Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2024 Apr 9.
Published in final edited form as: Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 2023 Nov 3;158:105450. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2023.105450

The Human Affectome

Daniela Schiller a,*,1, Alessandra NC Yu b,*,1, Nelly Alia-Klein c, Susanne Becker d,e, Howard C Cromwell f, Florin Dolcos g,h, Paul J Eslinger i, Paul Frewen j, Andrew H Kemp k, Edward F Pace-Schott l,m, Jacob Raber n,o, Rebecca L Silton p, Elka Stefanova q,r, Justin HG Williams s, Nobuhito Abe t, Moji Aghajani u,v, Franziska Albrecht w,x,y,z, Rebecca Alexander aa,ab, Silke Anders ac,ad, Oriana R Aragón ae,af, Juan A Arias k,ag,ah, Shahar Arzy ai, Tatjana Aue aj, Sandra Baez ak, Michela Balconi al, Tommaso Ballarini w, Scott Bannister am, Marlissa C Banta an, Karen Caplovitz Barrett ao,ap, Catherine Belzung aq, Moustafa Bensafi ar, Linda Booij as,at, Jamila Bookwala au, Julie Boulanger-Bertolus av, Sydney Weber Boutros n, Anne-Kathrin Bräscher aw,ax, Antonio Bruno ay, Geraldo Busatto az, Lauren M Bylsma ba, Catherine Caldwell-Harris bb, Raymond CK Chan bc, Nicolas Cherbuin bd, Julian Chiarella as,at, Pietro Cipresso be,bf, Hugo Critchley bg, Denise E Croote bh,bi, Heath A Demaree bj, Thomas F Denson bk, Brendan Depue bl, Birgit Derntl bm, Joanne M Dickson bn, Sanda Dolcos g,h, Anat Drach-Zahavy bo, Olga Dubljević bp,r, Tuomas Eerola am, Dan-Mikael Ellingsen bq, Beth Fairfield br,bs, Camille Ferdenzi ar, Bruce H Friedman bt, Cynthia HY Fu bu,bv, Justine M Gatt bw,aa, Beatrice de Gelder bx, Guido HE Gendolla by, Gadi Gilam bz,ca, Hadass Goldblatt cb, Anne Elizabeth Kotynski Gooding bj, Olivia Gosseries cc, Alfons O Hamm cd, Jamie L Hanson ce, Talma Hendler cf,cg, Cornelia Herbert ch, Stefan G Hofmann ci, Agustin Ibanez cj,ck,cl,cm, Mateus Joffily cn, Tanja Jovanovic co, Ian J Kahrilas p, Maria Kangas cp, Yuta Katsumi cq,h, Elizabeth Kensinger cr, Lauren AJ Kirby cs, Rebecca Koncz ct,cu, Ernst HW Koster cv, Kasia Kozlowska cw, Sören Krach cx, Mariska E Kret cy, Martin Krippl cz, Kwabena Kusi-Mensah da,db,dc, Cecile D Ladouceur dd, Steven Laureys cc, Alistair Lawrence de,df, Chiang-shan R Li dg, Belinda J Liddell bw, Navdeep K Lidhar dh, Christopher A Lowry di, Kelsey Magee bj, Marie-France Marin dj,dk, Veronica Mariotti dl, Loren J Martin dh, Hilary A Marusak co,dm, Annalina V Mayer cx, Amanda R Merner bj, Jessica Minnier dn, Jorge Moll do, Robert G Morrison p, Matthew Moore g,h,dp, Anne-Marie Mouly dq, Sven C Mueller cv, Andreas Mühlberger dr, Nora A Murphy ds, Maria Rosaria Anna Muscatello ay, Erica D Musser dt, Tamara L Newton du, Michael Noll-Hussong dv, Seth Davin Norrholm co, Georg Northoff dw, Robin Nusslock dx, Hadas Okon-Singer dy, Thomas M Olino dz, Catherine Ortner ea, Mayowa Owolabi eb,ec, Caterina Padulo ed, Romina Palermo ee, Rocco Palumbo ed, Sara Palumbo ef, Christos Papadelis eg,eh, Alan J Pegna ei, Silvia Pellegrini dl, Kirsi Peltonen ej,ek, Brenda WJH Penninx v, Pietro Pietrini el, Graziano Pinna em, Rosario Pintos Lobo dt, Kelly L Polnaszek p, Maryna Polyakova en, Christine Rabinak eo, S Helene Richter ep, Thalia Richter dy, Giuseppe Riva be,eq, Amelia Rizzo ay, Jennifer L Robinson er, Pedro Rosa az, Perminder S Sachdev ct,es, Wataru Sato et, Matthias L Schroeter w,x, Susanne Schweizer eu,ev, Youssef Shiban dr,ew, Advaith Siddharthan ex, Ewa Siedlecka bk, Robert C Smith ey, Hermona Soreq ez, Derek P Spangler fa, Emily R Stern fb,ax, Charis Styliadis fc, Gavin B Sullivan fd, James E Swain fe, Sébastien Urben ff, Jan Van den Stock fg, Michael A vander Kooij fh, Mark van Overveld fi, Tamsyn E Van Rheenen fj, Michael B VanElzakker fk, Carlos Ventura-Bort fl, Edelyn Verona fm, Tyler Volk fn, Yi Wang bc, Leah T Weingast fo, Mathias Weymar fl,fp, Claire Williams k,fq, Megan L Willis fr, Paula Yamashita di, Roland Zahn bv, Barbra Zupan fs, Leroy Lowe ft,**
PMCID: PMC11003721  NIHMSID: NIHMS1970427  PMID: 37925091

Abstract

Over the last decades, theoretical perspectives in the interdisciplinary field of the affective sciences have proliferated rather than converged due to differing assumptions about what human affective phenomena are and how they work. These metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions, shaped by academic context and values, have dictated affective constructs and operationalizations. However, an assumption about the purpose of affective phenomena can guide us to a common set of metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions. In this capstone paper, we home in on a nested teleological principle for human affective phenomena in order to synthesize metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions. Under this framework, human affective phenomena can collectively be considered algorithms that either adjust based on the human comfort zone (affective concerns) or monitor those adaptive processes (affective features). This teleologically-grounded framework offers a principled agenda and launchpad for both organizing existing perspectives and generating new ones. Ultimately, we hope the Human Affectome brings us a step closer to not only an integrated understanding of human affective phenomena, but an integrated field for affective research.

Keywords: Affect, Framework, Enactivism, Allostasis, Feeling, Sensation, Emotion, Mood, Wellbeing, Valence, Arousal, Motivation, Stress, Self

1. Introduction

The affective sciences—the interdisciplinary study of affective phenomena, such as sensation, emotion, mood, and wellbeing—have their roots in neuroscience and psychology, but also intersect with philosophy, sociology, linguistics, anthropology, computer science, and economics (Ekman and Davidson, 1994; LeDoux, 1998; Panksepp, 2004; Davidson and Sutton, 1995; Damasio, 2005; Davidson et al., 2009; Kleinginna and Kleinginna, 1981; Sander and Scherer, 2014; Dalgleish et al., 2009; Gendron and Barrett, 2009, Adolphs and Anderson, 2018; Gross and Barrett, 2013; Keltner and Lerner, 2010; Gordon, 1990; Solomon, 1978; Lutz and White, 1986; Mesquita and Frijda, 1992; Beatty, 2014, 2019; Armony and Vuilleumier, 2013; Solomon, 1993; Goldie, 2009; Deonna and Teroni, 2012; Scarantino, 2016; Picard, 2000; Hoque et al., 2011; Calvo et al., 2015; Dukes et al., 2021). This interdisciplinary field seeks to explain the mechanisms of affective phenomena by inferring affective constructs from observable data in order to predict future effects (Mill, 1856; Whewell, 1858; Machamer et al., 2000; Glennan, 2002, 2008; Azzouni, 2004; Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 2005; Chang, 2005; Morganti and Tahko, 2017; Ivanova and Farr, 2020; Levenstein et al., 2023; Hempel and Oppenheim, 1948; Hempel, 1970; Kauffman, 1970; Glennan, 1996), a scientific endeavor that has gained traction in the last few decades and secured the rise of affective research (Dukes et al., 2021). This growth, however, has been accompanied by a surge in theoretical divisions: divergent academic communities differ in their background assumptions on the metaphysics of affective phenomena (i.e., what they are), (Marr, 2010; Danziger, 1997; Dayan and Abbott, 2005; Dixon, 2003, 2012; Solomon, 2008; Goldie, 2009; Deonna and Scherer, 2010; Izard, 2010a, 2010b; Gendron, 2010; Mulligan and Scherer, 2012; Barrett, 2012; Scarantino, 2012, 2016; Adolphs, 2017; Fox, 2018; Tappolet, 2022; Moors, 2022) which further distances their assumptions about the mechanisms of those phenomena (i.e., how affective phenomena arise) (Scherer, 2005; Bridgman, 1927; Chang, 2004; Levenstein et al., 2023). These assumptions frame the basic terms of a theory, such as each theory’s affective constructs, the scientific abstractions of affective phenomena that should be used (i.e., what should be studied), as well as their appropriate operationalizations, the methods of measuring those abstractions (i.e., how to observe them) (Hempel, 1952, 1970; Carnap and Gardner, 1966; Lewis, 1970, 1972). Even when assumptions are not explicitly disclosed, they are hidden in decision points at each stage of the scientific process meant to test that theory—from experimental design and methodology all the way to analysis and interpretation (Mill, 1856; Whewell, 1858; Azzouni, 2004; Chang, 2005; Morganti and Tahko, 2017; Ivanova and Farr, 2020; Scarantino, 2016; Fox, 2018). Thus, despite the field’s agreement that studying affective phenomena is important, discrepancies have yielded lasting theoretical debates, bodies of experimental work within separate frameworks have proliferated, and limited progress has been made in pruning or integrating existing frameworks with no clear consensus in sight (Kuhn, 1974, 2012; Box, 1976; Craver and Darden, 2013; Strevens, 2013; Levy and Bechtel, 2013; Woodward, 2014).

This persistence of theoretical splitting is in part due to empirical data being inadequate in arbitrating between sets of theoretical assumptions (Holton, 1975; Kuhn, 2012; Lakatos, 1978, 2014; Lowe, 2002; Notturno and Popper, 2014; Ormerod, 2009; Popper, 1963; Laudan, 1978; Godfrey-Smith, 2021). Such disagreements can only be settled by examining each camp’s take on theoretical virtues (i.e., what qualities make good framework and resulting theory), and comparing each theory’s underlying sets of assumptions (Galilei, 1953; Newton, 1999; Einstein, 1934; Achinstein, 1983; Duhem, 1982; Sober, 2015; Poincaré 2022; Schindler, 2018; Keas, 2018; Ivanova and Farr, 2020). In addition, proponents of different theories with separate overarching frameworks differ in their assumptions about why certain affective phenomena are scientifically important—why their particular versions of the phenomena should be studied and why their methods of observation should be used (Bromberger, 1966; Achinstein, 1983; De Regt and Dieks, 2005; Kitcher, 2001; Brown, 2010; Dayan and Abbott, 2005; Kording et al., 2020; Levenstein et al., 2023). These pragmatic motivations tend to be prone to biases, such as which research tradition has been status quo in a proponent’s local context, which methods for observation are practical, which types of observational data are accessible, and which questions about affective phenomena are of interest to certain audiences (Ivanova and Farr, 2020; Duhem, 1982; Lowe, 2002; Ivanova, 2014, 2017; Paul, 2012; Ladyman, 2012; Latour and Woolgar, 2013; Achinstein, 1983; van Fraassen, 1980). Therefore, when evaluating sets of assumptions, collaboration across proponents of different camps and members of different disciplines can go a long way in shoring up these theoretical blind spots (Table 1) (Wray, 2002; Andersen and Wagenknecht, 2013; Callard and Fitzgerald, 2015; MacLeod, 2018).

Table 1. Domains of Assumptions Shaping Scientific Frameworks and Resulting Theory.

This table summarizes domains of theoretical assumptions for scientific frameworks which shape the scientific theories resulting from them. As a case study, we highlight the framework of assumptions for Affect-as-Information Theory, to provide an exemplar in affective research. The first two rows correspond to domains of assumptions embedded in our individual contexts as affective researchers; the latter rows are the assumptions about affective phenomena themselves. Each unitalicized domain forms the basis of the italicized domain following it. Finally, the last row, indicated in bold, corresponds to the collective of all the domains of assumptions above it.

Domain of Assumptions (collectively, framework) Description Relationships between Domains of Assumptions Shorthand Exemplar in Affective Research Affect-as-Information Theory (Schwarz and Clore, 1983, 2003; Clore et al., 2001; Schwarz, 2012)
Pragmatics assumed context-dependent motivation for the study of theoretical constructs Shapes metaphysics and mechanism and, therefore, determines construct and operationalization. why a construct should be studied and why a certain operationalization should be used to study it Affect should be studied as information, by observing its effect on judgments, to situate subjective experience in decision-making.
Theoretical virtues assumed desiderata for what makes good framework and theory (e.g., parsimony, elegance, simplicity) shaped by aesthetic preferences; frames how theory that applies construct and operationalization is evaluated why an explanation of a phenomenon is good Characterizing affect as information provides parsimonious explanation for its influence on decision-making.
Metaphysics assumed nature of phenomenon shaped by pragmatics what the phenomenon is One set of studies testing affect-as-information theory examines mood as an influence on decision-making.
Construct assumed abstraction of phenomenon shaped by pragmatics, metaphysics, and (sometimes) operationalization; what construct is studied Mood is construed as ranging from positive to negative.
Mechanism assumed process of phenomenon guided by pragmatics and metaphysics how phenomenon arises In the mechanism of mood functioning as information, positive valence biases positive judgment and negative valence biases negative judgment.
Operationalization assumed measurement of abstracted phenomenon guided by pragmatics, construct, and mechanism how construct is observed Overall positive to negative mood was manipulated by prompting recall of happy or sad events.
Teleology assumed purpose of the phenomenon existing determined by pragmatics; motivates metaphysics and mechanism why phenomenon exists Affect-as-information theory suggests that mood functions as information in order to indicate benign or problematic environment.
Framework (or paradigm) a set of the above domains of assumptions; terms used to articulate and organize testable theories usually explicitly or implicitly consists of all of the above all of the above All of the above

Even if comprehensive collaboration on scientific incentives and theoretical virtues could be achieved, it would be unproductive to compare the metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions governing affective research without a premise of why affective phenomena exist in the first placei.e., a teleological assumption (Deacon, 2011; Mayr, 1985; Levenstein et al., 2023). A framework grounded in a principle for the purpose of affective phenomena would allow us to (1) bridge across metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions behind different theories, (2) organize theories with respect to that teleological principle, and (3) evaluate theories in light of scientific motivations and theoretical virtues (Craver, 2007; Schindler, 2018; Keas, 2018; Levenstein, 2023). Therefore, to truly achieve an integrated understanding of affective phenomena, collaborative and interdisciplinary efforts should aim to integrate scholarly and theoretical values in order to synthesize a common set of metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions grounded in teleological principle—a framework with which to articulate and organize theories for conducting affective research as well as compare and integrate existing ones (Popper, 1963; Kuhn, 2012; Holton, 1975; Lakatos, 2014, 1978; Laudan, 1978; Lowe, 2002; Ormerod, 2009; Jabareen, 2009; Notturno and Popper, 2014; Godfrey-Smith, 2021).

In this capstone paper, we conclude the special issue “Towards an Integrated Understanding of the Human Affectome” (Cromwell and Papadelis, 2022, this issue) by synthesizing the various assumptions ruling different affective fields and camps into a common teleologically-grounded set: the Human Affectome (Cromwell and Lowe, 2022, this issue). To get to this point, 173 researchers from 23 countries came together as a global, interdisciplinary taskforce to examine existing assumptions and approaches in the study of affective constructs. As a preliminary step, a team within this working group performed an exploratory computational linguistic analysis: identifying 3664 words for feelings, sorting them into feeling categories, and characterizing more specific senses for each word (Siddharthan et al., 2018). Guided by the themes that emerged from that initial exploration, twelve teams went on to produce the twelve reviews of this special issue. Each review summarized the state of current behavioral and neuroscientific research with special emphasis on theoretical concerns (this issue: Arias et al., 2020; Raber et al., 2019; Becker et al., 2019; Pace-Schott et al., 2019; Williams et al., 2020; Cromwell et al., 2020; Dolcos et al., 2020; Stefanova et al., 2020; Alia-Klein et al., 2020; Frewen et al., 2020; Alexander et al., 2021; Eslinger et al., 2021; Cromwell and Papadelis, 2022). Thus, the initial linguistic approach encouraged an exploratory, yet integrative approach in reviewing the sampling of theoretical perspectives across the affective domains. However, these themes have yet to be considered holistically by the taskforce from a top-down perspective: how can the metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions in the affective sciences be rooted in common teleological principles to motivate shared scientific constructs and operationalizations, and frame consequent testable theories? (Machamer et al., 2000; Craver, 2007; Bechtel, 2007, 2008, 2009, 2013; Bechtel and Richardson, 2010).

In what follows, we probe the question of purpose: why are there affective phenomena? We synthesize a common set of teleological principles to guide the metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions and, ultimately, motivate shared scientific constructs and operationalizations. What we offer here is not another theory, nor is it a history or review of the field—it is a scaffold of premises that accommodates existing theories by organizing them in terms of a common set of assumptions, and promotes the articulation of new theories. Thus, this synthesis can facilitate a better understanding of assumptions, differences, and possible cohesion among perspectives in the field. We hope that you, reader, whether you are an affective neuroscientist, philosopher of emotion, cognitive psychologist, computational psychiatrist, clinician, or another interested in affect, will take something away from this synthesis. We recommend not to treat this work as the ultimate answer to the long-lasting debates the field has been entrenched in, but as the beginning of the incremental untangling of assumptions in a principled way toward a new integrative paradigm. Practically speaking, we encourage you to start with your own work—to situate your explanatory goals within the Human Affectome, relate them to other theories based on principles distilled by this synthesis, and articulate your future theories and accompanying hypotheses using these teleological terms. Ultimately, we hope that the wider community of affective sciences leverages this cohesive framework to generate and test more specific theories and hypotheses on the basis of its premises—so that in due course we will build a concrete, comprehensive, and, most importantly, principled set of affective constructs and operationalizations (analogous to Schuler et al., 1996, and Sporns et al., 2005). In this manner, this rich and sprawling field can come to an integrated understanding of human affective phenomena within which to situate past and future research.

2. Teleological Principle: Why are there human affective phenomena?

Among the affective sciences, we are united by our interest in phenomena that are subjectively felt, have neurobiological basis, influence decision-making and behavior, and can be expressed through implicit and explicit means (Darwin, 1965; James, 1890; Scherer, 1984; Leighton, 1985; Frijda, 1986; Clore and Ortony, 1988; Schwarz and Clore, 1988, 2007; Kleinginna and Kleinginna, 1981; Solomon, 1993; Ekman and Davidson, 1994; LeDoux, 1998; Panksepp, 2004; Pugmire, 1998; Davidson and Sutton, 1995; Cacioppo et al., 1999; Panksepp, 2004; Damasio, 2005; Davidson et al., 2009; Sander and Scherer, 2014; Dalgleish et al., 2009; Goldie, 2009; Deonna and Scherer, 2010; Keltner and Lerner, 2010; Hoque et al., 2011; LeDoux, 2012, 2015, 2023; Deonna and Teroni, 2012; Schwarz, 2012; Damasio and Carvalho, 2013; Gross and Barrett, 2013; Armony and Vuilleumier, 2013; Elpidorou and Freeman, 2014; Ekman, 2016; Scarantino, 2016; Deonna and Teroni, 2017; LeDoux and Brown, 2017; Adolphs and Anderson, 2018; Adolphs et al., 2019; Dukes et al., 2021). Our differing interpretations of those metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions, however, generate an expansive range of constructs and operationalizations, and resulting theories and hypotheses. Therefore, these assumptions require a teleological principle to be reduced and systematized. In this section, we will progress from the broadest purpose of an organism to the most specific principle in humans, in order to synthesize metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions for complete coverage of human affective phenomena: the Human Affectome.

2.1. To ensure viability

An organism can be considered a system or network of interconnected parts collectively and continuously (re)generating and distinguishing itself, with the ultimate purpose of autonomously ensuring its own persistent recreation and integrity (autopoiesis) (Jonas, 1973; Maturana and Varela, 1991; Varela et al., 1974, 2017; Varela, 1979; Weber and Varela, 2002; Di Paolo and Thompson, 2014). This involves recursively creating its own components, so that those components can both sustain the processes producing them as well as maintain their coordination such that, altogether, they are an organization distinct from an environment—that is, the organism. Each of these processes enables others within the system, such that they collectively support themselves and will disintegrate if even one is disrupted (Beer and Di Paolo, 2023). This dependence entails the entire neurobiological system staying within a narrow range of states, such as a specific set of glucose levels, temperature, pH, etc. (homeostasis) (Cannon, 1929; MacArthur, 1955). Therefore, the primary purpose of an organism is to ensure its own viability, where being an organism can be considered a collective inherent act of self-generating and self-distinguishing itself into continuous being through error-correcting means (Wiener et al., 2019). This helps us understand what neurobiological processes are doing at large—but more importantly for our purposes, this is our launchpad for tracing the purpose of human affective phenomena (Damasio and Carvalho, 2013; Panksepp, 2004, 2005; Strigo and Craig, 2016).

2.2. To execute operations

Complex organisms execute many varied operations to ensure viability in the face of complex and changing environments. The capacity to discern more than just a handful of facets of the environment usually goes hand-in-hand with the capacity for many dimensions of action (Tooby and Cosmides, 1990, 2008; Cosmides and Tooby, 2000, 2013). This complexity poses more risks to viability, but also allows for flexibility when circumstances change. Such a complex organism cannot afford to let any one of the many elements push its system to the brink or it risks collapse (i.e., resulting in the organism dissolving, dying, ceasing to be). The complex organism does not remain idle but rather triumphs by doing the opposite: instead of remaining in a simplistic stable state, it moves between levels of relative stability (attractor states). When a perturbation to its ongoing organization approaches, the complex organism does not immediately address the breach, the way simpler life forms reset to more suitable states when an error is detected (Pereira, 2021). Instead, it acts in the direction of that breach so that, even if its actions temporarily make things worse, the organism will be on better footing in the future (Rosenblueth et al., 1943; Ruiz-Mirazo and Moreno, 2012; Boone and Piccinini, 2016; Williams and Colling, 2018; Fingelkurts and Fingelkurts, 2004). It preempts and prepares, choosing between different courses of action to anticipate and prevent a potentially fatal state brought on by the changing aspects of the environments before that point arrives (allostasis) (Sterling and Eyer, 1988; Carpenter, 2004; Cooper, 2008; McEwen and Wingfield, 2003; Sterling, 2012, 2020; Sterling and Laughlin, 2015; Schulkin and Sterling, 2019; Moors and Fischer, 2019).

