious tuberculosis, cholera, smallpox, yellow fever, and many more (6).

So what are social responsibilities? There is probably no single correct or accepted answer, as individuals, industries, cultures, and periods in history seem to define it differently. Our definition is the responsibilities or obligations an individual has to their community. However, we strongly believe it is intrinsically tied with the rules of social engagement. It involves the unwritten and written contracts we all are under when born in a civilized society. Social responsibility is built into the rules that govern how we behave around others. It is the lining up or waiting your turn in line, and not just pushing others in front of you out of the way because you feel your individual rights and desires trump others. In yesteryear, we called this part of one's “civic duty.”

As physicians and officers in the US Army, all three of us believe strongly in service for others’ benefit many times over duties to the self. At times, and commonly seen during military service, when one signs up to put on the uniform, one's conduct and expectations may differ from those who do not elect to wear the uniform. We must consider the interests of others more so when we agree to wear the uniform, even if it may conflict with our own personally held views. This is our social responsibility.

Drs. Urdaneta and Giwa have written on this topic, and in fact crafted the American Academy of Emergency Medicine's Principles of Ethics based around certain professional responsibilities when physicians put on their “uniforms.” Social responsibility calls for holding the interests of those around you, and especially the patients you serve, in higher regard than your own. Interestingly, many leadership scholars are utilizing this philosophy and calling it “Servant Leadership,” and have found great success in leading multicultural and multigenerational workforces (7).

How do we resolve the seeming conflict between individual rights and social responsibility? A better question to pose may be, do you as an individual believe in a need for social responsibility? If so, then the discussion can be channeled to, what degree are you willing to sacrifice your individual rights vs. your obligations to being socially responsible? If you do not believe in social responsibility, despite living in a world built around the premise that harmony among individuals can be achieved only if there is order, rules, and a respect for the rights of others, then you will live a life in constant conflict with other members of society, and further discussion is a moot point. As Drs. Urdaneta and Giwa wrote, our oaths as physicians compel us to uphold fiduciary duties as enshrined in our roles as physicians. This duty comes even in the face of potential harm to our individual rights.

This normative ethic may seem more of a cry from the days of the “Great War” and a society all united in response to an external threat. However, in several polls on society's expectations of physicians, even when faced with potential danger to the physician, the respondents overwhelmingly believed physicians should put their lives on the line to save a patient's life (8). So although we may be immersed in a social media world claiming “it's all about me,” society still maintains old-world views on its expectations of physicians. Notwithstanding, most medical schools still require all entrants or graduates to recite an oath, which, generally speaking, vows to uphold a patient's interests over their own (9). So if society expects it, and our own training ensures we swear an oath to uphold it, how can a physician argue against social responsibility to their own patients?

So we conclude and restate our acknowledgment of individual rights, but stress that, as physicians, we must maintain the interests of society above our own and uphold social responsibility when there are clear-cut cases of a need to protect the public health over individual objections not based on clear-cut science. Again, we limited our arguments to only physicians because they are explicitly held to oaths and societal obligations to protect society and put their personal beliefs aside for the sake of patients.

Declaration of Competing Interest

The authors declare that they have no known competing financial interests or personal relationships that could have appeared to influence the work reported in this paper.

Footnotes

The views expressed herein are those of the authors and do not reflect the official policy or position of Brooke Army Medical Center, the U.S. Army Medical Department, the U.S. Army Office of the Surgeon General, the Department of the Army, the Department of the Air Force, the Department of Defense, or the U.S. Government.

REFERENCES

  • 1.Kelly PJ. Clarendon Press; Oxford, UK: 1990. Utilitarianism and distributive justice: Jeremy Bentham and the Civil Law. [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Kapp MB. Patient autonomy in the age of consumer-driven health care: informed consent and informed choice. J Health Biomed Law. 2006;2:1–32. doi: 10.1080/01947640601180398. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Farber D. The long shadow of Jacobson v. Massachusetts: public health, fundamental rights, and the courts. San Diego Law Rev. 2020;57:833. [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Jones MM, Bayer R. Paternalism and its discontents: motorcycle helmet laws, libertarian values, and public health. Am J Public Health. 2007;97:208–217. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.2005.083204. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Cole JP, Swendiman KS. Congressional Research Service, the Library of Congress; Washington, DC: 2014. Mandatory vaccinations: precedent and current laws.https://sgp.fas.org/crs/misc/RS21414.pdf Available at. Accessed May 1, 2023. [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC). Legal authorities for isolation and quarantine. Published July 20, 2022. Available at: https://www.cdc.gov/quarantine/aboutlawsregulationsquarantineisolation.html. Accessed February 27, 2023.
  • 7.Parris DL, Peachey JW. A systematic literature review of servant leadership theory in organizational contexts. J Bus Ethics. 2013;113:377–393. [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Jacobs LM, Burns KJ. The Hartford consensus: survey of the public and healthcare professionals on active shooter events in hospitals. J Am Coll Surg. 2017;225:435–442. doi: 10.1016/j.jamcollsurg.2017.06.009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Askitopoulou H, Vgontzas AN. The relevance of the Hippocratic Oath to the ethical and moral values of contemporary medicine. Part II: interpretation of the Hippocratic Oath—today's perspective. Eur Spine J. 2018;27:1491–1500. doi: 10.1007/s00586-018-5615-z. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from The Journal of Emergency Medicine are provided here courtesy of Elsevier

RESOURCES