For the complex organism, there are many, sometimes equally effective, ways to ensure viability, but all require operation. Some courses of action address metabolic intolerance more directly (e.g., raising food to one’s mouth for consumption), while others require further intermediary steps (e.g., buying groceries) (Jonas, 2001). However, not all processes, especially in more intricate sequences, involve interacting with the external environment. Internal adjustments are what orchestrate the necessary shifts in approach to the environment—everything from attention to planning (mental action) (Kirsh and Maglio, 1994; Mele, 1997; Peacocke, 2006; Soteriou, 2013; Metzinger, 2017; Dolcos et al., 2020, this issue), serving as the bridge between the processes receiving inputs and those causing behavioral outputs, and enabling these two capacities to guide each other (sensorimotor) (O’Regan and Noë 2001; Di Paolo et al., 2017). Collectively, these processes move the organism around a new set of states wherein the organism is comfortable—each state as a position on one of many dimensions of anticipated deviation from viability, addressable in many actionable ways (Panksepp, 2010; Cromwell and Lowe, 2022, this issue). This ‘comfort zone’ guides the adaptive use of a repertoire of operations, whose individual actions consider future possibilities (Moors and Fischer, 2019; Cromwell et al., 2020, this issue). To navigate this comfort zone, an organism needs the capacity to monitor how it is faring with respect to the multidimensional, continuous, and fluctuating norm—an implicit form of self-evaluation. That evaluation allows the organism to consider its tools of internal and external processes in order to deploy them to safeguard viability. Sometimes, the organism’s adaptive capabilities are surpassed in a way that strains its processes (Karastoreos and McEwen, 2011; Peters et al., 2017). Exceeding the comfort zone too often can result in pervasive damage to proactive processes (allostatic load) (McEwen, 1998, 2000). Therefore, beyond viability, the purpose of cognitive processes in complex organisms is to execute operations, which naturally involves managing them.

2.3. To enact relevance

Affective phenomena, to both academics and laypeople, can be felt (Chalmers, 1997; Craig, 2002; Frijda, 1986; Lambie and Marcel, 2002; Lange, 1885; Leighton, 1985; Nagel, 1974; Pugmire, 1998; Scherer, 1982b; Schwarz and Clore, 2007; James, 1890; Schwarz and Clore, 1988; Panksepp, 2008; Barrett, 2005; Barrett et al., 2007; Izard, 2010b; Deonna and Scherer, 2010; Schwarz, 2012; Damasio and Carvalho, 2013; Elpidorou and Freeman, 2014; Deonna and Teroni, 2017; LeDoux and Brown, 2017; Strigo and Craig, 2016; LeDoux and Hofmann, 2018; Adolphs et al., 2019; Paul et al., 2020; LeDoux, 2012, 2015, 2023; Szanto and Landweer, 2020; Álvarez-González, 2023; Davidson and Sutton, 1995; Cromwell and Lowe, 2022, this issue; Cromwell and Papadelis, 2022, this issue). We experience them over a duration of time (episodes) (Tye, 2003; Wollheim, 1999; Goldie, 2000; Locke, 1847; Levine, 1983; Hardin, 1988; Stein et al., 1993), how they feel has qualities (qualia) (Nagel, 1974; Chalmers, 1997; Silva, 2023), and they tend to mean something to us when we feel them, usually about how our concerns relate to objects, either physical or mental, such as things, people, and situations (intentionality) (Brentano, 2012; Tye, 2014; Deonna and Teroni, 2012). This aspect of meaning obliges us to consider not only the meaning of each individual affective experience, but also how different meanings of affective experiences relate to each other in an organized way (phenomenology) (Heidegger, 1967; Husserl and Dummett, 2001; Merleau-Ponty, 2011; Dreyfus, 1972; Sartre, 2022). A useful starting point for understanding why affective experiences exist would, therefore, be to ascertain how the structure in felt meaning relates to the entire system of neurobiological processes—including both those within the organism and those interacting with the environment (Horgan and Tienson, 2002; Strawson, 2004; Kriegel, 2014).

One major clue that the structure of affective experiences gives us is that they originate from a first-person perspective (self) (Descartes, 1644; Husserl, 2013; Kant, 1908; Searle, 1992; Shoemaker, 2003; Wittgenstein, 1958; James, 1890; Gallagher, 2000; Metzinger, 2003a, 2003b; Ochsner and Gross, 2005; Blanke and Metzinger, 2009, 2013; Christoff et al., 2011; Zahavi and Kriegel, 2015; Colombetti, 2011; Frewen et al., 2020, this issue). On the mechanistic side of things, this perspective seems to arise from the organism adeptly executing operations in order to ensure viability from a unified point of view (i.e., self). Being guided by a comfort zone means that all of the organism’s considerations are driven by potential for action such that properties of the environment perceived and acted upon are features of action-worthiness (affordances) (Bourgine and Stewart, 2004; Stewart, 2010; Gibson, 1977; Teroni, 2007; Frijda, 1986). From the perspective of the organism, the world appears to it only in a manner relatable to its capacities (perceived surroundings or umwelten) (Uexküll, 2013; Sebeok, 2001; Chang, 2009; Feiten, 2020). If we want to be precise in studying affective mechanisms, we should not just look at the brain—we should consider the entire nervous system and the rest of the body (embodied) (Barsalou, 1999; Barsalou, 2003; Pfeifer and Bongard, 2006; Varela, 1997; Chemero, 2011; Gallagher and Zahavi, 2020; Fuchs, 2017). Among internal processes, the felt aspect of signals from our internal viscera is an important factor to consider given how often bodily sensations characterize affective experiences (interoception) (Craig, 2008; Sel, 2014; Critchley and Garfinkel, 2017; Tsakiris and Preester, 2018). However, if we fixate too much on what’s going on inside, we miss the dynamic interplay between an organism and its environment (embedded) (Beer, 2014), which shapes the organism’s adaptive capacities and gives it its perspective (situated) (Roth and Jornet, 2013; Walter, 2014; Dawson, 2014; Stephan and Walter, 2020). Having that central comfort zone in mind is what gives the organism the imperative to make sense of the world through perception, as well as affect the world through action to make sense of it (sense-making) (Di Paolo, 2005; Colombetti, 2010). Therefore, underpinned by their prospective concern for viability, and at the heart of the cognitive activity that defines them, complex organisms such as humans enact relevance for themselves—by not only taking in what is relevant but also by purposefully creating relevance (enactive) (Colombetti and Thompson, 2008; Colombetti, 2014; Ward, 2017; Newen et al., 2018; Cromwell et al., 2020, this issue). When that activity is challenged, the organism’s awareness of its own comfort zone is, from its perspective, prioritized as intense feeling to orient it to more adaptive options for action (stress) (Averill, 1973; McEwen, 1998, 2005; Koolhaas et al., 2011; McEwen and Akil, 2020). Thus, our teleological foundation of affective phenomena seems to require this organism’s emergent capacity to find things meaningful based on their actionability.

2.4. To entertain abstraction

Humans are not limited to affective processes that reflect our first-person needs of the current moment. While not fundamental to all affective phenomena, concerned foresight poses at least some detachment from the present and, therefore, enables a rudimentary form of abstraction (Neisser, 1963; Plutchik, 1982; Clore and Huntsinger, 2009; Plutchik and Kellerman, 2013). An object in the present context can be tied to some distant meaning, being associated with operations not presently executed. This form of practical symbolism is still grounded in proactive operation in the service of viability (Tenenbaum et al., 2011). This capacity for abstraction is often overlooked when painting a picture of affective phenomena. However, when it comes to humans in particular, this abstract capacity is essential as it enables us to reflect on our adaptive activities in general (especially when we are not concurrently exercising them) as well as enact relevance that is abstract. This equips us as humans with the capacity to consider adaptive operations while departing from our individual first-person perspective. We can imagine other origins of concerned perspective, starting with that of other individuals—inferring how they are oriented actionably toward the world (theory of mind) (Saxe, 2006; Brüne and Brüne-Cohrs, 2006; Mehrabian and Epstein, 1972; Smith, 2006; Cuff et al., 2016; Fotopoulou and Tsakiris, 2017). As a result, we can share an orientation toward the environment with others such that we can complement each other’s operations. This shared perspective enhances our adaptivity, expanding our operational repertoires to include cooperation and collaboration (Dunbar, 1998; Lakin et al., 2003; De Jaegher and Di Paolo, 2007; Gray et al., 2007; Fischer and Manstead, 2008, 2016; Weisman et al., 2017; Nummenmaa et al., 2018; Williams, 2020; Tomasello, 2020, 2022). Beyond this social competence, we can conceive of origins of operations other than those driven by viability: anything, animate or inanimate, can seem like it has an effect. This explodes into possibilities of conceptualizing the significance of events, situations, ideas—over and above the collective activities of many individuals, that is, groups.

These expansions to abstraction do not only grant us the capacity to associate any process of animate or inanimate change with designated labels (language) (Wittgenstein, 1953; Itkonen, 1978; Pinker, 2010; Perniss and Vigliocco, 2014; Adolphs, 2017; Adolphs and Andler, 2018) but also give us the adaptive reason to do so. Labelling specific abstract activities in our operations greatly influences what operation is possible, determining where we are in our comfort zone (Whissell, 1989; Besnier, 1990; Barrett et al., 2007; Lindquist, 2021; Colombetti, 2009). Our communication is not merely an add-on to what we enact or an after-thought to what we feel. Expression of what we feel through bodily, vocal, or visual means carves the kind of relevance we are able to enact, consequently, constraining the feeling itself (Williams et al., 2020, this issue; Wharton et al., 2021; Wharton and de Saussure, 2023). The comfort zone is so inherent to us that we project that orientation of relevance to others, assigning perspective to both the animate and inanimate, to make events unfamiliar to us part of our world of relevance. This results in us assuming things have purpose or direction even when they don’t, including people, objects, events, or even ideas, as long as they look like they do (intentional stance) (Dennett, 1989; Brooks, 1991; Villalobos and Ward, 2015; Hutto and Satne, 2015; Hutto and Myin, 2017; Csibra and Gergely, 2007). Although this projection can seem futile, it allows us to articulate statements about not only our own concerns but also the hypothetical concerns of abstract objects (propositional attitudes) (Frege, 1948; Russell, 1905). This can be useful in that these articulations can match their targets in varying degrees of better or worse, making them more or less useful.

It’s no surprise then that reality that is mapped poorly is difficult for us to operate in (misrepresentation) (Searle, 1983; Grice, 1957; Papineau, 1984; Millikan, 1987, 1989; Neander, 1995; Godfrey-Smith, 2006). In cases of psychopathology especially, we can be very off (Beck, 1971; Leventhal and Diefenbach, 1991; Cummins, 2010). This usually becomes obvious in faulty communication with others, or when our operations prove to be ineffective (Burge, 2010; Izard et al., 2008). Abstractions provide the means to articulate mental processes in verbal language, mathematical symbols, or code (cognitive science) (Stillings et al., 1995; Eckardt, 1995; Clark, 2000; Thagard, 2005), such as what is happening when individuals have trouble navigating the environment in light of their comfort zone, as they are mapping either or both poorly. We can articulate such maladaptive mechanisms and use these labels to predict future outcomes of those individuals’ subjective operations (computational psychiatry) (Egan, 2018, 2020; Shin and Liberzon, 2010; Maia et al., 2017; Petzschner et al., 2017; Smith et al., 2021; Friston, 2023; Hitchcock et al., 2022; Hoemann et al., 2021). Taken together, there is much more associated with affective phenomena in humans than mere adaptive enaction of relevance. We cannot neglect our human capacity to entertain abstraction as it determines the versatility of our comfort zone.

Synthesizing the academic interests from different corners of the field, we have now built the teleological principle of human affective phenomena, illustrating how each purpose grounds the next. We began with root of purpose of a neurobiological organism—to ensure its viability. From there, we acknowledged the purpose of a complex organism—to execute operations in the service of its viability. We then explored the purpose of an organism’s basic mental capacities—to enact its own relevance by executing operations for the sake of its viability. Finally, we discussed the purpose of conceptual capacity typical in humans—to entertain abstraction, when enacting relevance, by executing operations, to ensure our viability. To answer the question—why are there human affective phenomena?—using only one of these rationales seems incomplete: human affective phenomena collectively exist to serve these nested, intertwined purposes. Only together do these purposes account for all human affective phenomena. Therefore, guided by this teleological principle, we are now poised to articulate assumptions about what human affective phenomena are and how they work to construct our integrated framework: the Human Affectome.

3. The Human Affectome: What are human affective phenomena?

The term ‘affect’ has traditionally referred to the collective phenomena of feeling, sensation, emotion, mood, wellbeing, etc. Here, we use it to refer to the phenomena of a human organism affecting their environment and being affected by that environment, such that they are enacting their particular relevance in the world by executing operations with respect to viability. This intrinsic teleological foundation, synthesized from a comprehensive sampling of perspectives in the field of affect, can guide a principled set of metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions, resulting in an integrated framework for understanding human affective phenomena (Table 2).

Table 2. Affective Concerns and Features.

This table describes two sets of algorithms among affective phenomena—affective concerns and features—providing examples and their theoretical rationale. Each phenomenon’s computational problem is also specified, as well as algorithmic solutions existing in the field already.

Affective Phenomenon Examples Theoretical Rationale Computational Problem Existing Algorithmic Solutions
AFFECTIVE CONCERNS inference of objects as actionable and thus relevant, which is reflected in the felt implication of those objects physiological, operational, global Intentionality: feelings are about something (Frege, 1948; Russell, 1905; Dennett, 1989; Bedford, 1956; Brentano, 2012; de Sousa, 1990; Kenny, 2003; Leighton, 1985; Pitcher, 1965; Teroni, 2007; Deonna and Teroni, 2012; Clore and Huntsinger, 2009)
Embodiment and Enactivism: all cognition is encoded as action (Varela et al., 2017; Colombetti and Thompson, 2008; Shargel and Prinz, 2017; Slaby and Wüschner, 2014; Hufendiek, 2015; Hutto, 2012)
Affordances: the environment provides actionable meaning for the organism (Gibson, 1977)
Motivation Theories: feeling states as motivational (Duffy, 1957; Frijda, 1986, 2017; Hommel et al., 2017)
how to infer relevance of objects Bayesian: using observable (interoceptive or exteroceptive) sensory data to infer and update the non-observable meaning (hidden or latent conditional probabilistic states) of those sensory data (Barrett, 2017; Dayan et al., 1995; Doya, 2007; Friston et al., 2016; Knill and Pouget, 2004; Lee and Mumford, 2003; Neal, 2012; Seth, 2013; Seth and Friston, 2016; Smith et al., 2019; Wolpert et al., 1995; Palacios et al., 2020)
Immediate to Distal gradient of relevance according to the distance from metabolic impact that the actions demanded would have (i.e., complexity, timescale, abstractness) physiological, operational Evolutionary and Biological Theories: courses of action can be more immediate or more distal (Jonas, 2001) how to organize needs with varying extents of actionability Bayesian: hierarchical inference with varying levels of complexity, timescale, or abstractness; immediate concerns are hidden states inferred at a lowest level and distal concerns are those at the highest (Pezzulo et al., 2015; Pezzulo and Levin, 2016; Pezzulo et al., 2022)
Physiological concerns require the most immediate or concrete actions nourishment (hunger), hydration (thirst), internal integrity (nauseous); sensation Interoception and Homeostasis: internal state as indicative of homeostatic status (Craig, 2002, 2013; Pace-Schott et al., 2019, this issue) how to address immediate needs Reinforcement Learning: reflexive decision-making in reinforcement learning (i.e., model-free; van Swieten et al., 2021); pain as aversive prediction errors (Roy et al., 2014)
Bayesian: fatigue as metacognitive inference (Stephan et al., 2016)
Operational concerns range from proximal to distal, wherein an organism has a feeling toward an object that, if acted upon, has proximal to eventual metabolic impact safety (joy, happiness, exhilaration), danger (fear, worry, dread), obstruction (frustration, annoyance, anger), loss (disappointment, sadness, grief), epistemic (curiosity, intrigue, fascination), cooperation (care, love, belonging, trust, empathy), moral (pride, admiration, shame, moral disgust), aesthetic (awe, appreciation, beauty); emotion Evaluative or Action-Oriented Theories: feelings or emotions are evaluation of readiness for action (Dewey, 1895; Frijda, 1986, 2017; King, 2009; Deonna et al., 2015; Deonna and Teroni, 2012, 2015; Scarantino, 2014, 2015; Simon, 1967; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990, 2008; Clore and Palmer, 2009; Seth, 2013; Oatley and Johnson-Laird, 2014; Bach and Dayan, 2017; Atzil and Gendron, 2017; Hommel et al., 2017; Hommel, 2019; Suri and Gross, 2022; Quadt et al., 2022; Del Giudice, 2021)
Basic and Discrete Appraisal Theories: differentiating emotion types by respective evaluations (Kragel and LaBar, 2016; Adolphs, 2017; Ekman and Cordaro, 2011; Lazarus, 2001; Roseman and Smith, 2001; Izard, 2007; Levenson, 2011; Panksepp and Watt, 2011; Scherer et al., 2010)
Dimensional Appraisal Theory: infinite combinations of concerns differentiate an infinite typology of emotions (Grandjean and Scherer, 2008; Scherer, 2009; Scherer and Moors, 2019; Lerner and Keltner, 2000, 2001)
Constitutive Appraisal Theory: emotions are these evaluated concerns (Clore and Ortony, 2000, 2013; Ortony et al., 1988) Constructionist Theories: emotions are constructed from lower-level ingredients (Damasio, 2003; Russell, 2003; Barrett, 2017; LeDoux, 2012)
how to address proximal to distal needs Affective Computing, Reinforcement Learning, and Bayesian: models for differentiating between emotions (Gratch and Marsella, 2004; Scherer et al., 2010; Broekens et al., 2013; Lee et al., 2021; Marsella and Gratch, 2009; Marsella et al., 2010; Poria et al., 2017; Bach and Dayan, 2017; Sennesh et al., 2022; Smith et al., 2019).
Global summative adaptive states trajectory, optimization Constructionist Theory: summarizing overall organism state (LeDoux, 2012) how to characterize own adaptive performance across time See below.
Trajectory the direction of adaptation with regard to comfort zone positive, negative; mood Philosophical Theories: increased likelihood of positive/negative occurrences (Price, 2006; Railton, 2017) how to characterize local direction of environment Reinforcement Learning: momentum or trajectory of reward and punishment prediction errors (Eldar et al., 2016)
Bayesian: mood as hyperpriors (Clark et al., 2018)
Optimization optimal match between the organism and the environment low, high; wellbeing Life Satisfaction: global evaluation of one’s life (Schwarz and Strack, 1999; Strack et al., 1991; Diener and Ryan, 2009; Diener, 2009; Diener et al., 2009; LeDoux, 2012; Krueger and Schkade, 2008; Maddux, 2017; Oishi et al., 2020) how to recognize best adaptive performance across an extensive period of time Bayesian: maximizing momentary valence—using momentary judgments of adaptiveness to evaluate global optimality in adaptiveness (Smith et al., 2022; Miller et al., 2022)
Information Theory: flow as mutual information (Melnikoff et al., 2022)
AFFECTIVE FEATURES momentary information on the adaptive process valence, arousal Allostasis: measures of predicted homeostatic need (Cannon, 1929; Cooper, 2008; Sterling and Eyer, 1988; Carpenter, 2004; McEwen and Wingfield, 2003; Sterling, 2012, 2020; Schulkin and Sterling, 2019; Sennesh et al., 2022) how to characterize momentary status of adaptive process See below.
Valence metric of evaluation of goodness or badness positive, negative Core Affect: valence as ubiquitous across all affective experience (Russell et al., 1989; Russell, 2003; Posner et al., 2005; Kuppens et al., 2013)
Philosophical Theory: minimal metacognition in self-assessment of own adaptiveness (Van de Cruys, 2017)
how to characterize momentary suitability for organism’s adaptivity Reinforcement Learning Implementation: predicted rewards and punishments as ‘happiness’ (Rutledge et al., 2014)
Bayesian Implementation: organism’s predictive evaluation of its adaptiveness or preparedness for its environment (Hesp et al., 2021)
Arousal metric of activation of various systems low, high Core Affect: arousal as ubiquitous across all affective experience (Russell, 2003; Russell et al., 1989; Posner et al., 2005; Kuppens et al., 2013)
Wakeful, Sexual, Autonomic, Physical, and Affective Arousal Theories: activation can occur within different systems at different levels (Duffy, 1957; Zuckerman, 1971; Pribram and McGuinness, 1975; Thayer, 1978; Robbins and Everitt, 1995; Robbins, 1997; Cahill and McGaugh, 1998; Jones, 2003; Eysenck, 2012; Satpute et al., 2019; Satpute et al., 2019; Neiss, 1988; Griffiths, 2013)
how to characterize momentary activation of system Vigor: effort as an outcome of arousal (Niv et al., 2007)

Affective phenomena, being phenomena, are processes, both felt and mechanistic. While they are but a tangle among all the tightly interconnected dynamic processes of a human neurobiological system, we can carve up any set of those processes. When isolated, these processes can be described as algorithms, sequences of steps articulable in words, equations, or code that are executed for specific goals or to solve particular computational problems (Suppes, 1969; Cartwright, 1983; Marr, 2010; Pylyshyn, 1986; Rapaport, 2012; Vardi, 2012; Hill, 2016; Dennett, 2002; Chalmers, 2012; Egan, 2017, 2020). For our purposes, the processes we are most interested in are grounded by the teleological principle above, so that we can identify types of problems among affective phenomena and articulate how affective mechanisms attempt to solve them.

All human affective phenomena are situated in both experience and mechanism from the perspective of the human organism. We distinguish between algorithms that address the relevance of a physical or mental object to the organism, and the algorithms that monitor that adaptation (Fig. 1). Thus, affective phenomena include the two sets of processes below:

  1. Algorithms reflecting affective concerns are processes that address the relevance of physical and mental objects, including things, people, and situations. These concerns signify what is of interest in affective experiences and are reflected in the felt actionability toward that object. These include concerns that have immediate to distal or global relevance to the organism. Several affective concerns can be active at the same time to make up any present moment’s total experience.

  2. Algorithms reflecting affective features are processes that provide information on the adaptive process itself. They are the dimensional metrics of the organism’s own performance in adaptation, integral to all affective concerns, and are reflected in qualitative aspects of affective experience. These include valence and arousal. These features are always present as they mark affective concerns, providing information on them.

Fig. 1. The Human Affectome.

Fig. 1.

This framework is guided by the teleological principle that the collection of human affective phenomena in their entirety can only be accounted for by the nested and intertwined purposes: to ensure viability, to execute operations, to enact relevance, and to entertain abstraction. The bidirectional arrows are used to indicate that the human is enacting—in both being affected by relevant aspects of their actionable world, and affecting that world in order to make it relevant. We characterize affective phenomena as algorithms that address the relevance of the environment and monitor that adaptation. We distinguish between processes that reflect affective concerns and those that reflect affective features. The algorithms that address affective concerns indicate the relevance of a physical or mental object by suggesting actions regarding that object. We can organize one set of these processes in a hierarchy according to the distance from metabolic impact that the actions demanded by the concerns would have. The most immediate concerns (dark blue) are also the most concrete, yet least complex in actionability (i.e., physiological concerns, such as consuming food to alleviate hunger). On the other end of the continuum, more distal concerns (light blue) are increasingly abstract and complicated in terms of actionability, wherein more causal steps are required to achieve homeostatic impact (i.e., operational concerns, such as running away from a dog to alleviate fear, flickering lights for right-of-way on the road to express irritation, or researching more on a topic to address interest). In addition, the set of algorithms addressing affective concerns that do not fall along this continuum of distance from metabolic impact instead summarize across affective concerns. These global concerns include trajectory (green), the direction that the environment is heading toward across time; optimization (yellow), the best match between the environment and organism’s adaptive capacities across a given duration of time—the self-evaluations of aspects of the organism’s own adaptive capacity that are persistent across time. Finally, algorithms expressing affective features provide momentary information on the status of the adaptive process in relation to the comfort zone. These include valence and arousal. Created using Biorender.com.

3.1. Affective Concerns

These processes reflect concerns that address the relevance of physical or mental objects, including things, people, and situations, to the organism’s viability. The organism is proactively oriented toward the object, which is reflected in the felt implications of those objects. The object is, therefore, meaningful to the organism in virtue of the organism’s enactive orientation toward the object—the affective concern (Teroni, 2007; Frijda, 1986, 2017; Bedford, 1956; Kenny and Kenny, 2003; Pitcher, 1965; Leighton, 1985; de Sousa, 1990; Pham, 1998; King, 2009; Deonna et al., 2015; Deonna and Teroni, 2015; Varela et al., 1974; Gibson, 1977; Colombetti and Thompson, 2008; Di Paolo and Thompson, 2014; Shargel and Prinz, 2017; Slaby and Wüschner, 2014; Hufendiek, 2015; Hutto, 2012). As such, affective concerns can be clustered based on whether those operations address a potential breach in viability more or less directly, or as global summaries of those prospective operations. We can thus distinguish between different sets of mechanisms that address affective concerns:

  • Algorithms that reflect hierarchy of immediate to distal concerns organize gradations of enactive relevance, according to the distance from metabolic impact that the actions demanded would have.

  • Algorithms that reflect global concerns summarize across affective concerns in a comprehensive evaluation of adaptive performance across time, rather than being driven by a particular enactive relevance.

Many of these processes can be ongoing at the same time as well as rapidly changing moment to moment (Larsen and McGraw, 2014; Hoemann et al., 2017; Godfrey-Smith, 2020), collectively making up the human’s profile of affective experience in a certain period of time.

3.1.1. Hierarchy

The algorithmic mechanisms that address a hierarchy of immediate to distal concerns reflect predictive actionability toward an object, its relevance, along a gradient or scale of distance to metabolic impact. This gradient can correspond to the number of causal steps needed to address the affective concern, the timescale necessary to achieve homeostatic impact, or its concreteness to abstractness (Gilead et al., 2020; McEwen and Seeman, 1999; Pezzulo et al., 2015). In formal and computational terms, this can be construed as hierarchical depth (Pezzulo et al., 2021; Levin, 2019; Friston, 2020; Tschantz et al., 2022; Tomasello, 2022). Immediate concerns, such as physiological ones, are inferred at a lowest level (i.e., shortest timescale, fewest number of calculations, closest mappings to one-to-one between prediction and sensory data) in the hierarchy of actionability. Distal concerns, such as moral and other abstract concerns, are those at the highest (Scherer, 1982b). Below, we organize ranges of concerns along the continuum of actionable depth.

3.1.1.1. Physiological.

Algorithms reflecting physiological concerns can be addressed by the most immediate or concrete actions required to maintain organismic balance. This set of concerns requires actions that immediately affect the internal environment of one’s own body, therefore, dealing with the adaptive process in the most direct actionable manner. Physiological affective experience arises from interoceptive sensations, and typically reflects the integration of many interoceptive sources (Craig, 2002; Pace-Schott et al., 2019, this issue; Seth, 2013; Seth and Friston, 2016). In the English language, different feeling words along this dimension typically capture the intensity or degree of departure from the organism’s comfort zone. Physiological affective states may pertain to nourishment (e.g., hungry or thirsty; Ombrato and Phillips, 2021), energy levels (e.g., rejuvenated; Podilchak, 1991; Caldwell, 2005; Iwasaki et al., 2005), and internal bodily concerns (e.g., sick; Quadt et al., 2018; pain; Coninx and Stilwell, 2021; Kiverstein et al., 2022), among others. Algorithms addressing physiological concerns seem to be what we tend to refer to as sensation.

3.1.1.2. Operational.

Algorithms reflecting operational concerns are beyond immediate physiological needs as they demand the human organism to operate as a cohesive unit to interact with the environment in sophisticated sequences of actions (Frijda, 1986; LeDoux, 1989; Adolphs and Andler, 2018; Ekman and Cordaro, 2011; Lazarus, 2001; Roseman and Smith, 2001; Izard, 2007; Levenson, 2011; Panksepp and Watt, 2011; Poria et al., 2017; Scherer et al., 2010; Sander et al., 2003, 2005; Grandjean and Scherer, 2008; Scherer, 2009; Scherer and Moors, 2019; Clore and Ortony, 2000, 2013; Ortony et al., 1988; Russell, 2003; Barrett, 2017; Scarantino, 2014; Moors, 2022; Teroni, 2023). The meaning of an operational concern is such that addressing it won’t impact metabolism in a few short steps. In fact, the hypothetical distance from metabolism means that there are many ways to address operational concerns. Given that these concerns demand complex sets of actions over extended periods of time, there are many possibilities for securing those future circumstances for the organism to remain viable. The more sophisticated the course of action, the more abstraction required from the present moment. In addition, while the first-person perspective of human organisms is always maintained, they may cast that perspective to other beings, inanimate objects, or even abstract concepts such that they may consider concerns that are not presently theirs or are imagined. In this way, operational concerns can vary in degree of complexity or abstractness along the higher levels of the hierarchy of distance from metabolic impact, ranging from more immediate and concrete (e.g., anger at a broken printer) or more distal and abstract (e.g., inspired by artwork). More strikingly, however, is the diversity of operational concerns—as they are as numerous as possible operations are for addressing the multidimensional spectrum of relevance to humans. Nevertheless, we offer some examples to demonstrate how potential operations toward objects tend to be clustered:

It seems that what the field often refers to as emotion maps well onto algorithms reflecting operational concerns (Simon, 1967; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990, 2008; Clore and Palmer, 2009; Seth, 2013; Oatley and Johnson-Laird, 2014; Scarantino, 2014; Bach and Dayan, 2017; Atzil and Gendron, 2017; Hommel et al., 2017; Hommel, 2019; Al-Shawaf and Lewis, 2020; Al-Shawaf and Shackelford, 2024; Del Giudice, 2021; Suri and Gross, 2022; Quadt et al., 2022). This should be no surprise considering the term’s etymology, which is inherently tied to movement and action (Dixon, 2003, 2012).

3.1.2. Global

Given that the hierarchical affective concerns above are comprised of separate process occurring at different timepoints and for different durations, other concerns are required to make sense of them combined or more globally. Algorithms reflecting global concerns are not driven by any particular level of enactive relevance, but instead summarize across hierarchical concerns in comprehensive evaluation at a higher timescale. These global concerns are not about particular objects but are rather directed at summations of concerns about particular objects to inform an overall state (LeDoux, 2012). Although integration across hierarchical concerns can be analyzed in a number of different ways, there are two orders of global concerns that are the most obvious and have been studied well in the field: trajectory and optimization.

3.1.2.1. Trajectory.

Algorithms reflecting trajectory concerns summarize hierarchical concerns by reflecting their global direction with regard to the organism’s comfort zone (Schwarz and Clore, 1996; Eldar et al., 2016). These processes take into account whether the slope of adaptation is trending in a positive or negative direction. This means that affective experiences reflecting trajectory concerns often feel like they are not directed at anything in particular or they are directed at everything—as the specificity of relevance is lost in the summary of trajectory (Deonna and Teroni, 2012; Kind, 2013; Bollnow and Boelhauve, 2009; Frijda, 1993; Gendolla, 2000; Crane, 1998; Goldie, 2000; Seager, 1999; Solomon, 1993; de Sousa, 1990; Mendelovici, 2013; Tye, 1995; Arregui, 1996; Kriegel, 2019; Gendolla et al., 2005; Gendolla and Krüsken, 2001). Processes reflecting trajectory concerns usually last for longer periods of time than the short-lived hierarchical concerns. The affective construct that fits this characterization is mood. When one is in a good mood, one can describe its relevant environment as heading in a good direction (Morris and Schnurr, 1989; Price, 2006; Pessiglione et al., 2023).

3.1.2.2. Optimization.

Algorithms of optimization concerns summarize hierarchical concerns by reflecting their global performance at a high temporal scale, indicating the extent to which the human organism has achieved their best match between their adaptive capacities and the environment’s actionable features, across an extended duration of time (Schwarz and Strack, 1999; Strack et al., 1991; Diener and Ryan, 2009; Diener, 2009; Diener et al., 2009; LeDoux, 2012; Krueger and Schkade, 2008; Maddux, 2017; Oishi et al., 2020). These processes assess how the organism is faring overall in their quest for the maintenance of their comfort zone, suggesting wholesale changes to future operations. This usually means that the organism has been able to consistently occupy its comfort zone despite engaging in various operations (De Neve et al., 2013; Lyubomirsky et al., 2005; Eid, 2008; Brown et al., 2020). These algorithms seem to be what the field often refers to as wellbeing, including affective experiences of life satisfaction, authenticity, fulfilment, and self-actualization (Alexander et al., 2021, this issue; Arias et al., 2020, this issue; Schwarz and Strack, 1999; Diener et al., 2013; Krueger and Schkade, 2008; Maddux, 2017; Oishi et al., 2020).

3.2. Affective Features

These processes reflect the momentary information on the adaptive process itself. Algorithms reflecting affective features monitor several standards inherent to the adaptive process:

  • Algorithms that reflect valence provide information on how well or poorly the human organism is doing with respect to the comfort zone.

  • Algorithms that reflect arousal provide information on how much resources should be put to various systems.

Unlike affective concerns, which highlight the object of interest as actionably relevant during an affective experience, affective features are reflected in the qualitative aspects of the experience itself. In addition, each can have multiple dimensions as opposed to being constrained to single scalars with two extremes.

3.2.1. Valence

Across affective concerns, algorithms reflecting valence arise in the hedonic quality of affective experience, often described as pleasure and displeasure, marking how adaptation is faring with respect to the concern at the heart of the affective phenomenon (Becker et al., 2019, this issue). This characteristic of affective phenomena can be construed to have multiple dimensions, such as when both positive and negative valence seem to be present (e.g., nostalgia) (Colombetti, 2005; Keltner and Lerner, 2010; Viinikainen et al., 2010; Batcho, 2013; Vazard, 2022). There are more recent formal accounts of the mechanism of valence—some from the perspective of the environment being good, while others of the view that it is the evaluation of the environment being good (e.g., Rutledge et al., 2014; Joffily and Coricelli, 2013; Hesp et al., 2021)—but it is largely agreed upon that valence is an intrinsic characteristic of affective phenomena, momentarily describing adaptivity (Charland, 2005; Berridge and Kringelbach, 2008; Van de Cruys, 2017; Trofimova, 2018).

3.2.2. Arousal

Across affective concerns, algorithms reflecting arousal assess the quality of intensity in affective experience, often described as low to high, marking the extent of excitation, activation, or mobilization of processes serving a particular concern (Duffy, 1957; Anderson and Adolphs, 2014; Clore et al., 2021). Given that many processes can be implicated in an affective concern, there are many dimensions of arousal (e.g., wakefulness, emotional arousal, sexual arousal, physical activity, attention) (Duffy, 1957; Zuckerman, 1971; Pribram and McGuinness, 1975; Thayer, 1978; Robbins and Everitt, 1995; Robbins, 1997; Cahill and McGaugh, 1998; Jones, 2003; Eysenck, 2012; Satpute et al., 2019; Dolcos et al., 2020, this issue). Although intermediate arousal across time can be an indication of effective adaptivity, these systems can have varying degrees of arousal at any one time (e.g., sexual arousal during fatigue) (Neiss, 1988; Griffiths, 2013).

Taken together, given the rapid change of a dynamic human neurobiological system, these algorithms rarely, if ever, reflect a neutral valence or arousal state, even in periods of high optimization. These two features are usually related but remain orthogonal due to operations that can involve opposing positions on their various spectra (Kuppens et al., 2013, 2017; Yik et al., 2023). These features are ever-present, marking every affective experience and evaluating every hierarchical affective concern. In addition, these are the sources of information used by algorithms of global concerns, responsible for summarizing across the dynamic momentary ones. Finally, these affective features are often what is referred to in the field as ‘affect’, perhaps because they are most inherently tied to the organism’s comfort zone (Russell, 2003; Posner et al., 2005; Barrett and Satpute, 2019). We, however, distinguish them as the affective gauges, while concerns are the focus of affective phenomena.

The feature of motivation has also been suggested as part of affect, often citing dimensions of approach and avoidance (Lang and Bradley, 2008). However, within this framework, given the central role of our teleological principle, it seems that affective phenomena can be more cohesively organized if motivation is taken as an inherent aspect (Klinger, 1975; Nelkin, 1989; Rosenthal, 1991; Di Paolo, 2005; Colombetti, 2014; Cromwell et al., 2020, this issue). Given our teleological principle, an organism has algorithms reflecting affective concerns that address actionability, and thus relevance, of the environment through this enaction. Therefore, affective phenomena inherently involve motivation in that actionability is at the heart of relevance. As such, motivation folds into the inherent enacting of relevance necessary for this framework’s teleological foundation, whereas valence and arousal can be found as distinct capacities in the human organism’s adaptive purpose.

4. Conclusions: How can we study human affective phenomena?

This capstone paper builds a teleological principle to guide the construction of an integrative framework for human affective phenomena, a set of assumptions about what they are and how they work. To account for the entire collection of affective phenomena in humans, we can consider them as arising to entertain abstraction, when enacting relevance, by executing operations, to ensure viability. Based on this principle, affective phenomena can be considered processes that adjust based on the human’s comfort zone (affective concerns) and monitor their adaptive process (affective features). Affective concerns, include a hierarchy of relevance ranging from courses of action with more immediate metabolic impact to those with more distal impact. They also include global concerns that summarize momentary affective concerns on the hierarchy at a higher timescale, such as tracking their trajectory and optimization with respect to the comfort zone. These global concerns use the momentary information that characterize all affective concerns provided by affective features—algorithms that monitor the adaptive process. These include multidimensional metrics of valence, how well or poorly the human organism performs in light of their comfort zone, and arousal, how much resource should be mobilized per necessary system for action. All affective phenomena are experientially and mechanistically organized from the perspective of the human organism, where affective concerns are the focus of the affective experiences and affective features mark them all as qualities of the experiences. This cohesive framework is offered to be used as a synthesized set of metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions organized around a teleological principle that is based on a comprehensive sampling of existing theoretical perspectives on affective phenomena (Table 2).

It is important to note that this is not intended as a semantic taxonomy of affective phenomena and their definitions, but rather as an ontology for how human affective phenomena might follow from a common principle and be related to each other (Fodor, 1998; Egan, 2017, 2020). To truly fold the richness of valid scholarly interests into an encyclopedia of semantic constructs in the field would require a full research program’s worth of time and work, spanning years, or even decades. This endeavor is also not meant to be another falsifiable theory for generating testable hypotheses. What we offer here instead is a principled multidisciplinary theoretical launchpad for many threads of inquiry and a scaffold for hosting specific theories and hypotheses differentiated from or situated among the tenets of this framework (Popper, 1963; Kuhn, 2012; Holton, 1975; Lakatos, 2014, 1978; Laudan, 1978; Godfrey-Smith, 2009; Ormerod, 2009; Jabareen, 2009; Notturno and Popper, 2014).

We hope this framework provides a template for an organized research agenda for the affective sciences moving forward, following similar endeavors in neighboring fields: the Human Genome, organizing the complete set of human genetic information (Schuler et al., 1996), and the Human Connectome, organizing all networks of connectivity in the human brain (Sporns et al., 2005). By the same token, we dub this framework the Human Affectome, where the suffix ‘-ome’ means “all the constituents of, considered collectively or in total” (Oxford English Dictionary, 2023), so that it can be used by the field to organize the collection of algorithms across human affective phenomena. We aim for this framework to encourage the interdisciplinary field of the affective sciences to identify concrete algorithms in order to test specific theories and hypotheses about affective phenomena. This will be an exercise in characterizing and organizing human affective phenomena based on the teleological principle, ultimately, applying this framework to build out the Human Affectome in a principled and comprehensive manner.

For each member of the field, the initial approach we advocate is to triangulate your explanatory goals among these assumptions in order to compare them to others in the field on the basis of the teleological principle described here. Paired with the perspectives incorporated into the teleological synthesis (Table 2), we offer an inverse, preliminary mapping of examples of the field’s existing theoretical accounts onto this framework (Table 3). We also suggest ways the existing theoretical constructs in the field can be situated within this framework (Table 4). We hope these resources can help efforts to regenerate existing theories and hypotheses as well as put forth new ones in terms of the teleologically-principled algorithms here. In this way, different disciplines, subdisciplines, and individual researchers can understand their differing context-dependent interests, disclose their assumptions, and work toward integrating their frameworks in a non-adversarial manner (Dijkstra, 1965; Mitchell, 2003, 2012; Bechtel, 2009; Tabery, 2014; Tabery et al., 2014).

Table 3. Situating Existing Theoretical Accounts within the Human Affectome.

This table summarizes explanatory goals of existing theoretical accounts of affective phenomena with their chosen methodologies and situates them within the algorithmic organization of the Human Affectome. For each entry of theoretical account in the table below, references to relevant theoretical accounts are bolded and references to the Human Affectome are italicized. References included here supplement citations in the main body of the text.

Theoretical Accounts Explanatory Goal Methodology Situated within The Human Affectome
Affective computing matching, recognizing, or simulating affective phenomena often using multidimensional data (Picard, 2000; Gratch and Marsella, 2004; Poria et al., 2017) computational modeling; machine learning Can be used to articulate affective algorithms. To entertain abstraction, Operational concerns.
Appraisal 1. the commonality of relations between evaluations and emotions across populations (discrete appraisal theories; Lazarus, 2001; Roseman and Smith, 2001) subjective report (fixed options); behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; affective computing The actionable orientation with which the human organism evaluates an object as relevant. Affective Concerns.
2. the variability in relations between emotions and combinations of evaluations across populations (dimensional appraisal theories; Grandjean and Scherer, 2008; Scherer, 2009; Scherer and Moors, 2019; Lerner and Keltner, 2000, 2001) subjective report (dimensional responses); behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; affective computing
3. evaluations as distinguishing between what constitutes different emotion types, rather than causing them (OCC model; Ortony et al., 1988) computational modeling and formalism
Autopoiesis See enactive: autopoietic.
Basic emotion the commonality of physiological, neural, and behavioral indicators of types of emotion across populations subjective report (fixed options); behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging Emotions can be grouped by their cluster of operational concerns but are not necessarily biologically determined. Operational concerns.
Bayesian inference 1. predictive inference of explanation for sensory data (Bayesian brain hypothesis or predictive coding) behavioral paradigms; computational modeling and formalism; neuroimaging Objects are evaluated by their meaning. Affective Concerns.
1a. predictive inference of explanation for sensory data based on principle of minimizing free energy by considering action (active inference) Objects are evaluated by their actionable meaning. Affective Concerns.
Cognitive science interdisciplinary field studying the mind behavioral paradigms; computational modeling and formalism; neuroimaging Entertaining abstraction allows us to engage in cognitive science, but we can also question whether cognition and affect are indeed separate. Conclusions.
Computational psychiatry the individual computational mechanisms at play in different people with psychiatric disorders behavioral paradigms; computational modeling and formalism; neuroimaging Mechanisms in psychiatric disorders can be construed as algorithms of adaptivity gone awry. See representation: misrepresentation. To entertain abstraction.
Connectionism the distributed activity across nodes of a neural network (see attractor states in Table 4 and dynamical systems) computational modeling and formalism An organism’s processes unfold across many nodes. To ensure viability.
Constructionist 1. the presence of felt bodily changes during emotional experience (somatic marker hypothesis) (Damasio, 1996) subjective report; behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging Emotions being felt reflections of algorithms addressing operational concerns, which can be inferences of lower-level affective concerns. Operational concerns.
2. the dimensional commonalities across all emotional experiences (core affect) (Russell, 2003; Russell et al., 1989; Posner et al., 2005; Kuppens et al., 2013) subjective report (dimensional responses); behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging
3. the variability in subjective reports of emotional experience (theory of constructed emotion) (Barrett, 2017) subjective report (free labeling); behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging
Dynamical systems the dynamics of distributed activity across time (see attractor states in Table 4) computational modeling and formalism An organism’s processes unfold across time as a complex system. To ensure viability.
Embedded interactions between organism and environment shape organism’s capacities (see situated) conceptual analysis The human organism must interact with the environment to enact its relevance. To enact relevance.
Embodied mental processes involve whole body, not just brain and nervous system subjective report; behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging; conceptual analysis All processes in an organism are contributing to enacting relevance. To enact relevance.
Enactive 1. everything an organism does, including cognition, is active—specifically, as interactions with its environment computational modeling and formalism; conceptual analysis conceptual analysis The Human Affectome is guided, in part, by the Teleological Principle that human organisms enact relevance. All affective phenomena are enactive. (Emotions, as references to operational concerns, can therefore also be considered enactive.)
1a. to be an organism is to self-generate and self-distinguish (autopoietic) To ensure viability.
1b. the organism both makes sense of the world and makes the world make sense (sense-making) To enact relevance.
2. how perception and action can guide each other (sensorimotor) subjective report; behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging;conceptual analysis To enact relevance.
3. enaction allows us to do away with representation (radical) conceptual analysis The Human Affectome does not assume a strong claim on representation, but representations can be used to describe algorithms. To enact relevance, To entertain abstraction.
Evolutionary affective phenomena can be explained based on aspects that developed via natural selection (Izard, 1978; Nesse, 1990; Porges, 1997; Panksepp, 1998; LeDoux, 2012; Al-Shawaf et al., 2016). behavioral paradigms; neuroimaging; conceptual analysis The Human Affectome does not take up an explicit evolutionary perspective, despite the assumption that part of the purpose of affective phenomena is to ensure viability. All else, such as metabolism, reproduction, and evolution, arise from necessarily being a unity in the first place (Varela et al., 1974; Maturana, 1980)
Extended the mind extends further than the body to objects used in a relevantly similar and reliable way (Clark and Chalmers, 1998) conceptual analysis The Human Affectome does not assume an extended mind, but merely highlights the interactions between human organism and environment. To enact relevance.
Goal-directed theories integration of dimensional appraisal and constructionist theories of emotion (Moors, 2017a; 2017b) conceptual analysis Emotion types grounded by clusters of goal-orientedness or action tendency. Operational concerns. See goal in Table 4.
Homeostasis how organism remains within viable states despite environmental change behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging; conceptual analysis This is entailed by autopoiesis. To ensure viability.
Human Affectome what affective phenomena are and how they work based on why they exist conceptual analysis Entire framework of the Human Affectome.
Intentionality the aspect of a mental state being about something conceptual analysis; phenomenological analysis Objects are relevant to an organism based on its actionable orientation toward them; allows distinction between affective types based on clusters of affective concerns. Affective Concerns.
projecting intentionality onto something whose behavior seems to have it (intentional stance) We can use the intentional stance to articulate processes, whether the source has intentionality or not. To entertain abstraction.
Moral emotions emotions that concern beliefs about violation behavioral paradigms; conceptual analysis Moral emotions as affective experiences grounded by algorithms addressing a moral subset of operational concerns. Operational concerns.
Motivational theories 1. the drive to act in emotion (action tendency; Frijda, 1986); see appraisal.
2. the evaluation in emotion in light of the drive to act (felt bodily attitude; Deonna and Teroni, 2012)
3. the drive to act as well as emotional actions (motivational theory of emotions; Scarantino, 2014)
conceptual analysis; behavioral paradigms; physiological measures; neuroimaging The actionability implied by an object in an affective phenomenon. To enact relevance, Affective Concerns.
Phenomenology the rich structure in the meaning of experience conceptual analysis This rich structure accompanies the organization of felt actionability implied by objects in affective phenomena. To enact relevance.
Reinforcement learning 1. learned behavior based on reward behavioral paradigms; computational modeling Reward as intrinsic rather than in the environment. To enact relevance.
1a. momentary affect as a function of reward Valence as metric of evaluation of goodness or badness. Valence.
1b. mood as a momentum of reward Mood as trajectory. Trajectory concerns.
Representation 1. mental content; can be written as propositional attitudes conceptual analysis We human organisms can seem as if we have representations, but this framework does not make a strong claim on representationalism. See intentionality: intentional stance.
1a. mental content can be unjustified (misrepresentation) If meaning is captured by actionability, then unjustified meaning is associated with maladaptivity. To entertain abstraction.
2. providing sufficient coverage of the interests of members within a group; in this case, of the affective field (see pragmatic in Table 1) The Human Affectome provides a sampling of Western perspectives, but lacks in coverage of Eastern or non-analytic approaches. Conclusions.
Situated the mind is shaped by environment in the interactions that are possible; see embedded; can be applied to affective phenomena (situated affectivity; Griffiths and Scarantino, 2005; Colombetti, 2010; Piredda, 2020; Stephan and Walter, 2020) conceptual analysis The human organism’s capacities are shaped by possible interactions with the environment. To enact relevance.
Unconscious emotions 1. the behavior of organisms whose mental state we cannot access behavioral paradigms; physiological measures, neuroimaging; computational modeling The systematicity in feeling can be inferred to explain behavior, assuming that system is rational. See intentionality. To enact relevance.
2. conscious feelings that the organism is not aware of on a higher-order, reflective level conceptual analysis Emotions, as affective experiences, are feelings that are minimally felt, but do not require reflection or reporting to be felt. To enact relevance.

Table 4. Situating Existing Theoretical Constructs within the Human Affectome.

This table summarizes meaning—and senses of meaning—of existing theoretical constructs of affective phenomena, situating them within the algorithmic organization of the Human Affectome. Within the entries below, references to relevant theoretical accounts are bolded; references to other theoretical constructs within this table are bolded and italicized; and references to the Human Affectome are italicized. References included here supplement citations in the main body of the text.

Theoretical Construct Sense Situated Within Human Affectome
Affect 1. all affective phenomena Affectome: all of the specified constituents of an organism’s system of algorithms for affective phenomena, considered collectively or in total. The Human Affectome.
2. aspects that characterize affective phenomena Affective features: the dimensional metrics of the organism’s own performance in predictive adaptation, integral to all affective concerns, and reflected in qualitative aspects of affective experience. See valence and arousal. Affective Features.
3. valence and arousal (core affect; Russell, 2003; Russell et al., 1989; Posner et al., 2005; Kuppens et al., 2013); sometimes also dominance (Mehrabian and Russell, 1974; Bakker et al., 2014) See valence and arousal. Affective Features.
Dominance can be seen as the manner in which the human organism is poised to act upon the world (see appraisal in Table 3); Affective Concerns. It can also be seen as the sense of agency the agent has or sense of control over intended outcomes or goal; Conclusions.
Affordance actionability features of objects in the environment To execute operations, Affective Concerns.
Allostasis predictive process to maintain stability despite change Dynamic regulation and navigation within a complex and changing environment in order to anticipate the approach of a fatal state before it approaches, i.e., to safeguard homeostasis. See homeostasis. To execute operations.
Allostatic load chronic burden on allostasis The repeated surpassing of an organism’s adaptive capabilities in anticipating its own needs due to a persistently difficult environment, usually consisting of persistent acute stress, resulting in chronic stress (i.e., bearing allostatic load). See allostasis and stress. To execute operations.
Algorithm description of process Sequences of steps executed for the sake of a goal. The Human Affectome.
Arousal an aspect of affective experience The metric of excitation, activation, or energy mobilization within different systems indicating the urgency to act; reflected in the aspect of intensity of an affective experience; measured as magnitude from low to high for each kind of arousal based on the system of interest or as a whole (e.g., wakefulness, emotional arousal, sexual arousal, physical activity, attention, etc.). Affective Feature: Arousal.
Attractor states configurations that a complex system is attracted to (see connectionism and dynamical systems in Table 3) To ensure viability and in executing operations, a complex organism will hover around states of relative stability.
Comfort zone set of states Range of comfortable states which an organism seeks to sustain. See allostasis. To execute operations.
Consciousness 1. qualitative state See feeling. To enact relevance.
2. phenomenology See feeling: phenomenology. To enact relevance.
3. higher-order, reflective experience See metacognition. To entertain abstraction.
Emotion a type of affective experience Affective experiences grounded in algorithms that reflect operational concerns, implications of an object’s actionability in terms of sophisticated sequences of actions.
Episodes duration of time Affective experiences are episodes of experience. To enact relevance.
Expression articulation of affective phenomenon through implicit or explicit means Human organisms express affective phenomena to communicate with others as part of their adaptive operations. To entertain abstraction.
Feeling 1. affective experiences First-person, conscious mental states with qualitative character that is experienced which reflect affective algorithms. To enact relevance.
2. aspect of experience (felt) Raw qualitative aspect that marks all experience. See qualia. To enact relevance.
3. experience Having a what it’s like and rich structure. See qualia and phenomenology. To enact relevance.
4. metacognitive awareness Higher-order, reflective conscious awareness of being in an affective state; can sometimes be verbalized in subjective report. See subjective report. To entertain abstraction, Conclusions.
Goal 1. final state that explains development (Aristotle, 1999) As a dynamic, complex system, the human organism is not seeking, whether implicitly or explicitly, a final state. It can be considered a self-producing and self-distinguishing act. See enactive: autopoiesis in Table 3. To ensure viability.
2. purpose that explains certain capacities or characteristics (Mayr, 1998, 1985; Cartwright, 1986; Schlosser, 1998; McLaughlin, 2000; Ward et al., 2017) A Teleological Principle, an assumption about what purpose explains capacities and characteristics associated with affective phenomena, can ground other assumptions in the field. See teleology in Table 1 and goal-directed in Table 3.
3. hypothetical end result that explains explicit deliberation, decision, and planning Human organisms can explicitly aim for goals as individual agents or among a group in a collaborative context. See metacognition and theory of mind. To entertain
Interoception the afferent signaling, central neural, and perceptual representation of the internal (physiological) state of the body Interoception is among the internal processes in organism’s adaptivity. To enact relevance.
Language designating and using symbols to communicate abstract meaning Human organisms can associate labels with abstracted operations. To entertain abstraction, Conclusions.
Mental action actions can be taken internally without interaction with the outside world The organism uses mental actions to orchestrate operations. To execute operations.
Metacognition 1. reflective consciousness Higher-order processing of oneself that is necessary for organisms to be able to subjectively report on their feelings but is not necessary for feeling itself. See subjective report. To entertain abstraction, Conclusions.
2. reported confidence A measurement of subjective report about how confident a participant is about their responses, which is used as a parameter of precision in understanding that participant’s algorithms. See metacognition: 3. Conclusions.
3. parameter of precision A parameter used in algorithm which reflects an evaluation of weighting of a lower-level parameter, e.g., sensation, valence. See sensation and valence. To entertain abstraction, Valence, Conclusions.
Mood a type of affective experience An affective experience reflecting the direction or momentum of positive or negative outcomes in the environment. Trajectory concerns.
Motivation an aspect of being actionably oriented toward the world The entire Human Affectome is motivational. Not among Affective Features.
Qualia quality, or ‘what it’s like’, of conscious experience Affective experiences have qualities that mark them—Affective Features. To enact relevance.
Reward inherent relevance of an object, learned with experience See reinforcement learning in Table 3.
Self 1. perspective from which conscious experience is organized All affective phenomena are organized from the perspective of a self. To enact relevance.
2. metacognitive reflection of self as an object Human organism can reflect abstractly upon itself. See metacognition: 1. To entertain abstraction.
Sensation a type of affective experience An affective experience grounded in algorithms reflecting physiological concerns.
Stress a type of affective experience Acute or chronic state of intense affective experience which can lead to allostatic load if persistent. To execute operations.
Subjective report (self-report) behavioral operationalization Verbalized account of one’s feelings, which requires reflective, higher-order metacognition; an empirical measurement used to gain insight into the systematicity of feeling, but not required for feeling itself. See metacognition. Conclusions.
Theory of mind the capacity to infer the mental state of others Human organisms can project their adaptive perspective to others in order to cooperate or to abstract about non-agentive objects. See intentionality: intentional stance in Table 3. To entertain abstraction.
Umwelten the way the world appears to an organism based on its adaptive capacities The world appears to the human organism in a manner based on their adaptive capacities. To enact relevance.
Valence an aspect of affective experience The metric of how good or bad something is evaluated with relation to affective concerns indicating how suited the human organism is; reflected in the aspect of pleasure or displeasure of an affective experience; measured as low to high positive or negative fit. Affective Feature: Valence.
Wellbeing 1. life satisfaction An affective experience reflecting the optimal match between the organism’s adaptive capabilities and the environment’s demands. Optimization concerns.
2. mood See mood. Trajectory concerns.
3. momentary affective state See valence. Valence, Optimization.

For the time being, we highlight a few avenues of guidance implicit in this paper:

Firstly, assuming affective phenomena to be mechanistic is not unique to empirical approaches. Beyond the sciences, affective phenomena are acknowledged as processes of change that not only shape the nature of the humanities but are a major part of the content among the humanities (Brouwer et al., 2017; Desmet and Schifferstein, 2008; Hogan, 2011, 2017; Juslin, 2013; Kaneko et al., 2018; Mastandrea et al., 2019; Menninghaus et al., 2019; Scherer and Coutinho, 2013; Silvia, 2005; Van Dyck et al., 2017a). On the other hand, among the sciences, this mechanistic assumption need not result in methodological factions (Lange, 1885; Scherer, 1982a; Schwarz and Clore, Averill et al., 1983, 1994; Frijda, 1994; Keltner and Gross, 1999; Cacioppo et al., 1999; Mill, 1856; Whewell, 1858; Machamer et al., 2000; Glennan, 2002, 2008; Azzouni, 2004; Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 2005; Chang, 2005; Morganti and Tahko, 2017; Ivanova and Farr, 2020; Levenstein et al., 2023). The classical cognitivist approach—that affective mechanisms transform inputs into outputs or are otherwise processes between stimulus and response—accords with our felt experience and has underpinned efforts to localize affective processes to specific brain regions (Haugeland, 1978, 1997; Marr, 2010; Kanwisher, 2010; Cromwell and Papadelis, 2022, this issue). This is not incompatible with more distributed and dynamic perspectives—that these processes are interactions between nodes of a neural network that change in configuration over time (connectionism) (Fodor and Pylyshyn, 1988; Bechtel and Abrahamsen, 1991; Clark, 1989)—which invite the articulation of those processes of change in formal terms with differential equations (dynamical systems theory) (Horgan and Tienson, 1996; Thelen and Smith, 1994; Port and Van Gelder, 1995; Clark, 1998; Boone and Piccinini, 2016). These views can be reconciled by considering the classical linear and localizable processes as emergent from distributed and dynamic neural activity (Friston and Price, 2001a, 2001b; De Wolf and Holvoet, 2005).

Secondly, we do not present an explicit formal or computational model precisely to encourage the multiple empirical interpretations of this framework by articulating the algorithms for your own hypotheses. We will caution that selecting a modeling framework introduces assumptions as well. For example, some frameworks that invoke the concept of reward tend to assume relevance and action to be separate (reinforcement learning) (Kaelbling et al., 1996; Wiering and Van Otterlo, 2012; Sequeira et al., 2011; Moerland et al., 2018; Grahek et al., 2020; Levine, 2018; Sutton and Barto, 2018), while others view relevance as probabilistic (Bayesian inference), going as far as building relevance from action (active inference) (Friston et al., 2017; Attias, 2003; Botvinick and Toussaint, 2012; Knill and Pouget, 2004; Friston and Kiebel, 2009; Allen and Friston, 2018; Friston et al., 2013; Ramstead et al., 2020; Sajid et al., 2021; Clark, 2013, 2015, 1997; Parr et al., 2022; Kiverstein et al., 2022; Smith et al., 2019, 2022; Millidge et al., 2020; Miłkowski and Litwin, 2022; Di Paolo et al., 2022; Nave, 2023). Notwithstanding accounts that mix these methods, none to our knowledge have successfully built algorithms of affective phenomena up from the earliest principle of an organism, although the groundwork is being laid (Prokopenko et al., 2009; Fernández et al., 2014; Ringstrom, 2022; Heylighen and Busseniers, 2023; Hodson et al., 2023; Broekens et al., 2013; Cunningham et al., 2013; Scherer et al., 2010; Marsella and Gratch, 2009; Marsella et al., 2010, 2016; Calvo et al., 2015; Poria et al., 2017; Emanuel and Eldar, 2023).

Thirdly, we do not make a strong claim about consciousness (Berridge and Winkielman, 2003; Winkielman and Berridge, 2004; Hatzimoysis, 2007; Lacewing, 2007; de Waal, 2011; Carmel and Sprevak, 2014; Díaz, 2023; Reuter, forthcoming). We do assume, however, that the affective experiences discussed here are feelings and, therefore, are felt in the broadest sense (i.e., qualitatively organized by a unified perspective). As such, a first-person perspective from oneself—an assumption in the Human Affectome—should be taken seriously. One approach that has gained traction in the cognitive sciences is one that investigates the correlations between the structure of experience and the organization of neurocomputational mechanism (neurophenomenology) (Gallagher, 1997; Van Gelder, 2022; Varela, 1996; Thompson et al., 2005). This can be done through rigorous comparison of subjective report and case studies with neuroimaging and behavioral measures (Weiskrantz, 1997; Dehaene et al., 2003; Koch and Tsuchiya, 2007; Rosenthal, 2019; Cunningham, 1977; Scarantino, 2017; Wharton and de Saussure, 2023). Especially when it comes to psychopathology, investigation into aberrations in the capacity to maintain a perceived and actionable comfort zone is paramount—and methodologies to perform such studies are on the rise (Metzinger, 2003a, 2003b, 2013; Möller et al., 2021). For example, given the fundamental role that actionability plays in this framework, research into an integrated sense of agency (Georgieff and Jeannerod, 1998; Horgan et al., 2003; Engbert et al., 2008; Gallagher, 2000; Hohwy, 2007; de Haan and de Bruin, 2010; David, 2012; Synofzik et al., 2008, 2013; Roessler and Eilan, 2003; Pacherie, 2008; Gallagher, 2012; Moore, 2016; Haggard, 2017; Braun et al., 2018) as well as sense of control over intended outcomes (Pacherie, 2007; Rotter, 1966; Lachman and Weaver, 1998; Bandura, 1977, 2006; Na et al., 2023) in relation to affective phenomena can be expanded.

Moreover, we should not shut out language and thought as non-affective phenomena. Indeed, both communication and thinking have felt aspect themselves (Siewert, 2012; Siewert, 1998; Pitt, 2004; Bayne et al., 2014; Kind, 2001; Tulving, 1987; Roediger, 1990; Teroni, 2017; Gardiner and Java, 2019; Wharton et al., 2021). Instead, we should emphasize these abstract activities as active constructs in our picture of affective phenomena, such as by considering them determinants of relevance and, thus, generating activities of subjective report and communication as dynamic processes in themselves (Wharton and de Saussure, 2023; Satpute et al., 2020; Ryan et al., 2023; Gohm and Clore, 2000; Robinson and Clore, 2002; Barrett, 2004; Cowen and Keltner, 2017; Russell, 1980; Watson et al., 1988; Bradley and Lang, 1994; Boehner et al., 2007; Wilhelm and Grossman, 2010; Betella and Verschure, 2016; Shiffman et al., 2008; Csikszentmihalyi and Larson, 2014; Kuppens et al., 2022; Betz et al., 2019; Satpute and Lindquist, 2021; Ericcson and Simon, 1993; Wilson, 1994; Schwarz, 1999; Dehaene et al., 2003; Mauss and Robinson, 2009; Barrett et al., 2011; Lindquist et al., 2015; Harmon-Jones et al., 2016; Rosenthal, 2019; Li et al., 2023; Teoh et al., 2023). In addition, we should acknowledge that we academics, as humans ourselves, are performing the very same activity of abstraction and—if we choose not to investigate ourselves as affect-ridden researchers—should at least acknowledge and disclose the assumptions from our pragmatic context and theoretical virtues (e.g., Scarantino, 2016). All in all, we should take seriously the question whether cognition is truly separate from affect (Wharton and de Saussure, 2023; Lyons, 2005; Adolphs and Damasio, 2001; Duncan and Barrett, 2007; Okon-Singer et al., 2015; Zajonc et al., 1982, 2014; Bower et al., 1997; Isen, 1984; Hoffman, 1986; LeDoux, 1989; Izard, 1992; Ochsner and Phelps, 2007; Forgas, 2000; Storbeck and Clore, 2007).

Relatedly, as interdisciplinary and integrative as this framework is, only Western academic perspectives have been considered, while Eastern ones as well as Indigenous perspectives have not been breached. This is a significant drawback as Western academia tends to take a metaphysically categorical approach to affect, considering it separate from cognition, while this is not necessarily the case among Eastern and Indigenous psychologies and philosophies (e.g., Mercado, 1994; Reyes, 2015; Rošker, 2021; Sundararajan, 2015; Tuske, 2021; Zhou et al., 2021; Yik, 2010; Pernau, 2021; Briggs, 2010; Choi et al., 2007; Crivelli et al., 2016; Beatty, 2014, 2019; Allard, 2022; Michaels and Wulf, 2020; Pak, 2021; Yik et al., 2023). Further research and collaboration among those from different cultures of academia as well as beyond is highly encouraged.

In addition, areas of academic and industry perspectives in affective research beyond philosophy and science have not been touched upon, such as design and architecture (Desmet, 2003; Desmet et al., 2021; Hassenzahl and Tractinsky, 2006; Norman, 2002, 2013; Fokkinga and Desmet, 2022). These sectors pose fertile collaboration in studying affective phenomena in new ways—especially given the growing scientific interest in the embodiment of affect.

Finally, although this framework exclusively covers humans—obliging us to incorporate abstraction, language, and self-report—its core tenets can apply to non-human animals as well. This could involve a nested teleological principle focusing on ensuring viability, executing operations, and enacting relevance, while motivating a more limited set of affective concerns and features. Converging on such teleologically grounded affective phenomena in this way could promote translation and collaboration across levels of investigation in the context of non-human animal affective research.

In conclusion, assumptions ruling academic research into affective explananda have been tangled and discussed in disparate pockets of inquiry—each field, subfield, and researcher, with their own explanatory motives. In this capstone paper of the special issue “Towards an Integrated Understanding of the Human Affectome”, we present the Human Affectome—a set of metaphysical and mechanistic assumptions guided by a common teleological principle based on a synthesis of interdisciplinary perspectives—in order to motivate a comprehensive and organized research agenda that differentiates the theoretical aspects of this integrative framework into specific theories and hypotheses. As we mentioned in the Introduction, we hope that you have taken something away, no matter how small the message and no matter what background you have in affect, from this endeavor and are inspired to bridge our rich and sprawling field further. We hope that we are one step closer to not only an integrated understanding of human affective phenomena, but an integrated field for affective research.

Acknowledgements

We are especially grateful to the support provided by Professor Jaak Panksepp in the early stages of this project prior to his passing on the 18th April 2017. We extend special thanks to Dr. Denis Tarasov, Chief Software Architect at Meanotek AI, for his early efforts to help us understand the full range of feeling words that could be retrieved using a big data approach. In addition, we would like to give a special thanks to Drs. Ralph Adolphs, Roger Clem, Antonio Damasio, Roeland Heerema, Joseph LeDoux, Ifat Levy, James H. McIntyre, Seth Pollak, Disa Sauter, Norbert Schwarz, Fabrice Teroni, Dave Ward, and Tim Wharton, for their guidance and feedback. A. Ibanez was supported by grants from Takeda; CW2680521; CONICET; FONCYT-PICT (2017-1818, 2017-1820); ANID/FONDECYT Regular (1210195, 1210176, 1220995); ANID/FONDAP (15150012); ANID/PIA/ANILLOS ACT210096; and the Multi-Partner Consortium to Expand Dementia Research in Latin America (ReDLat), funded by the National Institutes of Aging of the National Institutes of Health under award number R01AG057234, an Alzheimer’s Association grant (SG-20-725707-ReDLat), the Rainwater Foundation, and the Global Brain Health Institute. A. Lawrence was supported by the Scottish Government Strategic Research Programme (Theme 2) and by the BBSRC Institute Strategic Programme to the Roslin Institute (ISP3; Theme 2). A.H. Kemp acknowledges support from a CHERISH-DE international mobility fellowship that supported his contributions to the Human Affectome Project. He was also supported by research funding for patient and public benefit awarded by Health and Care Research Wales (RfPPB-18-1502). B. Derntl was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG, DE2319/6-1, DE2319/9-1). C.A. Lowry was supported by the National Institute of Mental Health [R21MH116263], the National Center for Complementary and Integrative Health [R01AT010005 and R41AT011390], the Colorado Office of Economic Development and International Trade (OEDIT) Advanced Industries Accelerator Program [CTGG1-2020-3064] and the Department of the Navy, Office of Naval Research Multidisciplinary University Research Initiative (MURI) Award [N00014-15-1-2809]. C.D. Ladou-frameworkceur was funded by the National Institute of Mental Health [R01MH099007, R01MH103241, R01MH101096]. C.H.Y. Fu acknowledges support from MRC grant (G0802594). D. Ellingsen was supported by the Norwegian Research Council/Marie Sklodowska-Curie Actions [FRICON/COFUND-240553/F20].D. Schiller is supported by NIH grants [R01MH122611], [R01MH123069], and The Misophonia Research Fund. E. Stefanova was supported by Ministry of Education Science, and Technological Development, Republic of Serbia (Project No. 175090), Alzheimer Association grant for Promoting Diversity. E. Stern and C. Brown are supported by National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH) R01 MH111794, R33 MH107589, and R01 MH126981 awarded to ERS. E.D. Musser was supported by the National Institutes of Mental Health [R03MH110812-02, K23MH117280]. E.F. Pace-Schott was supported by MH109638, MH115279.F. Dolcos acknowledges support received from a Helen Corley Petit Scholarship in Liberal Arts and Sciences, an Emanuel Donchin Professorial Scholarship in Psychology, and an Arnold O. Beckman Award from the University of Illinois, during his contribution to this article. G. Northoff acknowledges that this work was funded by PSI and CIHR as well as the European Human Brain project. G. Pinna is supported in part by the United States U. S. Department of Defense Grant W81XWH-15-1-0521. G. Riva and P. Cipresso were funded by the Italian MIUR research project “Unlocking the memory of the body: Virtual Reality in Anorexia Nervosa” (201597WTTM) and by the Italian Ministry of Health research project “High-end and Low-End Virtual Reality Systems for the Rehabilitation of Frailty in the Elderly” (PE-2013-0235594). J. Gatt was supported by a NHMRC Project Grant (APP1122816). J. Raber was supported in part by the United States Department of Defense Grant W81XWH-17-1-0193, NIH RF1 AG059088, R21 ES027943, R21 AG065914, R01 NS080866, RF1 AG058273, R01 HL140182, R21 CA223461, U19 AT010829, and by NASA NSCOR NNX15AK13G to M.Weil (OHSU subcontract to J. Raber) and NASA NASA 80NSSC19K0498 -P00001 to J. Baker (subcontract to J. Raber). J. Williams and C. Huggins were supported by the Northwood Trust. J.E. Swain was supported by the Research Foundation for the State University of New York (SUNY), the National Institutes for Health (NIH)/National Institute on Drug Abuse (NIDA) R01 DA047336 and R01 DA047094, and the Peter F. McManus Charitable Trust. L. Booij was supported by a career award from the Fonds de Recherche du Québec - Santé. L. M. Bylsma was supported by MH118218, MH104325, MH101750 and a NARSAD Young Investigator Award from the Brain and Behavior Research Foundation (BBRF) and Vital Projects Fund, Inc. M. Bensafi was supported by the French-German ANR/DFG SHS FRAL program [MEROD Project, ANR-15-FRAL-0002]. M. Joffily was supported by the LABEX CORTEX of the University of Lyon [ANR-11-LABX-0042] and the program Investissements d’Avenir of the French National Research Agency (ANR) [ANR-11-IDEX-007]. M.Owolabi was supported by SIREN (U54HG007479), SIBS Genomics (R01NS107900), SIBS Gen Gen (R01NS107900-02S1), ARISES (R01NS115944-01), H3Africa CVD Supplement (3U24HG009780-03S5), CaNVAS (1R01NS114045-01), Sub-Saharan Africa Conference on Stroke (SSACS) 1R13NS115395-01A1 and Training Africans to Lead and Execute Neurological Trials & Studies (TALENTS) D43TW012030 from the NIH. M. Owolabi and K. Kusi-Mensah would like to thank the following medical students of the Kwame Nkrumah University of Science and Technology, Kumasi-Ghana, class of 2019 for volunteering their time to work on the classification of affect words in English: Gladys Akrofi, Loretta Agyare, Felix Allotey and Edwin Akomaning. M. Polyakova was supported by the International Max Planck Research School (IMPRS) NeuroCom by the Max Planck Society. M.-F. Marin was supported by an award from the Fonds de recherche du Qúebec - Santé (FRQS). M.L. Schroeter was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG; SCHR 774/5-1), by the German Consortium for Frontotemporal Lobar Degeneration, funded by the German Federal Ministry of Education and Research (BMBF; FKZ 01GI1007A), by the Parkinson’s Disease Foundation (PDFIRG-1307), the Michael J Fox Foundation (MJFF-11362), by LIFE -Leipzig Research Center for Civilization Diseases, Universität Leipzig, and by the eHealthSax Initiative of the Sächsische Aufbaubank (SAB). M. Weymar was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG; WE 4801/3-1, WE 4801/6-1). N. Abe was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number 17H06054 and 19H00628. O. Gosseries and S. Laureys are research associate and research director at FRS-FNRS respectively and acknowledge support from the Human Brain Project SGA3 (No. 945539). P. Eslinger was supported by NIH/NIEHS RO1 ES019672 and the Alzheimer’s Therapeutic Research Institute/USC/NIA. P. Frewen was supported by the Canadian Institutes for Health Research, Canadian Department of National Defense, and Veteran’s Affairs Canada. P.S. Sachdev was supported by an Investigator Grant from the National Health and Medical Research Council of Australia. R. Alexander was supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program Domestic Scholarship. R.C.K Chan was supported by the National Natural Foundation of China [81571317], National Key Research and Development Programme [2016YFC0906402], and the Beijing Municipal Science & Technology Commission [Z161100000216138]. R.C.K Chan and Y. Wang were supported by the CAS Key Laboratory of Mental Health, Institute of Psychology. R. Nusslock was supported by the National Institute of Mental Health [MH100117; MH077908] and the National Institute on Drug Abuse [DAO51361]. R. Palermo and M. Willis were supported by the the Australian Research Council (ARC) Centre of Excellence for Cognition and its Disorders (CE110001021). S. Boutros was supported by National Science Foundation GVPRS0014D9, NIA T32 AG055378, and F31 AG067269. S. Krach was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG KR 3803/9–1; KR 3803/11–1). S.Schweizer was supported by the Wellcome Trust, Sir Henry Wellcome Fellowship, 209127/Z/17/Z. S. Urben was supported by Swiss National Science Foundation (SPARK# CRSK-3_190490). S.G. Hofmann receives financial support by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation (as part of the Alexander von Humboldt Professur) and the Hessische Ministerium für Wissenschaft und Kunst (as part of the LOEWE Spitzenprofessur). He also receives compensation for his work as editor from SpringerNature and royalties and payments for his work from various publishers. T. Aue was supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation (grants PP00P1_150492 and PP00P1_183709). T.E. Van Rheenen was supported by a National Health and Medical Research Council (NHMRC) Early Career Fellowship (1088785) and a Dame Kate Campbell Fellowship from the University of Melbourne. T. Jovanovic was supported by the National Institute of Mental Health (R01MH111682, R01MH100122, R01MH110364). T.Olino was supported by the National Institute of Mental Health [R01MH107495]. Y. Wang was supported by the National Natural Foundation of China [31871114].

Footnotes

Declaration of Generative AI and AI-Assisted Technologies in the Writing Process

During the preparation of this work, the authors used GPT-4 for edits. After using this tool, the authors reviewed and edited the content as needed and take full responsibility for the content of the publication.

Data Availability

No data was used for the research described in the article.

References

  1. Achinstein P, 1983. The nature of explanation. Oxford University Press, USA. [Google Scholar]
  2. Adolphs R, 2017. How should neuroscience study emotions? By distinguishing emotion states, concepts, and experiences. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci 12 (1), 24–31. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Adolphs R, Damasio AR, 2001. The interaction of affect and cognition: a neurobiological perspective. In Handbook of affect and social cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers,, pp. 27–49. [Google Scholar]
  4. Adolphs R, Anderson DJ, 2018. The neuroscience of emotion: a new synthesis. In The Neuroscience of Emotion. Princeton University Press. 10.23943/9781400889914. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  5. Adolphs R, Andler D, 2018. Investigating emotions as functional states distinct from feelings. Emot. Rev.: J. Int. Soc. Res. Emot 10 (3), 191–201. 10.1177/1754073918765662. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  6. Adolphs R, Mlodinow L, Barrett LF, 2019. What is an emotion? Curr. Biol 29 (20), R1060–R1064. 10.1016/j.cub.2019.09.008. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Alexander R, Aragón OR, Bookwala J, Cherbuin N, Gatt JM, Kahrilas IJ, Kästner N, Lawrence A, Lowe L, Morrison RG, Mueller SC, Nusslock R, Papadelis C, Polnaszek KL, Helene Richter S, Silton RL, Styliadis C, 2021. The neuroscience of positive emotions and affect: Implications for cultivating happiness and wellbeing (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 121, 220–249. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.12.002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  8. Alia-Klein N, Gan G, Gilam G, Bezek J, Bruno A, Denson TF, Hendler T, Lowe L, Mariotti V, Muscatello MR, Palumbo S, Pellegrini S, Pietrini P, Rizzo A, Verona E, 2020. The feeling of anger: From brain networks to linguistic expressions (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 108, 480–497. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.12.002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Allard O (2022). Anthropology of Emotion. Oxford Bibliographies. DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780199766567-0161. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  10. Allen M, Friston KJ, 2018. From cognitivism to autopoiesis: Towards a computational framework for the embodied mind. Synthese 195 (6), 2459–2482. 10.1007/s11229-016-1288-5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Al-Shawaf L, Lewis DMG, 2020. Evolutionary psychology and the emotions. In: Zeigler-Hill V, Shackelford TK (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences. Springer International Publishing, pp. 1452–1461. 10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_516. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  12. Al-Shawaf L, Shackelford TK, 2024. The Oxford Handbook of Evolution and the Emotions. Oxford University Press,, New York. [Google Scholar]
  13. Al-Shawaf L, Conroy-Beam D, Asao K, Buss DM, 2016. Human emotions: An evolutionary psychological perspective. Emotion Review 8 (2), 173–186. [Google Scholar]
  14. Álvarez-González A, 2023. Emotional phenomenology: a new puzzle. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 10.1007/s11097-023-09887-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  15. Andersen H, Wagenknecht S, 2013. Epistemic dependence in interdisciplinary groups. Synthese 190 (11), 1881–1898. 10.1007/s11229-012-0172-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  16. Anderson DJ, Adolphs R, 2014. A framework for studying emotions across Species. Cell 157 (1), 187–200. 10.1016/j.cell.2014.03.003. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Archer J, 1999. The nature of grief: The evolution and psychology of reactions to loss, 317. Taylor & Frances/Routledge, p. xiii. 10.4324/9780203360651. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  18. Arias JA, Williams C, Raghvani R, Aghajani M, Baez S, Belzung C, Booij L, Busatto G, Chiarella J, Fu CH, Ibanez A, Liddell BJ, Lowe L, Penninx BWJH, Rosa P, Kemp AH, 2020. The neuroscience of sadness: a multidisciplinary synthesis and collaborative review (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 111, 199–228. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.01.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Aristotle, 1999. Physics. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Armony J, Vuilleumier P, 2013. The Cambridge Handbook of Human Affective Neuroscience. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  21. Arregui JV, 1996. On the intentionality of moods: phenomenology and linguistic analysis. Am. Cathol. Philos. Q 70 (3), 397–411. 10.5840/acpq199670337. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  22. Attias H, 2003. Planning by probabilistic inference. Int. Workshop Artif. Intell. Stat 9–16. [Google Scholar]
  23. Atzil S, Gendron M, 2017. Bio-behavioral synchrony promotes the development of conceptualized emotions. Curr. Opin. Psychol 17, 162–169. 10.1016/j.copsyc.2017.07.009. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Atzil S, Gao W, Fradkin I, Barrett LF, 2018. Growing a social brain. Article 9 Nat. Hum. Behav 2 (9). 10.1038/s41562-018-0384-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Averill JR, 1968. Grief: Its nature and significance. Psychol. Bull 70 (6, Pt.1), 721–748. 10.1037/h0026824. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Averill JR, 1973. Personal control over aversive stimuli and its relationship to stress. Psychol. Bull 80 (4), 286–303. 10.1037/h0034845. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  27. Averill JR, Clore GL, Frijda NH, Levenson RW, Scherer KR, Clark LA, Watson D, Ekman P, Davidson RJ, 1994. What is the function of emotions? In The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions. Oxford University Press, pp. 97–177. [Google Scholar]
  28. Azzouni J, 2004. Theory, observation and scientific realism. Br. J. Philos. Sci 55 (3), 371–392. 10.1093/bjps/55.3.371. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  29. Bach DR, Dayan P, 2017. Algorithms for survival: a comparative perspective on emotions. Article 5 Nat. Rev. Neurosci 18 (5). 10.1038/nrn.2017.35. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Bakker I, van der Voordt T, Vink P, de Boon J, 2014. Pleasure, arousal, dominance: mehrabian and russell revisited. Curr. Psychol 33 (3), 405–421. 10.1007/s12144-014-9219-4. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  31. Bandura A, 1977. Self-efficacy: toward a unifying theory of behavioral change. Psychol. Rev 84 (2), 191–215. 10.1037/0033-295X.84.2.191. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Bandura A, 2006. Toward a psychology of human agency. Perspect. Psychol. Sci 1 (2), 164–180. 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00011.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  33. Barrett LF, 2004. Feelings or words? Understanding the content in self-report ratings of experienced emotion. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 87 (2), 266–281. 10.1037/0022-3514.87.2.266. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Barrett LF, 2005. Feeling is perceiving: core affect and conceptualization in the experience of emotion. In Emotion and consciousness. The Guilford Press, pp. 255–284. [Google Scholar]
  35. Barrett LF, 2012. Emotions are real. Emotion 12 (3), 413–429. 10.1037/a0027555. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Barrett LF, 2017. The theory of constructed emotion: an active inference account of interoception and categorization. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci 12 (1), 1–23. 10.1093/scan/nsw154. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Barrett LF, Satpute AB, 2019. Historical pitfalls and new directions in the neuroscience of emotion. Neurosci. Lett 693, 9–18. 10.1016/j.neulet.2017.07.045. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Barrett LF, Lindquist KA, Gendron M, 2007. Language as context for the perception of emotion. Trends Cogn. Sci 11 (8), 327–332. 10.1016/j.tics.2007.06.003. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  39. Barrett LF, Mesquita B, Gendron M, 2011. Context in emotion perception. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci 20 (5), 286–290. 10.1177/0963721411422522. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  40. Barrett LF, Mesquita B, Ochsner KN, Gross JJ, 2007. The experience of emotion. Annu. Rev. Psychol 58 (1), 373–403. 10.1146/annurev.psych.58.110405.085709. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Barsalou LW, 1999. Perceptual symbol systems. Behav. Brain Sci 22 (4), 577–660. 10.1017/S0140525X99002149. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  42. Barsalou LW, 2003. Situated simulation in the human conceptual system. Lang. Cogn. Process 18 (5–6), 513–562. 10.1080/01690960344000026. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  43. Batcho KI, 2013. Nostalgia: the bittersweet history of a psychological concept. Hist. Psychol 16 (3), 165–176. 10.1037/a0032427. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Bayne T, Montague M, Bayne T, Montague M (Eds.), 2014. Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  45. Beatty A, 2014. Anthropology and emotion. J. R. Anthropol. Inst 20 (3), 545–563. [Google Scholar]
  46. Beatty A, 2019. Emotional Worlds: Beyond an Anthropology of Emotion. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/9781139108096. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  47. Bechtel W, 2007. Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Psychology Press. [Google Scholar]
  48. Bechtel W, 2008. Mechanisms in cognitive psychology: What are the operations? Philosophy of Science 75 (5), 983–994. [Google Scholar]
  49. Bechtel W, 2009. Looking down, around, and up: mechanistic explanation in psychology. Philos. Psychol 22 (5), 543–564. [Google Scholar]
  50. Bechtel W, 2013. Philosophy of Science: An Overview for Cognitive Science. Psychology Press. 10.4324/9781315802084. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  51. Bechtel W, & Abrahamsen A (1991). Connectionism and the mind: An introduction to parallel processing in networks (pp. xiv, 349). Basil Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  52. Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A, 2005. Explanation: a mechanist alternative. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part C: Stud. Hist. Philos. Biol. Biomed. Sci 36 (2), 421–441. 10.1016/j.shpsc.2005.03.010. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  53. Bechtel W, Richardson RC, 2010. Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. MIT press. [Google Scholar]
  54. Beck AT, 1971. Cognition, affect, and psychopathology. Arch. Gen. Psychiatry 24 (6), 495–500. 10.1001/archpsyc.1971.01750120011002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Becker S, Bräscher A-K, Bannister S, Bensafi M, Calma-Birling D, Chan RCK, Eerola T, Ellingsen D-M, Ferdenzi C, Hanson JL, Joffily M, Lidhar NK, Lowe LJ, Martin LJ, Musser ED, Noll-Hussong M, Olino TM, Pintos Lobo R, Wang Y, 2019. The role of hedonics in the Human Affectome (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 102, 221–241. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.05.003. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Bedford E, 1956. Emotions. Proc. Aristot. Soc 57, 281–304. [Google Scholar]
  57. Beer RD, 2014. Dynamical systems and embedded cognition. In: Frankish K, Ramsey WM (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Artificial Intelligence. Cambridge University Press, pp. 128–148. 10.1017/CBO9781139046855.009. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  58. Beer RD, Di Paolo EA, 2023. The theoretical foundations of enaction: Precariousness. Biosystems 223, 104823. 10.1016/j.biosystems.2022.104823. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  59. Berridge K, Winkielman P, 2003. What is an unconscious emotion? (The case for unconscious “liking”. Cogn. Emot 17 (2), 181–211. 10.1080/02699930302289. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Berridge KC, Kringelbach ML, 2008. Affective neuroscience of pleasure: reward in humans and animals. Psychopharmacology 199, 457–480. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  61. Besnier N, 1990. Language and affect. Annu. Rev. Anthropol 19 (1), 419–451. 10.1146/annurev.an.19.100190.002223. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  62. Betella A, Verschure PFMJ, 2016. The affective slider: a digital self-assessment scale for the measurement of human emotions. PLoS One 11 (2), e0148037. 10.1371/journal.pone.0148037. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  63. Betz N, Hoemann K, Barrett LF, 2019. Words are a context for mental inference. Emot. (Wash., D. C.) 19 (8), 1463–1477. 10.1037/emo0000510. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  64. Blanke O, Metzinger T, 2009. Full-body illusions and minimal phenomenal selfhood. Trends Cogn. Sci 13 (1), 7–13. 10.1016/j.tics.2008.10.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  65. Boehner K, DePaula R, Dourish P, Sengers P, 2007. How emotion is made and measured. Int. J. Hum. Comput. Stud 65 (4), 275–291. 10.1016/j.ijhcs.2006.11.016. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  66. Bollnow OF, Boelhauve U, 2009. Das Wesen der Stimmungen. Königshausen & Neumann. [Google Scholar]
  67. Bonanno GA, 2019. The Other Side of Sadness: What the New Science of Bereavement Tells Us About Life After Loss. Hachette; UK. [Google Scholar]
  68. Bonanno GA, Kaltman S, 2001. The varieties of grief experience. Clin. Psychol. Rev 21 (5), 705–734. 10.1016/s0272-7358(00)00062-3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  69. Boone W, Piccinini G, 2016. The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese 193 (5), 1509–1534. 10.1007/s11229-015-0783-4. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  70. Botvinick M, Toussaint M, 2012. Planning as inference. Trends Cogn. Sci 16 (10), 485–488. 10.1016/j.tics.2012.08.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Bourgine P, Stewart J, 2004. Autopoiesis and cognition. Artif. Life 10 (3), 327–345. 10.1162/1064546041255557. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Bower GH, Sahgal A, Routh DA, Broadbent DE, 1997. Affect and cognition. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B, Biol. Sci 302 (1110), 387–402. 10.1098/rstb.1983.0062. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  73. Box GE, 1976. Science and statistics. J. Am. Stat. Assoc 71 (356), 791–799. [Google Scholar]
  74. Bradley MM, Lang PJ, 1994. Measuring emotion: the self-assessment manikin and the semantic differential. J. Behav. Ther. Exp. Psychiatry 25 (1), 49–59. 10.1016/0005-7916(94)90063-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Braun N, Debener S, Spychala N, Bongartz E, Sörös P, Müller HHO, Philipsen A, 2018. The Senses of Agency and Ownership: A Review. Front. Psychol, 9. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00535. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  76. Brentano F, 2012. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  77. Bridgman PW, 1927. The logic of modern physics, Vol. 3. Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
  78. Briggs J, 2010. Emotions have many faces: Inuit lessons. Wiley Blackwell, p. 67. [Google Scholar]
  79. Britt SH, Janus SQ, 1940. Criteria of frustration. Psychol. Rev 47 (5), 451–470. 10.1037/h0061381. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  80. Broekens J, Bosse T, Marsella SC, 2013. Challenges in computational modeling of affective processes. IEEE Trans. Affect. Comput 4 (3), 242–245. 10.1109/T-AFFC.2013.23. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  81. Bromberger S, 1966. Why-Questions. In: Robert GC (Ed.), Mind and Cosmos – Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy. University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 86–111. [Google Scholar]
  82. Brooks RA, 1991. New Approaches to Robotics. Science 253 (5025), 1227–1232. 10.1126/science.253.5025.1227. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  83. Brouwer A-M, Hogervorst MA, Grootjen M, van Erp JBF, Zandstra EH, 2017. Neurophysiological responses during cooking food associated with different emotions. Food Qual. Prefer 62, 307–316. 10.1016/j.foodqual.2017.03.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  84. Brown CL, Van Doren N, Ford BQ, Mauss IB, Sze JW, Levenson RW, 2020. Coherence between subjective experience and physiology in emotion: Individual differences and implications for well-being. Emotion 20 (5), 818–829. 10.1037/emo0000579. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  85. Brown MJ, 2010. Genuine problems and the significance of science. Contemp. Pragmatism 7 (2), 131. [Google Scholar]
  86. Brüne M, Brüne-Cohrs U, 2006. Theory of mind—evolution, ontogeny, brain mechanisms and psychopathology. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 30 (4), 437–455. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2005.08.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. Burge T, 2010. Origins of Objectivity. OUP, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  88. Cacioppo JT, Gardner WL, Berntson GG, 1999. The affect system has parallel and integrative processing components: Form follows function. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 76 (5), 839–855. 10.1037/0022-3514.76.5.839. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  89. Cahill L, McGaugh JL, 1998. Mechanisms of emotional arousal and lasting declarative memory. Trends Neurosci. 21 (7), 294–299. 10.1016/S0166-2236(97)01214-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  90. Caldwell LL, 2005. Leisure and health: why is leisure therapeutic. Br. J. Guid. Couns 33 (1), 7–26. 10.1080/03069880412331335939. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  91. Callard F, Fitzgerald D, 2015. Rethinking interdisciplinarity across the social sciences and neurosciences. Springer Nature. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  92. Calvo RA, D’Mello S, Gratch JM, Kappas A, 2015. The Oxford Handbook of Affective Computing. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  93. Cannon WB, 1929. Organization for physiological homeostasis. Physiol. Rev 9 (3), 399–431. 10.1152/physrev.1929.9.3.399. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  94. Carmel D, Sprevak M, 2014. What is consciousness? In Philosophy and the Sciences For Everyone. Routledge. https://www.research.ed.ac.uk/en/publications/what-is-consciousness. [Google Scholar]
  95. Carnap R, Gardner M, 1966. Philos. Found. Phys.: Introd. Philos. Sci
  96. Carpenter RHS, 2004. Homeostasis: a plea for a unified approach. Adv. Physiol. Educ 28 (4), 180–187. 10.1152/advan.00012.2004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  97. Cartwright N, 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. OUP, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  98. Cartwright N, 1986. Two Kinds of Teleological Explanation. In: Donagan A, Perovich AN, Wedin MV (Eds.), Human Nature and Natural Knowledge: Essays Presented to Marjorie Grene on the Occasion of Her Seventy-Fifth Birthday. Springer, Netherlands, pp. 201–210. 10.1007/978-94-009-5349-9_10. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  99. Chalmers DJ, 1997. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. OUP; USA. [Google Scholar]
  100. Chalmers DJ, 2012. The Varieties of Computation: A Reply. J. Cogn. Sci 13 (3), 211–248. 10.17791/JCS.2012.13.3.211. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  101. Chang H, 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  102. Chang H, 2005. A case for old-fashioned observability, and a reconstructed constructive empiricism. Philos. Sci 72 (5), 876–887. 10.1086/508116. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  103. Chang RS, 2009. Relating to Environments: A New Look at Umwelt. IAP. [Google Scholar]
  104. Charland LC, 2005. The heat of emotion: valence and the demarcation problem. J. Conscious. Stud 12 (8–9), 82–102. [Google Scholar]
  105. Chemero A, 2011. Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  106. Chemero A, 2016. Sensorimotor empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 (5–6), 138–152. [Google Scholar]
  107. Choi S-C, Han G, Kim C-W, 2007. Analysis of cultural emotion: Understanding of indigenous psychology for universal implications. In The Cambridge handbook of sociocultural psychology. Cambridge University Press, pp. 318–342. 10.1017/CBO9780511611162.018. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  108. Christoff K, Cosmelli D, Legrand D, Thompson E, 2011. Specifying the self for cognitive neuroscience. Trends Cogn. Sci 15 (3), 104–112. 10.1016/j.tics.2011.01.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  109. Chua HF, Gonzalez R, Taylor SF, Welsh RC, Liberzon I, 2009. Decision-related loss: regret and disappointment. NeuroImage 47 (4), 2031–2040. 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2009.06.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  110. Clark A, 1989. Microcognition: Philosophy. Cognitive Science, and Parallel Distributed Processing. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  111. Clark A, 1997. The dynamical challenge. Cogn. Sci 21 (4), 461–481. 10.1016/S0364-0213(99)80030-5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  112. Clark A, 1998. Being There: Putting Brain, Body, and World Together Again. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  113. Clark A, 2000. Mindware: An introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science (pp. xiii, 210). Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  114. Clark A, 2013. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci 36 (3), 181–204. 10.1017/S0140525X12000477. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  115. Clark A, 2015. Surfing Uncertainty: Prediction, Action, and the Embodied Mind. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  116. Clark A, Chalmers D, 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58 (1), 7–19. [Google Scholar]
  117. Clark JE, Watson S, Friston KJ, 2018. What is mood? A computational perspective. Psychol. Med 48 (14), 2277–2284. 10.1017/S0033291718000430. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  118. Clore GL, Ortony A, 1988. The semantics of the affective lexicon. In: Hamilton V, Bower GH, Frijda NH (Eds.), Cognitive Perspectives on Emotion and Motivation. Springer, Netherlands, pp. 367–397. 10.1007/978-94-009-2792-6_15. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  119. Clore GL, Ortony A, 2000. Cognition in Emotion: Always, Sometimes, or Never. In: Lane RDR, Nadel L, Ahern GL, Allen J, Kaszniak AW (Eds.), Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotion. Oxford University Press, pp. 24–61. [Google Scholar]
  120. Clore GL, Huntsinger JR, 2009. How the object of affect guides its impact. Emot. Rev 1 (1), 39–54. 10.1177/1754073908097185. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  121. Clore GL, Palmer J, 2009. Affective guidance of intelligent agents: How emotion controls cognition. Cogn. Syst. Res 10 (1), 21–30. 10.1016/j.cogsys.2008.03.002. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  122. Clore GL, Ortony A, 2013. Psychological construction in the OCC model of emotion. Emot. Rev 5 (4), 335–343. 10.1177/1754073913489751. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  123. Clore GL, Gasper K, Garvin E, 2001. Affect as information. In: Handbook of affect and social cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, pp. 121–144. [Google Scholar]
  124. Clore GL, Proffitt DR, Zadra JR, 2021. Feeling, seeing, and liking: how bodily resources inform perception and emotion. In: Robinson MD, Thomas LE (Eds.), Handbook of Embodied Psychology: Thinking, Feeling, and Acting. Springer International Publishing, pp. 43–64. 10.1007/978-3-030-78471-3_3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  125. Colombetti G, 2005. Appraising valence. J. Conscious. Stud 12 (8–9), 103–126. [Google Scholar]
  126. Colombetti G, 2009. What language does to feelings. J. Conscious. Stud 16 (9), 4–26. [Google Scholar]
  127. Colombetti G, 2010. Enaction, sense-making, and emotion. In: Stewart J, Gapenne O, Di Paolo EA (Eds.), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. The MIT Press, pp. 145–164. 10.7551/mitpress/9780262014601.003.0006. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  128. Colombetti G, 2011. Varieties of pre-reflective self-awareness: foreground and background bodily feelings in emotion experience. Inquiry 54, 293–313. 10.1080/0020174X.2011.575003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  129. Colombetti G, 2014. The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  130. Colombetti G, Thompson E, 2008. The Feeling Body: Towards an Enactive Approach to Emotion. In: Overton WF, Müller U, Newman JL (Eds.), Developmental Perspectives on Embodiment and Consciousness. Erlbaum. [Google Scholar]
  131. Coninx S, Stilwell P, 2021. Pain and the field of affordances: an enactive approach to acute and chronic pain. Synthese 199 (3), 7835–7863. 10.1007/s11229-021-03142-3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  132. Cooper SJ, 2008. From claude bernard to walter cannon. emergence of the concept of homeostasis. Appetite 51 (3), 419–427. 10.1016/j.appet.2008.06.005. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  133. Tooby J, Cosmides L, 2008. The evolutionary psychology of the emotions and their relationship to internal regulatory variables. In: Handbook of Emotions, 3rd Ed. The Guilford Press, New York, NY, US, pp. 114–137. [Google Scholar]
  134. Cosmides L, Tooby J, 2013. Evolutionary Psychology: New Perspectives on Cognition and Motivation. Annual Review of Psychology 64 (1), 201–229. 10.1146/annurev.psych.121208.131628. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  135. Cowen AS, & Keltner D (2017). Self-report captures 27 distinct categories of emotion bridged by continuous gradients. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 114(38), E7900–E7909. 10.1073/pnas.1702247114. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  136. Craig AD, 2002. How do you feel? Interoception: the sense of the physiological condition of the body. Article 8 Nat. Rev. Neurosci 3 (8). 10.1038/nrn894. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  137. Craig AD(B), 2008. Interoception and emotion: A neuroanatomical perspective. In Handbook of emotions, 3rd ed. The Guilford Press, New York, NY, USA, pp. 272–292. [Google Scholar]
  138. Craig AD, 2013. Chapter 9—Cooling, pain, and other feelings from the body in relation to the autonomic nervous system. In: Buijs RM, Swaab DF (Eds.), Handbook of Clinical Neurology, Vol. 117. Elsevier, pp. 103–109. 10.1016/B978-0-444-53491-0.00009-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  139. Crane T, 1998. Intentionality as the mark of the mental. R. Inst. Philos. Suppl 43, 229–251. 10.1017/S1358246100004380. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  140. Craver CF, 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
  141. Craver CF, Darden L, 2013. In search of mechanisms: discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
  142. Critchley HD, Garfinkel SN, 2017. Interoception and emotion. Curr. Opin. Psychol 17, 7–14. 10.1016/j.copsyc.2017.04.020. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  143. Crivelli C, Jarillo S, Russell JA, Fernández-Dols J-M, 2016. Reading emotions from faces in two indigenous societies. J. Exp. Psychol.: Gen 145 (7), 830–843. 10.1037/xge0000172. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  144. Cromwell HC, Lowe LJ, 2022. The human affectome project: a dedication to Jaak Panksepp (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 138, 104693. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104693. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  145. Cromwell HC, Papadelis C, 2022. Mapping the brain basis of feelings, emotions and much more: a special issue focused on ‘The Human Affectome (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 137, 104672. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104672. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  146. Cromwell HC, Abe N, Barrett KC, Caldwell-Harris C, Gendolla GHE, Koncz R, Sachdev PS, 2020. Mapping the interconnected neural systems underlying motivation and emotion: a key step toward understanding the human affectome (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 113, 204–226. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.02.032. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  147. Csibra G, Gergely G, 2007. “Obsessed with goals”: Functions and mechanisms of teleological interpretation of actions in humans. Acta Psychol. 124 (1), 60–78. 10.1016/j.actpsy.2006.09.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  148. Csikszentmihalyi M, 2014. Flow and the Foundations of Positive Psychology: The Collected Works of Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi. Springr,, Netherlands. 10.1007/978-94-017-9088-8. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  149. Csikszentmihalyi M, Larson R, 2014. Validity and Reliability of the Experience-Sampling Method. In: Csikszentmihalyi M (Ed.), Flow and the Foundations of Positive Psychology: The Collected Works of Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi. Springer, Netherlands, pp. 35–54. 10.1007/978-94-017-9088-8_3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  150. Cuff BMP, Brown SJ, Taylor L, Howat DJ, 2016. Empathy: a review of the concept. Emot. Rev 8 (2), 144–153. 10.1177/1754073914558466. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  151. Cummins RA, 2010. Subjective wellbeing, homeostatically protected mood and depression: a synthesis. J. Happiness Stud 11 (1), 1–17. 10.1007/s10902-009-9167-0. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  152. Cunningham MR, 1977. Personality and the structure of the nonverbal communication of emotion. J. Personal 45 (4), 564–584. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.1977.tb00172.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  153. Cunningham WA, Dunfield KA, Stillman PE, 2013. Emotional states from affective dynamics. Emot. Rev 5 (4), 344–355. 10.1177/1754073913489749. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  154. D’Mello S, Graesser A, 2012. Dynamics of affective states during complex learning. Learn. Instr 22 (2), 145–157. 10.1016/j.learninstruc.2011.10.001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  155. Dalgleish T, Dunn BD, & Mobbs D (2009). Affective Neuroscience: Past, Present, and Future. Emotion Review, 1(4), 355–368. 10.1177/1754073909338307e. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  156. Damasio A, 2003. Feelings of emotion and the self. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1001 (1), 253–261. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  157. Damasio A, 2005. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (Reprint edition). Penguin Books. [Google Scholar]
  158. Damasio A, Carvalho GB, 2013. The nature of feelings: evolutionary and neurobiological origins. Article 2 Nat. Rev. Neurosci 14 (2). 10.1038/nrn3403. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  159. Damasio AR, 1996. The somatic marker hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B: Biological Sciences 351 (1346), 1413–1420. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  160. Danziger K, 1997. Naming the mind: how psychology found its language. Namin. Mind 1–224. [Google Scholar]
  161. Darwin C, 1965. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. University of Chicago Press. https://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/E/bo24666926.html. [Google Scholar]
  162. David N, 2012. New frontiers in the neuroscience of the sense of agency. Front. Hum. Neurosci 6. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00161. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  163. Davidson RJ, Sutton SK, 1995. Affective neuroscience: the emergence of a discipline. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol 5 (2), 217–224. 10.1016/0959-4388(95)80029-8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  164. Davidson RJ, Sherer KR, Goldsmith HH, 2009. Handbook of Affective Sciences. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  165. Dawson M, 2014. Embedded and situated cognition. In The Routledge Handbook of Embodied Cognition. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  166. Dayan P, Abbott LF, 2005. Theoretical neuroscience: computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. MIT press. [Google Scholar]
  167. Dayan P, Hinton GE, Neal RM, Zemel RS, 1995. The helmholtz machine. Neural Comput. 7 (5), 889–904. 10.1162/neco.1995.7.5.889. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  168. de Haan S, de Bruin L, 2010. Reconstructing the minimal self, or how to make sense of agency and ownership. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 9 (3), 373–396. 10.1007/s11097-009-9148-0. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  169. De Jaegher H, Di Paolo E, 2007. Participatory sense-making: an enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 6 (4), 485–507. 10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  170. De Neve J-E, Diener E, Tay L, & Xuereb C (2013). The Objective Benefits of Subjective Well-Being (SSRN Scholarly Paper 2306651). https://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2306651.
  171. De Regt HW, Dieks D, 2005. A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese 144, 137–170. [Google Scholar]
  172. de Sousa R, 1990. The Rationality of Emotion. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  173. de Waal FBM, 2011. What is an animal emotion. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci 1224 (1), 191–206. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2010.05912.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  174. De Wolf T, Holvoet T, 2005. Emergence versus self-organisation: different concepts but promising when combined. In: Brueckner SA, Di Marzo Serugendo G, Karageorgos A, Nagpal R (Eds.), Engineering Self-Organising Systems. Springer, pp. 1–15. 10.1007/11494676_1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  175. Deacon TW, 2011. Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. WW Norton & Company. [Google Scholar]
  176. Dehaene S, Sergent C, Changeux J-P, 2003. A neuronal network model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data during conscious perception. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 100 (14), 8520–8525. 10.1073/pnas.1332574100. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  177. Dennett DC, 1989. The Intentional Stance. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  178. Dennett DC, 2002. Content and Consciousness. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  179. Deonna J, Teroni F, 2012. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  180. Deonna J, Tappolet C, Teroni F, 2015. Emotion, philosophical issues about. WIREs Cogn. Sci 6 (3), 193–207. 10.1002/wcs.1342. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  181. Deonna JA, Scherer KR, 2010. The case of the disappearing intentional object: constraints on a definition of emotion. Emot. Rev 2 (1), 44–52. [Google Scholar]
  182. Deonna JA, Teroni F, 2015. Emotions as Attitudes. Dialectica 69 (3), 293–311. 10.1111/1746-8361.12116. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  183. Deonna JA, Teroni F, 2017. Getting bodily feelings into emotional experience in the right way. Emot. Rev 9 (1), 55–63. 10.1177/1754073916639666. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  184. Deonna JA, Rodogno R, Teroni F, 2012. In Defense of Shame: The Faces of an Emotion. Oxford University Press, USA. [Google Scholar]
  185. Descartes R, 1644. Principia philosophiae. Ludovicum Elzevirium. [Google Scholar]
  186. Desmet P, 2003. Measuring Emotion: Development and Application of an Instrument to Measure Emotional Responses to Products. In: Blythe MA, Overbeeke K, Monk AF, Wright PC (Eds.), Funology, Vol. 3. Springer; Netherlands, pp. 111–123. 10.1007/1-4020-2967-5_12. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  187. Desmet PMA, Schifferstein HNJ, 2008. Sources of positive and negative emotions in food experience. Appetite 50 (2), 290–301. 10.1016/j.appet.2007.08.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  188. Desmet PMA, Fokkinga SF, Ozkaramanli D, Yoon J, 2021. Chapter 20—Emotion-driven product design. In: Meiselman HL (Ed.), Emotion Measurement, Second edition.,. Woodhead Publishing, pp. 645–670. 10.1016/B978-0-12-821124-3.00020-X. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  189. Dewey J, 1895. The theory of emotion. Psychol. Rev 2 (1), 13–32. 10.1037/h0070927. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  190. Di Paolo E, Thompson E, 2014. The enactive approach. In The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition. Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group,, pp. 68–78. [Google Scholar]
  191. Di Paolo E, Thompson E, Beer R, 2022. Laying down a forking path: Tensions between enaction and the free energy principle. Philos. Mind Sci 3. 10.33735/phimisci.2022.9187. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  192. Di Paolo EA, 2005. Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 4 (4), 429–452. 10.1007/s11097-005-9002-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  193. Díaz R, 2023. Experimental Philosophy of Emotion. In: Bauer AM, Kornmesser S (Eds.), Compact Compendium of Experimental Philosophy. De Gruyter. https://philarchive.org/rec/DAZEPO. [Google Scholar]
  194. Diener E (Ed.), 2009. The Science of Well-Being, Vol. 37. Springer; Netherlands. 10.1007/978-90-481-2350-6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  195. Diener E, Ryan K, 2009. Subjective well-being: a general overview. South Afr. J. Psychol 39 (4), 391–406. 10.1177/008124630903900402. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  196. Diener E, Oishi S, Lucas RE, 2009. Subjective well-being: The science of happiness and life satisfaction. In Oxford handbook of positive psychology, 2nd ed.,. Oxford University Press, pp. 187–194. [Google Scholar]
  197. Diener E, Inglehart R, Tay L, 2013. Theory and validity of life satisfaction scales. Soc. Indic. Res 112 (3), 497–527. 10.1007/s11205-012-0076-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  198. Dijkstra EW, 2002. Cooperating sequential processes, in: The Origin of Concurrent Programming: From Semaphores to Remote Procedure Calls. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp. 65–138. [Google Scholar]
  199. Dixon T, 2003. From passions to emotions: the creation of a secular psychological category. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  200. Dixon T, 2012. “Emotion”: The history of a keyword in crisis. Emot. Rev 4 (4), 338–344. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  201. Djerassi M, Ophir S, Atzil S, 2021. What is social about autism? The role of allostasis-driven learning. Article 10 Brain Sci. 11 (10). 10.3390/brainsci11101269. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  202. Dolcos F, Katsumi Y, Moore M, Berggren N, De Gelder B, Derakshan N, Hamm AO, Koster EHW, Ladouceur CD, Okon-Singer H, Pegna AJ, Richter T, Schweizer S, Van Den Stock J, Ventura-Bort C, Weymar M, Dolcos S, 2020. Neural correlates of emotion-attention interactions: From perception, learning, and memory to social cognition, individual differences, and training interventions (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 108, 559–601. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.08.017. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  203. Doya K, 2007. Bayesian Brain: Probabilistic Approaches to Neural Coding. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  204. Draper K, 1999. Disappointment, sadness, and death. Philos. Rev 108 (3), 387–414. 10.2307/2998466. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  205. Dreyfus HL, 1972. What Computers Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
  206. Duffy E, 1957. The psychological significance of the concept of “arousal” or “activation. Psychol. Rev 64 (5), 265–275. 10.1037/h0048837. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  207. Duhem P, Wiener PP, Vuillemin J, 1982. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Princeton University Press. 10.2307/j.ctv1nj34vm. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  208. Dukes D, Abrams K, Adolphs R, Ahmed ME, Beatty A, Berridge KC, Broomhall S, Brosch T, Campos JJ, Clay Z, Clément F, Cunningham WA, Damasio A, Damasio H, D’Arms J, Davidson JW, de Gelder B, Deonna J, de Sousa R, Sander D, 2021. The rise of affectivism. Article 7 Nat. Hum. Behav 5 (7). 10.1038/s41562-021-01130-8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  209. Dunbar R, 1998. Grooming, Gossip, and the Evolution of Language. Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
  210. Duncan S, Barrett LF, 2007. Affect is a form of cognition: a neurobiological analysis. Cogn. Emot 21 (6), 1184–1211. 10.1080/02699930701437931. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  211. Eckardt BV, 1995. What is Cognitive Science? MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  212. Egan F, 2017. Function-theoretic explanation and the search for neural mechanisms, in: Explanation and Integration in Mind and Brain Science. Oxford University Press, New York, NY, US, pp. 145–163. [Google Scholar]
  213. Egan F, 2020. A Deflationary Account of Mental Representation. In: Smortchkova J, Dolega K, Schlicht T (Eds.), What Are Mental Representations? Oxford University Press, pp. 26–53. 10.1093/oso/9780190686673.003.0002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  214. Eid M (Ed.), 2008. The science of subjective well-being. Guilford Press. [Google Scholar]
  215. Einstein A, 1934. On the method of theoretical physics. Philos. Sci 1 (2), 163–169. [Google Scholar]
  216. Ekman P, 2016. What scientists who study emotion agree about. Perspect. Psychol. Sci 11 (1), 31–34. 10.1177/1745691615596992. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  217. Ekman P, Davidson RJ (Eds.), 1994. The nature of emotion: Fundamental questions, 496. Oxford University Press, p. xiv. [Google Scholar]
  218. Ekman P, Cordaro D, 2011. What is meant by calling emotions basic. Emot. Rev 3 (4), 364–370. 10.1177/1754073911410740. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  219. Eldar E, Rutledge RB, Dolan RJ, Niv Y, 2016. Mood as representation of momentum. Trends in cognitive sciences 20 (1), 15–24. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  220. Elpidorou A, Freeman L, 2014. The phenomenology and science of emotions: an introduction. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 13 (4), 507–511. 10.1007/s11097-014-9402-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  221. Emanuel A, Eldar E, 2023. Emotions as computations. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 144, 104977 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2022.104977. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  222. Engbert K, Wohlschläger A, Haggard P, 2008. Who is causing what? The sense of agency is relational and efferent-triggered. Cognition 107 (2), 693–704. 10.1016/j.cognition.2007.07.021. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  223. Ericsson KA, Simon HA, 1993. Protocol Analysis: Verbal Reports as Data. The MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/5657.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  224. Eslinger PJ, Anders S, Ballarini T, Boutros S, Krach S, Mayer AV, Moll J, Newton TL, Schroeter ML, De Oliveira-Souza R, Raber J, Sullivan GB, Swain JE, Lowe L, Zahn R, 2021. The neuroscience of social feelings: mechanisms of adaptive social functioning (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 128, 592–620. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2021.05.028. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  225. Eysenck M, 2012. Attention and Arousal: Cognition and Performance. Springer Science & Business Media. [Google Scholar]
  226. Feiten TE, 2020. Mind after uexküll: a foray into the worlds of ecological psychologists and enactivists. Front. Psychol 11. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2020.00480. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  227. Fernández N, Maldonado C, Gershenson C, 2014. Information measures of complexity, emergence, self-organization, homeostasis, and autopoiesis. In: Prokopenko M (Ed.), Guided Self-Organization: Inception. Springer, pp. 19–51. 10.1007/978-3-642-53734-9_2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  228. Fingelkurts AA, Fingelkurts A, 2004. Making complexity simpler: multivariability and metastability in the brain. Int. J. Neurosci 114 (7), 843–862. 10.1080/00207450490450046. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  229. Fischer AH, Manstead ASR, 2008. Social functions of emotion. In Handbook of emotions, 3rd ed.,. The Guilford Press,, pp. 456–468. [Google Scholar]
  230. Fischer AH, Manstead AS, 2016. Social functions of emotion and emotion regulation. Handbook of emotions 4, 424–439. [Google Scholar]
  231. Fodor JA, 1998. Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  232. Fodor JA, Pylyshyn ZW, 1988. Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition 28 (1), 3–71. 10.1016/0010-0277(88)90031-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  233. Fokkinga SF, Desmet PMA, 2022. Emot. Typology Emot. Typology. https://emotiontypology.com.
  234. Forgas JP (Ed.), 2000. Feeling and thinking: The role of affect in social cognition, 421. Cambridge University Press, p. xvi. [Google Scholar]
  235. Forgas JP (Ed.), 2001. Handbook of affect and social cognition, 457. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, p. xviii. [Google Scholar]
  236. Forgas JP, 2012. Handbook of Affect and Social Cognition. Psychology Press. [Google Scholar]
  237. Fotopoulou A, Tsakiris M, 2017. Mentalizing homeostasis: the social origins of interoceptive inference. Neuropsychoanalysis 19 (1), 3–28. 10.1080/15294145.2017.1294031. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  238. Fox E, 2018. Perspectives from affective science on understanding the nature of emotion. Brain Neurosci. Adv 2, 2398212818812628. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  239. Fredrickson BL, 2001. The role of positive emotions in positive psychology. Am. Psychol 56 (3), 218–226. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  240. Fredrickson BL, 2005. The broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions. In The science of well-being. Oxford University Press,, pp. 217–238. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198567523.003.0008. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  241. Fredrickson BL, Joiner T, 2002. Positive emotions trigger upward spirals toward emotional well-being. Psychological science 13 (2), 172–175. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  242. Freed PJ, Mann JJ, 2007. Sadness and loss: toward a neurobiopsychosocial model. Am. J. Psychiatry 164 (1), 28–34. 10.1176/ajp.2007.164.1.28. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  243. Frege G, 1948. Sense and reference. Philos. Rev 57 (3), 209–230. 10.2307/2181485. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  244. Frewen P, Schroeter ML, Riva G, Cipresso P, Fairfield B, Padulo C, Kemp AH, Palaniyappan L, Owolabi M, Kusi-Mensah K, Polyakova M, Fehertoi N, D’Andrea W, Lowe L, Northoff G, 2020. Neuroimaging the consciousness of self: Review, and conceptual-methodological framework (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 112, 164–212. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.01.023. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  245. Frijda NH, 1986. The Emotions. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  246. Frijda NH, 1993. Moods, emotion episodes, and emotions. In Handbook of emotions. The Guilford Press, pp. 381–403. [Google Scholar]
  247. Frijda NH, 2017. The Laws of Emotion. Psychology Press. 10.4324/9781315086071. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  248. Frijda Nico H. 1994. “Emotions are Functional, Most of the Time.” In The Nature of Emotion: Fundamental Questions, edited by Ekman Paul and Davidson Richard J., 112–122. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  249. Friston K, 2020. Representation and agency. Behav. Brain Sci 43, e134 10.1017/S0140525X19002929. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  250. Friston K, 2023. Computational psychiatry: from synapses to sentience. Article 1 Mol. Psychiatry 28 (1). 10.1038/s41380-022-01743-z. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  251. Friston K, Kiebel S, 2009. Predictive coding under the free-energy principle. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci 364 (1521), 1211–1221. 10.1098/rstb.2008.0300. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  252. Friston K, FitzGerald T, Rigoli F, Schwartenbeck P, Pezzulo G, 2017. Active Inference: A Process Theory. Neural Computation 29 (1), 1–49. 10.1162/NECO_a_00912. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  253. Friston K, Schwartenbeck P, Fitzgerald T, Moutoussis M, Behrens T, Dolan R, 2013. The anatomy of choice: active inference and agency. Front. Hum. Neurosci, 7. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00598. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  254. Friston K, FitzGerald T, Rigoli F, Schwartenbeck P, O?Doherty J, Pezzulo G, 2016. Active inference and learning. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 68, 862–879. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2016.06.022. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  255. Friston KJ, Price CJ, 2001a. Dynamic representations and generative models of brain function. Brain Res. Bull 54 (3), 275–285. 10.1016/S0361-9230(00)00436-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  256. Friston KJ, Price CJ, 2001b. Generative models, brain function and neuroimaging. Scand. J. Psychol 42 (3), 167–177. 10.1111/1467-9450.00228. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  257. Fuchs T, 2017. Ecology of the Brain: The phenomenology and biology of the embodied mind. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  258. Fuchs T, 2018. Presence in absence. The ambiguous phenomenology of grief. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (1), 43–63. 10.1007/s11097-017-9506-2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  259. Galilei G, 1953. Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems, Ptolemaic and Copernican, Second Revised edition. University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
  260. Gallagher S, 1997. Mutual enlightenment: Recent phenomenology in cognitive science. J. Conscious. Stud 4, 195–214. [Google Scholar]
  261. Gallagher S, 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends Cogn. Sci 4 (1), 14–21. 10.1016/S1364-6613(99)01417-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  262. Gallagher S, 2012. Multiple aspects in the sense of agency. N. Ideas Psychol 30 (1), 15–31. 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2010.03.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  263. Gallagher S, Zahavi D, 2020. The Phenomenological Mind, 3rd ed. Routledge, London. 10.4324/9780429319792. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  264. Gardiner JM, Java RI, 2019. Recognising and remembering. In Theories of memory. Psychology Press, pp. 163–188. [Google Scholar]
  265. Gendolla GHE, 2000. On the impact of mood on behavior: an integrative theory and a review. Rev. Gen. Psychol 4 (4), 378–408. 10.1037/1089-2680.4.4.378. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  266. Gendolla GHE, Krüsken J, 2001. Mood state and cardiovascular response in active coping with an affect-regulative challenge. Int. J. Psychophysiol 41 (2), 169–180. 10.1016/S0167-8760(01)00130-1. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  267. Gendolla GHE, Abele AE, Andrei A, Spurk D, Richter M, 2005. Negative mood, self-focused attention, and the experience of physical symptoms: the joint impact hypothesis. Emotion 5 (2), 131–144. 10.1037/1528-3542.5.2.131. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  268. Gendron M, 2010. Defining emotion: a brief history. Emot. Rev 2 (4), 371–372. [Google Scholar]
  269. Gendron M, Barrett LF, 2009. Reconstructing the past: a century of ideas about emotion in psychology. Emot. Rev 1 (4), 316–339. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  270. Georgieff N, Jeannerod M, 1998. Beyond Consciousness of External Reality: A “Who” System for Consciousness of Action and Self-Consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 7 (3), 465–477. 10.1006/ccog.1998.0367. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  271. Gibson JJ, 1977. The Theory of Affordances, in: The People, Place, and Space Reader. Routledge, pp. 56–60. [Google Scholar]
  272. Gilead M, Trope Y, Liberman N, 2020. Above and beyond the concrete: the diverse representational substrates of the predictive brain. Behav. Brain Sci 43, e121 10.1017/S0140525X19002000. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  273. Glennan S, 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philos. Sci 69 (S3), S342–S353. 10.1086/341857. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  274. Glennan S, 2008. Mechanisms. In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  275. Glennan SS, 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44 (1), 49–71. [Google Scholar]
  276. Godfrey-Smith P, 2006. Mental Representation, Naturalism, and Teleosemantics. In Teleosemantics. Clarendon Press,. https://philpapers.org/rec/GODMRN-2. [Google Scholar]
  277. Godfrey-Smith P, 2020. Gradualism and the evolution of experience. Philos. Top 48 (1), 201–220. [Google Scholar]
  278. Godfrey-Smith P, 2021. Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Second Edition. University of Chicago Press. https://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/T/bo37447570.html. [Google Scholar]
  279. Gohm CL, Clore GL, 2000. Individual differences in emotional experience: mapping available scales to processes. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull 26 (6), 679–697. 10.1177/0146167200268004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  280. Goldie P, 2000. The Emotions: A Philosophical Exploration. Clarendon Press. [Google Scholar]
  281. Goldie P, 2009. The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion. OUP; Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  282. Gordon SL, 1990. The Sociology of Sentiments and Emotion. In. Social Psychology. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  283. Grahek I, Musslick S, Shenhav A, 2020. A computational perspective on the roles of affect in cognitive control. Int. J. Psychophysiol 151, 25–34. 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2020.02.001. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  284. Grandjean D, Scherer KR, 2008. Unpacking the cognitive architecture of emotion processes. Emotion 8 (3), 341–351. 10.1037/1528-3542.8.3.341. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  285. Gratch J, Marsella S, 2004. A domain-independent framework for modeling emotion. Cogn. Syst. Res 5 (4), 269–306. 10.1016/j.cogsys.2004.02.002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  286. Gray K, Wegner DM, 2011. Dimensions of moral emotions. Emot. Rev 3 (3), 258–260. 10.1177/1754073911402388. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  287. Gray HM, Gray K, Wegner DM, 2007. Dimensions of Mind Perception. Science 315, 619. 10.1126/science.1134475. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  288. Grice HP, 1957. Meaning. Philos. Rev 66 (3), 377–388. 10.2307/2182440. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  289. Griffiths PE, 2013. Current emotion research in philosophy. Emot. Rev 5 (2), 215–222. 10.1177/1754073912468299. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  290. Griffiths PE, Scarantino A, 2005. Emotions in the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion. In: Robbins P, Aydede M (Eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. Cambridge University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/GRIEIT. [Google Scholar]
  291. Gross JJ, Barrett LF, 2013. The emerging field of affective science. Emotion 13 (6), 997–998. 10.1037/a0034512. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  292. Haggard P, 2017. Sense of agency in the human brain. Nat. Rev. Neurosci, 18(4), Artic. 4. 10.1038/nrn.2017.14. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  293. Haidt J, 2003. The moral emotions. In Handbook of affective sciences. Oxford University Press, pp. 852–870. [Google Scholar]
  294. Hardin CL, 1988. Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Hackett Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  295. Harmon-Jones C, Bastian B, Harmon-Jones E, 2016. The discrete emotions questionnaire: a new tool for measuring state self-reported emotions. PLoS One 11 (8), e0159915. 10.1371/journal.pone.0159915. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  296. Hassenzahl M, Tractinsky N, 2006. User experience—a research agenda. Behav. Inf. Technol 25 (2), 91–97. 10.1080/01449290500330331. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  297. Hatzimoysis A, 2007. The case against unconscious emotions. Analysis 67 (4), 292–299. [Google Scholar]
  298. Haugeland J, 1978. The nature and plausibility of cognitivism. Behav. Brain Sci 1 (2), 215–226. 10.1017/S0140525X00074148. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  299. Haugeland J, 1997. Mind Design II: Philosophy, Psychology, and Artificial Intelligence. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  300. Heidegger M, 1967. Being and Time. Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  301. Heise DR, 1977. Social action as the control of affect. Behav. Sci 22 (3), 163–177. 10.1002/bs.3830220303. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  302. Hempel CG, 1952. Fundamentals of concept formation in empirical science, Vol. II. No. 7. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, USA. [Google Scholar]
  303. Hempel CG, Oppenheim P, 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philos. Sci 15 (2), 135–175. 10.1086/286983. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  304. Hempel CG, 1970. Aspects of Scientific Explanation: And Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. Free Press. [Google Scholar]
  305. Hesp C, Smith R, Parr T, Allen M, Friston KJ, Ramstead MJD, 2021. Deeply felt affect: the emergence of valence in deep active inference. Neural Comput. 33 (2), 398–446. 10.1162/neco_a_01341. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  306. Heylighen F, Busseniers E, 2023. Modeling autopoiesis and cognition with reaction networks. Biosystems 230, 104937. 10.1016/j.biosystems.2023.104937. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  307. Hill RK, 2016. What an algorithm is. Philos. Technol 29 (1), 35–59. 10.1007/s13347-014-0184-5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  308. Hitchcock PF, Fried EI, Frank MJ, 2022. Computational Psychiatry Needs Time and Context. Annual Review of Psychology 73, 243–270. 10.1146/annurev-psych-021621-124910. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  309. Ho MK, Saxe R, Cushman F, 2022. Planning with theory of mind. Trends Cogn. Sci 26 (11), 959–971. 10.1016/j.tics.2022.08.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  310. Hodson R, Bassett B, van Hoof C, Rosman B, Solms M, Shock JP, & Smith R (2023, August 15). Planning to Learn: A Novel Algorithm for Active Learning during Model-Based Planning. ArXiv.Org. https://arxiv.org/abs/2308.08029v1. [Google Scholar]
  311. Hoemann K, Gendron M, Barrett LF, 2017. Mixed emotions in the predictive brain. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 15, 51–57. 10.1016/j.cobeha.2017.05.013. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  312. Hoemann K, Nielson C, Yuen A, Gurera JW, Quigley KS, Barrett LF, 2021. Expertise in emotion: a scoping review and unifying framework for individual differences in the mental representation of emotional experience. Psychol. Bull 147 (11), 1159–1183. 10.1037/bul0000327. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  313. Hoffman ML, 1986. Affect, cognition, and motivation. In Handbook of motivation and cognition: Foundations of social behavior. Guilford Press,, pp. 244–280. [Google Scholar]
  314. Hogan P, 2017. Literature and Emotion. Routledge. 10.4324/9781315644639. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  315. Hogan PC, 2011. What literature teaches us about emotion. Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, US. 10.1017/CBO9780511976773. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  316. Hohwy J, 2007. The sense of self in the phenomenology of agency and perception. Sense Self 13 (1), 20. [Google Scholar]
  317. Holton G, 1975. On the role of themata in scientific thought. Science 188 (4186), 328–334. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  318. Hommel B, 2019. Affect and control: a conceptual clarification. Int. J. Psychophysiol 144, 1–6. 10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2019.07.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  319. Hommel B, Moors A, Sander D, Deonna J, 2017. Emotion meets action: towards an integration of research and theory. Emot. Rev 9 (4), 295–298. 10.1177/1754073916689379. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  320. Hoque M, McDuff DJ, Morency L-P, Picard RW, 2011. Machine learning for affective computing. In: D’Mello S, Graesser A, Schuller B, Martin J-C (Eds.), Affective Computing and Intelligent Interaction. Springer., p. 567. 10.1007/978-3-642-24571-8_70 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  321. Horgan T, Tienson J, 1996. Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  322. Horgan T, & Tienson J (2002). The Intentionality of Phenomenology and the Phenomenology of Intentionality. https://philpapers.org/rec/HORTIO. [Google Scholar]
  323. Horgan T, Tienson J, Graham G, 2003. The phenomenology of first-person agency. In Physicalism and mental causation: The metaphysics of mind and action. Imprint Academic, pp. 323–340. [Google Scholar]
  324. Horwitz AV, Wakefield JC, 2007. The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow into Depressive Disorder. Oxford University Press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  325. Hufendiek R, 2015. Embodied Emotions: A Naturalist Approach to a Normative Phenomenon. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  326. Husserl E, Dummett M, 2001. Logical Investigations. Routledge, London; New York. [Google Scholar]
  327. Husserl E, 2013. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Springer Science & Business Media. [Google Scholar]
  328. Hutto DD, 2012. Truly enactive emotion. Emot. Rev 4 (2), 176–181. 10.1177/1754073911430134. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  329. Hutto DD, Satne G, 2015. The natural origins of content. Philosophia 43 (3), 521–536. 10.1007/s11406-015-9644-0. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  330. Hutto DD, Myin E, 2017. Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  331. Isen AM, 1984. Toward understanding the role of affect in cognition, in: Handbook of Social Cognition, Vol 3. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers, Mahwah, NJ, US, pp. 179–236. [Google Scholar]
  332. Isen AM, 1987. Positive affect, cognitive processes, and social behavior. In: Advances in experimental social psychology, Vol. 20. Academic Press, pp. 203–253. [Google Scholar]
  333. Itkonen E, 1978. Grammatical Theory and Metascience: A critical investigation into the methodological and philosophical foundations of “autonomous” linguistics. John Benjamins Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  334. Ivanova M, 2014. Is There a Place for Epistemic Virtues in Theory Choice? In: Fairweather A (Ed.), Virtue Epistemology Naturalized: Bridges Between Virtue Epistemology and Philosophy of Science. Springer International Publishing, pp. 207–226. 10.1007/978-3-319-04672-3_13. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  335. Ivanova M, 2017. Aesthetic values in science. Philos. Compass 12 (10), e12433. [Google Scholar]
  336. Ivanova M, Farr M, 2020. Methods in science and metaphysics. Routledge Handb. Metametaphysics Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  337. Iwasaki Y, MacTavish J, MacKay K, 2005. Building on strengths and resilience: Leisure as a stress survival strategy. Br. J. Guid. Couns 33 (1), 81–100. 10.1080/03069880412331335894. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  338. Izard C, Stark K, Trentacosta C, Schultz D, 2008. Beyond emotion regulation: emotion utilization and adaptive functioning. Child Dev. Perspect 2 (3), 156–163. 10.1111/j.1750-8606.2008.00058.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  339. Izard CE, 1978. Emotions as motivations: An evolutionary-developmental perspective. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation 26, 163–200. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  340. Izard CE, 1992. Basic emotions, relations among emotions, and emotion-cognition relations. Psychological Review 99 (3), 561–565. 10.1037/0033-295X.99.3.561. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  341. Izard CE, 2007. Basic emotions, natural kinds, emotion schemas, and a new paradigm. Perspect. Psychol. Sci 2 (3), 260–280. 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2007.00044.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  342. Izard CE, 2010a. More meanings and more questions for the term “emotion”. Emot. Rev 2 (4), 383–385. [Google Scholar]
  343. Izard CE, 2010b. The many meanings/aspects of emotion: definitions, functions, activation, and regulation. Emot. Rev 2 (4), 363–370. [Google Scholar]
  344. Jabareen Y, 2009. Building a conceptual framework: philosophy, definitions, and procedure. Int. J. Qual. Methods 8 (4), 49–62. 10.1177/160940690900800406. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  345. James W, 1890. The Principles of Psychology. Dover Publications. [Google Scholar]
  346. Joffily M, Coricelli G, 2013. Emotional valence and the free-energy principle. PLoS Comput. Biol 9 (6), e1003094 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003094. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  347. Jonas H, 1973. Organismus und Freiheit: Ansätze zu einer philosophischen Biologie. Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht. [Google Scholar]
  348. Jonas H, 2001. The Phenomenon of Life: Toward a Philosophical Biology. Northwestern University Press. [Google Scholar]
  349. Jones BE, 2003. Arousal systems. Front. Biosci.: A J. Virtual Libr 8, s438–s451. 10.2741/1074. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  350. Juslin PN, 2013. From everyday emotions to aesthetic emotions: towards a unified theory of musical emotions. Phys. Life Rev 10 (3), 235–266. 10.1016/j.plrev.2013.05.008. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  351. Kaelbling LP, Littman ML, Moore AW, 1996. Reinforcement learning: a survey. J. Artif. Intell. Res 4, 237–285. 10.1613/jair.301. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  352. Kaneko D, Toet A, Brouwer A-M, Kallen V, van Erp JBF, 2018. Methods for Evaluating Emotions Evoked by Food Experiences: A Literature Review. Front. Psychol, 9. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2018.00911. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  353. Kant I, 1781. Critique of pure reason. Modern Classical Philosophers. Houghton Mifflin; (1908), Cambridge, MA, pp. 370–456. [Google Scholar]
  354. Kanwisher N, 2010. Functional specificity in the human brain: a window into the functional architecture of the mind. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 107 (25), 11163–11170. 10.1073/pnas.1005062107. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  355. Karatsoreos IN, McEwen BS, 2011. Psychobiological allostasis: resistance, resilience and vulnerability. Trends Cogn. Sci 15 (12), 576–584. 10.1016/j.tics.2011.10.005. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  356. Kauffman SA, 1970. Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. PSA: Proc. Bienn. Meet. Philos. Sci. Assoc 1970, 257–272. [Google Scholar]
  357. Keas MN, 2018. Systematizing the theoretical virtues. Synthese 195 (6), 2761–2793. [Google Scholar]
  358. Keltner D, Gross JJ, 1999. Functional accounts of emotions. Cogn. Emot 13 (5), 467–480. 10.1080/026999399379140. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  359. Keltner D, Lerner JS, 2010. Emotion, in: Handbook of Social Psychology, Vol. 1, 5th Ed. John Wiley & Sons, Inc., Hoboken, NJ, US, pp. 317–352. 10.1002/9780470561119.socpsy001009. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  360. Kenny DA, Kenny A, 2003. Action, Emotion and Will. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  361. Kind A, 2001. Putting the image back in imagination. Philos. Phenomenol. Res 62 (1), 85–109. 10.2307/2653590. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  362. Kind A, 2013. The Case against Representationalism about Moods. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  363. King P, 2009. Emotions in Medieval Thought. In: Goldie P (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Emotion (p. 0). Oxford University Press. 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199235018.003.0008. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  364. Kirsh D, Maglio P, 1994. On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cogn. Sci 18 (4), 513–549. 10.1016/0364-0213(94)90007-8. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  365. Kitcher P, 2001. Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  366. Kiverstein J, Kirchhoff MD, Thacker M, 2022. An embodied predictive processing theory of pain experience. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 13 (4), 973–998. [Google Scholar]
  367. Kleinginna PR, Kleinginna AM, 1981. A categorized list of emotion definitions, with suggestions for a consensual definition. Motiv. Emot 5 (4), 345–379. 10.1007/BF00992553. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  368. Klinger E, 1975. Consequences of commitment to and disengagement from incentives. Psychol. Rev 82 (1), 1–25. 10.1037/h0076171. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  369. Knill DC, Pouget A, 2004. The Bayesian brain: the role of uncertainty in neural coding and computation. Trends Neurosci. 27 (12), 712–719. 10.1016/j.tins.2004.10.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  370. Koch C, Tsuchiya N, 2007. Phenomenology without conscious access is a form of consciousness without top-down attention. Behav. Brain Sci 30 (5–6), 509–510. 10.1017/S0140525X07002907. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  371. Koolhaas JM, Bartolomucci A, Buwalda B, de Boer SF, Flügge G, Korte SM, Meerlo P, Murison R, Olivier B, Palanza P, Richter-Levin G, Sgoifo A, Steimer T, Stiedl O, van Dijk G, Wöhr M, Fuchs E, 2011. Stress revisited: a critical evaluation of the stress concept. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 35 (5), 1291–1301. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2011.02.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  372. Kording KP, Blohm G, Schrater P, Kay K, 2020. Appreciating the variety of goals in computational neuroscience (arXiv:2002.03211). arXiv. 10.48550/arXiv.2002.03211. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  373. Kragel PA, LaBar KS, 2016. Decoding the nature of emotion in the brain. Trends Cogn. Sci 20 (6), 444–455. 10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.011. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  374. Kriegel U, 2014. The Sources of Intentionality, Reprint ed. Oxford University Press, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  375. Kriegel U, 2019. The Intentional Structure of Moods. Philosophers’ Imprint 19, 1–19. [Google Scholar]
  376. Krueger AB, Schkade DA, 2008. The reliability of subjective well-being measures. J. Public Econ 92 (8), 1833–1845. 10.1016/j.jpubeco.2007.12.015. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  377. Kübler-Ross E, Kessler D, 2005. On Grief and Grieving: Finding the Meaning of Grief Through the Five Stages of Loss. Simon and Schuster. [Google Scholar]
  378. Kuhn TS, 1974. Second thoughts on paradigms. Struct. Sci. Theor 2, 459–482. [Google Scholar]
  379. Kuhn TS, Hacking I, 2012. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions: 50th Anniversary, 4th ed. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. [Google Scholar]
  380. Kuppens P, Van Mechelen I, Smits DJ, De Boeck P, 2003. The appraisal basis of anger: specificity, necessity and sufficiency of components. Emotion 3 (3), 254. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  381. Kuppens P, Tuerlinckx F, Russell JA, Barrett LF, 2013. The relation between valence and arousal in subjective experience. Psychol. Bull 139 (4), 917–940. 10.1037/a0030811. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  382. Kuppens P, Dejonckheere E, Kalokerinos EK, Koval P, 2022. Some recommendations on the use of daily life methods in affective science. Affect. Sci 3 (2), 505–515. 10.1007/s42761-022-00101-0. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  383. Kuppens P, Tuerlinckx F, Yik M, Koval P, Coosemans J, Zeng KJ, Russell JA, 2017. The relation between valence and arousal in subjective experience varies with personality and culture. J. Personal 85 (4), 530–542. 10.1111/jopy.12258. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  384. Lacewing M, 2007. Do unconscious emotions involve unconscious feelings. Philos. Psychol 20 (1), 81–104. 10.1080/09515080601023402. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  385. Lachman ME, Weaver SL, 1998. The sense of control as a moderator of social class differences in health and well-being. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 74 (3), 763–773. 10.1037//0022-3514.74.3.763. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  386. Ladyman J, 2012. Science, metaphysics and method. Philos. Stud 160, 31–51. [Google Scholar]
  387. Lakatos I, 1978. Science and pseudoscience. Philos. Pap 1, 1–7. [Google Scholar]
  388. Lakatos I, 2014. Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Philosophy. Science, and History Routledge, pp. 89–94. [Google Scholar]
  389. Lakin JL, Jefferis VE, Cheng CM, Chartrand TL, 2003. The chameleon effect as social glue: evidence for the evolutionary significance of nonconscious mimicry. J. Nonverbal Behav 27 (3), 145–162. 10.1023/A:1025389814290. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  390. Lambie JA, Marcel AJ, 2002. Consciousness and the varieties of emotion experience: a theoretical framework. Psychol. Rev 109 (2), 219–259. 10.1037/0033-295X.109.2.219. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  391. Lang PJ, Bradley MM, 2008. Appetitive and defensive motivation is the substrate of emotion. In Handbook of approach and avoidance motivation. Psychology Press,, pp. 51–65. [Google Scholar]
  392. Lange CG, 1885. Om sindsbevaegelser; et psyko-fysiologisk studie. Lund.,.
  393. Larsen JT, McGraw AP, 2014. The case for mixed emotions. Soc. Personal. Psychol. Compass 8 (6), 263–274. 10.1111/spc3.12108. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  394. Latour B, Woolgar S, 2013. Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
  395. Laudan L (1978). Progress and Its Problems: Towards a Theory of Scientific Growth.
  396. Lazarus RS, 2001. Relational meaning and discrete emotions. In. Appraisal processes in emotion: Theory, methods, research. Oxford University Press,, pp. 37–67. [Google Scholar]
  397. Leary MR, 2000. Affect, cognition, and the social emotions. In Feeling and thinking: The role of affect in social cognition. Cambridge University Press,, pp. 331–356. [Google Scholar]
  398. LeDoux J, 1996. Emotional networks and motor control: a fearful view. Prog. Brain Res 107, 437–446. 10.1016/s0079-6123(08)61880-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  399. LeDoux J, 2012. Rethinking the emotional brain. Neuron 73 (4), 653–676. 10.1016/j.neuron.2012.02.004. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  400. LeDoux J, 2023. Deep history and beyond: a reply to commentators. Philos. Psychol 36 (4), 756–766. 10.1080/09515089.2022.2160312. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  401. LeDoux JE, 1989. Cognitive-emotional interactions in the brain. Cogn. Emot 3 (4), 267–289. 10.1080/02699938908412709. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  402. LeDoux JE, 1998. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life. Simon and Schuster. [Google Scholar]
  403. LeDoux JE, 2015. Feelings: what are they & how does the brain make them? Daedalus 144 (1), 96–111. 10.1162/DAED_a_00319. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  404. LeDoux JE, 2022. As soon as there was life, there was danger: the deep history of survival behaviours and the shallower history of consciousness. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 377 (1844), 20210292. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  405. LeDoux JE, Brown R, 2017. A higher-order theory of emotional consciousness. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 114 (10) 10.1073/pnas.1619316114. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  406. LeDoux JE, Hofmann SG, 2018. The subjective experience of emotion: a fearful view. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 19, 67–72. 10.1016/j.cobeha.2017.09.011. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  407. Lee KM, Ferreira-Santos F, Satpute AB, 2021. Predictive processing models and affective neuroscience. Neuroscience and biobehavioral reviews 131, 211–228. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2021.09.009. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  408. Lee TS, Mumford D, 2003. Hierarchical Bayesian inference in the visual cortex. JOSA A 20 (7), 1434–1448. 10.1364/JOSAA.20.001434. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  409. Leighton SR, 1985. A new view of emotion. Am. Philos. Q 22 (2), 133–141. [Google Scholar]
  410. Lench HC, Tibbett TP, Bench SW, 2016. Exploring the toolkit of emotion: what do sadness and anger do for us? Soc. Personal. Psychol. Compass 10 (1), 11–25. 10.1111/spc3.12229. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  411. Lerner JS, Keltner D, 2000. Beyond valence: toward a model of emotion-specific influences on judgement and choice. Cogn. Emot 14 (4), 473–493. 10.1080/026999300402763. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  412. Lerner JS, Keltner D, 2001. Fear, anger, and risk. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 81 (1), 146–159. 10.1037/0022-3514.81.1.146. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  413. Levenson RW, 2011. Basic emotion questions. Emot. Rev 3 (4), 379–386. 10.1177/1754073911410743. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  414. Levenstein D, Alvarez VA, Amarasingham A, Azab H, Chen ZS, Gerkin RC, Hasenstaub A, Iyer R, Jolivet RB, Marzen S, Monaco JD, Prinz AA, Quraishi S, Santamaria F, Shivkumar S, Singh MF, Traub R, Nadim F, Rotstein HG, Redish AD, 2023. On the role of theory and modeling in neuroscience. J. Neurosci 43 (7), 1074–1088. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.1179-22.2022. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  415. Leventhal H, Diefenbach M, 1991. The Active Side of Illness Cognition. In: Skelton JA, Croyle RT (Eds.), Mental Representation in Health and Illness. Springer, US, pp. 247–272. 10.1007/978-1-4613-9074-9_11. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  416. Levin M, 2019. The Computational Boundary of a “Self”: Developmental Bioelectricity Drives Multicellularity and Scale-Free Cognition. Front. Psychol 10. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02688. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  417. Levine J, 1983. Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pac. Philos. Q 64 (4), 354–361. 10.1111/j.1468-0114.1983.tb00207.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  418. Levine S, 2018. Reinforcement Learning and Control as Probabilistic Inference: Tutorial and Review (arXiv:1805.00909). arXiv. 10.48550/arXiv.1805.00909. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  419. Levy A, Bechtel W, 2013. Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philos. Sci 80 (2), 241–261. [Google Scholar]
  420. Levy I, Schiller D, 2021. Neural Computations of Threat. Trends Cogn. Sci 25, 151–171. 10.1016/j.tics.2020.11.007. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  421. Lewis D, 1970. How to define theoretical terms. J. Philos 67 (13), 427–446. [Google Scholar]
  422. Lewis D, 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australas. J. Philos 50 (3), 249–258. [Google Scholar]
  423. Li Z, Lu H, Liu D, Yu ANC, Gendron M, 2023. Emotional event perception is related to lexical complexity and emotion knowledge. PsyArXiv. 10.31234/osf.io/vfsc4. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  424. Lin H, Coricelli G, Feng C, Luo S, Young S, 2023. Social Emotions and Their Influences. Frontiers Media; SA. [Google Scholar]
  425. Lindquist KA, 2021. Language and emotion: introduction to the special issue. Affect. Sci 2 (2), 91–98. 10.1007/s42761-021-00049-7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  426. Lindquist KA, Satpute AB, Gendron M, 2015. Does language do more than communicate emotion. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci 24 (2), 99–108. 10.1177/0963721414553440. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  427. Locke J, 1847. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Kay & Troutman. [Google Scholar]
  428. Lopez SJ, & Snyder CR (2011). The Oxford Handbook of Positive Psychology. OUP; USA. [Google Scholar]
  429. Lowe EJ, 2002. A survey of metaphysics, (Vol. 15).. Oxford University Press, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  430. Lutz C, White GM, 1986. The Anthropology of Emotions. Annual Review of Anthropology 15 (1), 405–436. 10.1146/annurev.an.15.100186.002201. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  431. Lyons W, 2005. Philos. Cogn. Emot 21–44. 10.1002/0470013494.ch2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  432. Lyubomirsky S, Sheldon KM, Schkade D, 2005. Pursuing happiness: the architecture of sustainable change. Rev. Gen. Psychol 9 (2), 111–131. 10.1037/1089-2680.9.2.111. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  433. Del Giudice M. 2021. The motivational architecture of emotions. The Oxford Handbook of Evolution and the Emotions. Oxford, p. 39. [Google Scholar]
  434. MacArthur R, 1955. Fluctuations of animal populations and a measure of community stability. Ecology 36 (3), 533–536. 10.2307/1929601. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  435. Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF, 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philos. Sci 67 (1), 1–25. 10.1086/392759. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  436. MacLeod M, 2018. What makes interdisciplinarity difficult? Some consequences of domain specificity in interdisciplinary practice. Synthese 195 (2), 697–720. 10.1007/s11229-016-1236-4. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  437. Maddux JE, 2017. Subjective Well-Being and Life Satisfaction. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  438. Maia TV, Huys QJM, Frank MJ, 2017. Theory-based computational psychiatry. Biol. Psychiatry 82 (6), 382–384. 10.1016/j.biopsych.2017.07.016. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  439. Markovic S, 2012. Components of aesthetic experience: aesthetic fascination, aesthetic appraisal, and aesthetic emotion. I-Percept. 3 (1), 1–17. 10.1068/i0450aap. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  440. Marr D, 2010. Vision: a computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, USA. [Google Scholar]
  441. Marsella S, Gratch J, 2016. Computational models of emotion as psychological tools. In: Barrett LF, Lewis M, Haviland-Jones JM (Eds.), Handbook of emotions, 4th ed. Guilford Press, pp. 113–129. [Google Scholar]
  442. Marsella S, Gratch J, Petta P, 2010. Computational models of emotion. A Blueprint for Affective Computing-A sourcebook and manual 11 (1), 21–46. [Google Scholar]
  443. Marsella SC, Gratch J, 2009. EMA: A process model of appraisal dynamics. Cognitive Systems Research 10 (1), 70–90. 10.1016/j.cogsys.2008.03.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  444. Mastandrea S, Fagioli S, Biasi V, 2019. Art and psychological well-being: linking the brain to the aesthetic emotion. Front. Psychol, 10. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00739. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  445. Maturana HR (1980). Autopoiesis: reproduction, heredity and evolution. In Autopoiesis, dissipative structures and spontaneous social orders, AAAS Selected Symposium 55 (AAAS National Annual Meeting, Houston TX, 3–8 January 1979) (pp. 45–79). Westview Press. [Google Scholar]
  446. Maturana HR, Varela FJ, 1991. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Springer Science & Business Media. [Google Scholar]
  447. Mauss IB, Robinson MD, 2009. Measures of emotion: a review. Cogn. Emot 23 (2), 209–237. 10.1080/02699930802204677. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  448. Mayr E, 1985. Teleological and Teleonomic, a New Analysis. In: Cohen RS, Wartofsky MW (Eds.), A Portrait of Twenty-Five Years: Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1960–1985, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Springer, Netherlands, Dordrecht, pp. 133–159. 10.1007/978-94-009-5345-1_10. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  449. Mayr E, 1998. The Multiple Meanings of “Teleological.”. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 20 (1), 35–40. [Google Scholar]
  450. McEwen BS, 1998. Stress, adaptation, and disease: allostasis and allostatic load. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci 840 (1), 33–44. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1998.tb09546.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  451. McEwen BS, 2000. Allostasis and allostatic load: implications for neuropsychopharmacology. Neuropsychopharmacology 22 (2), 108–124. 10.1016/S0893-133X(99)00129-3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  452. McEwen BS, 2005. Stressed or stressed out: what is the difference? J. Psychiatry Neurosci 30 (5), 315–318. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  453. McEwen BS, Seeman T, 1999. Protective and damaging effects of mediators of stress: elaborating and testing the concepts of allostasis and allostatic load. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci 896 (1), 30–47. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1999.tb08103.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  454. McEwen BS, Wingfield JC, 2003. The concept of allostasis in biology and biomedicine. Horm. Behav 43 (1), 2–15. 10.1016/S0018-506X(02)00024-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  455. McEwen BS, Akil H, 2020. Revisiting the stress concept: implications for affective disorders. J. Neurosci.: Off. J. Soc. Neurosci 40 (1), 12–21. 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0733-19.2019. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  456. McLaughlin P, 2000. What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-Reproducing Systems. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  457. Mehrabian A, Epstein N, 1972. A measure of emotional empathy. J. Personal 40 (4), 525–543. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.1972.tb00078.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  458. Mehrabian A, Russell JA, 1974. An approach to environmental psychology (pp. xii, 266). The MIT Press,. [Google Scholar]
  459. Mele AR, 1997. Agency and Mental Action. Philos. Perspect 11, 231–249. [Google Scholar]
  460. Melnikoff DE, Carlson RW, Stillman PE, 2022. A computational theory of the subjective experience of flow. Article 1 Nat. Commun 13 (1). 10.1038/s41467-022-29742-2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  461. Mendelovici A, 2013. Pure Intentionalism about Moods and Emotions. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Mind. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  462. Menninghaus W, Wagner V, Wassiliwizky E, Schindler I, Hanich J, Jacobsen T, Koelsch S, 2019. What are aesthetic emotions. Psychol. Rev 126 (2), 171–195. 10.1037/rev0000135. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  463. Mercado LN, 1994. The Filipino mind. Council for Research in Values and Philosophy. [Google Scholar]
  464. Merleau-Ponty M, 2011. Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge. 10.4324/9780203720714. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  465. Mesquita B, Frijda NH, 1992. Cultural variations in emotions: A review. Psychological Bulletin 112 (2), 179–204. 10.1037/0033-2909.112.2.179. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  466. Metzinger T, 2003a. Being No One: The Self-Model Theory of Subjectivity. MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/1551.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  467. Metzinger T, 2003b. Phenomenal transparency and cognitive self-reference. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 2 (4), 353–393. 10.1023/B:PHEN.0000007366.42918.eb. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  468. Metzinger T, 2013. Why are dreams interesting for philosophers? The example of minimal phenomenal selfhood, plus an agenda for future research1. Front. Psychol 4. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00746. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  469. Metzinger T, 2017. Probl. Ment. Action https://philpapers.org/rec/METTPO-14.
  470. Michaels A, Wulf C, 2020. Emotions in Rituals and Performances: South Asian and European Perspectives on Rituals and Performativity. Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
  471. Migeot J, Hesse E, Fittipaldi S, Mejía J, Fraile M, García AM, García M, del C, Ortega R, Lawlor B, Lopez V, Ibáñez A, 2023. Allostatic-interoceptive anticipation of social rejection. NeuroImage 276, 120200. 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2023.120200. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  472. Milkowski M, Litwin P, 2022. Testable or bust: Theoretical lessons for predictive processing. Synthese 200 (6), 462. 10.1007/s11229-022-03891-9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  473. Mill JS, 1856. A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive: 1. Parker. [Google Scholar]
  474. Miller M, Kiverstein J, Rietveld E, 2022. The Predictive Dynamics of Happiness and Well-Being. Emotion Review 14 (1), 15–30. 10.1177/17540739211063851. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  475. Millidge B, Tschantz A, Seth AK, Buckley CL, 2020. On the Relationship Between Active Inference and Control as Inference. In: Verbelen T, Lanillos P, Buckley CL, De Boom C (Eds.), Active Inference. Springer International Publishing, pp. 3–11. 10.1007/978-3-030-64919-7_1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  476. Millikan RG, 1987. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  477. Millikan RG, 1989. In Defense of Proper Functions. Philos. Sci 56 (2), 288–302. [Google Scholar]
  478. Mitchell SD, 2003. Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism. Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511802683. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  479. Mitchell SD, 2012. Unsimple Truths: Science. Complexity, and Policy. University of Chicago Press. 〈https://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/books/book/chicago/U/bo8205034.html〉. [Google Scholar]
  480. Mobbs D, Adolphs R, Fanselow MS, Barrett LF, LeDoux JE, Ressler K, Tye KM, 2019. Viewpoints: approaches to defining and investigating fear. Article 8 Nat. Neurosci 22 (8). 10.1038/s41593-019-0456-6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  481. Moerland TM, Broekens J, Jonker CM, 2018. Emotion in reinforcement learning agents and robots: a survey. Mach. Learn 107 (2), 443–480. 10.1007/s10994-017-5666-0. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  482. Möller TJ, Georgie YK, Schillaci G, Voss M, Hafner VV, Kaltwasser L, 2021. Computational models of the “active self” and its disturbances in schizophrenia. Conscious. Cogn 93, 103155 10.1016/j.concog.2021.103155. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  483. Moore JW, 2016. What is the sense of agency and why does it matter. Front. Psychol 7, 1272. 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01272. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  484. Moors A, 2017a. Integration of two skeptical emotion theories: Dimensional appraisal theory and Russell’s psychological construction theory. Psychological Inquiry 28 (1), 1–19. [Google Scholar]
  485. Moors A, 2017b. The integrated theory of emotional behavior follows a radically goal-directed approach. Psychological Inquiry 28 (1), 68–75. [Google Scholar]
  486. Moors A, 2022. Demystifying emotions: A typology of theories in psychology and philosophy. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  487. Moors A, Fischer M, 2019. Demystifying the role of emotion in behaviour: toward a goal-directed account. Cogn. Emot 33 (1), 94–100. 10.1080/02699931.2018.1510381. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  488. Morganti M, Tahko TE, 2017. Moderately naturalistic metaphysics. Synthese 194 (7), 2557–2580. 10.1007/s11229-016-1068-2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  489. Morris WN, Schnurr PP, 1989. Mood: The frame of mind, 261. Springer-Verlag Publishing, p. xii. [Google Scholar]
  490. Mulligan K, Scherer KR, 2012. Toward a working definition of emotion. Emot. Rev 4 (4), 345–357. [Google Scholar]
  491. Na S, Rhoads SA, Yu ANC, Fiore VG, Gu X, 2023. Towards a neurocomputational account of social controllability: From models to mental health. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 148, 105139 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2023.105139. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  492. Nagel T, 1974. What Is It Like to Be a Bat. Philos. Rev 83 (4), 435–450. 10.2307/2183914. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  493. Nave K, 2023. A Drive to Survive: The free energy principle and the meaning of life (draft). PsyArXiv. 10.31234/osf.io/ds9mn. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  494. Neal RM, 2012. Bayesian Learning for Neural Networks. Springer Science & Business Media. [Google Scholar]
  495. Neander K, 1995. Misrepresenting & Malfunctioning. Philos. Stud.: Int. J. Philos. Anal. Tradit 79 (2), 109–141. [Google Scholar]
  496. Neimeyer RA, Klass D, Dennis MR, 2014. A social constructionist account of grief: Loss and the narration of meaning. Death Stud. 38 (6–10), 485–498. 10.1080/07481187.2014.913454. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  497. Neiss R, 1988. Reconceptualizing arousal: psychobiological states in motor performance. Psychol. Bull 103 (3), 345–366. 10.1037/0033-2909.103.3.345. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  498. Neisser U, 1963. The Imitation of Man by Machine: the view that machines will think as man does reveals misunderstanding of the nature of human thought. Science 139 (3551), 193–197. 10.1126/science.139.3551.193. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  499. Nelkin N, 1989. Unconscious sensations. Philos. Psychol 2 (2), 129–141. 10.1080/09515088908572969. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  500. Nesse RM, 1990. Evolutionary explanations of emotions. Hum. Nat 1 (3), 261–289. 10.1007/BF02733986. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  501. Newen A, Bruin LD, Gallagher S, Newen A, Bruin LD, Gallagher S (Eds.), 2018. The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  502. Newton I, 1999. The Principia: Mathematical principles of natural philosophy. Univ of California Press, Berkeley. [Google Scholar]
  503. Niv Y, Daw ND, Joel D, Dayan P, 2007. Tonic dopamine: opportunity costs and the control of response vigor. Psychopharmacology 191 (3), 507–520. 10.1007/s00213-006-0502-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  504. Norman D, 2002. Emotion & design: attractive things work better. Interactions 9 (4), 36–42. 10.1145/543434.543435. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  505. Norman DA, 2013. The Design of Everyday Things. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  506. Notturno MA, Popper K, 2014. Myth Framew.: Def. Sci. Ration
  507. Nummenmaa L, Hari R, Hietanen JK, Glerean E, 2018. Maps of subjective feelings. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 115 (37), 9198–9203. 10.1073/pnas.1807390115. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  508. O’Regan JK, Nöe A, 2001. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci 24 (5), 939–973. 10.1017/S0140525X01000115. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  509. Oatley K, Johnson-Laird PN, 2014. Cognitive approaches to emotions. Trends Cogn. Sci 18 (3), 134–140. 10.1016/j.tics.2013.12.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  510. Ochsner KN, Gross JJ, 2005. Putting the ‘I’ and the ‘Me’ in emotion regulation: Reply to Northoff. Trends Cogn. Sci 9 (9), 409–410. 10.1016/j.tics.2005.06.004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  511. Ochsner KN, Phelps E, 2007. Emerging perspectives on emotion-cognition interactions. Trends Cogn. Sci 11 (8), 317–318. 10.1016/j.tics.2007.06.008. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  512. Oishi S, Choi H, Koo M, Galinha I, Ishii K, Komiya A, Luhmann M, Scollon C, Shin J, Lee H, Suh EM, Vittersø J, Heintzelman SJ, Kushlev K, Westgate EC, Buttrick N, Tucker J, Ebersole CR, Axt J, Besser LL, 2020. Happiness, Meaning, and Psychological Richness. Affect. Sci 1 (2), 107–115. 10.1007/s42761-020-00011-z. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  513. Okon-Singer H, Hendler T, Pessoa L, Shackman AJ, 2015. The neurobiology of emotion–cognition interactions: Fundamental questions and strategies for future research. Front. Hum. Neurosci 9. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00058. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  514. Ombrato MD, Phillips E, 2021. The mind of the hungry agent: hunger, affect and appetite. Topoi 40 (3), 517–526. 10.1007/s11245-020-09733-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  515. Ormerod RJ, 2009. The history and ideas of critical rationalism: the philosophy of Karl Popper and its implications for OR. J. Oper. Res. Soc 60, 441–460. [Google Scholar]
  516. Ortony A, 1988. Are emotion metaphors conceptual or lexical. Cogn. Emot 2 (2), 95–104. 10.1080/02699938808408066. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  517. Oxford English Dictionary. (2023). -ome, comb. Form Oxford University Press; Oxford English Dictionary. 10.1093/OED/7066684522. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  518. Pace-Schott EF, Amole MC, Aue T, Balconi M, Bylsma LM, Critchley H, Demaree HA, Friedman BH, Gooding AEK, Gosseries O, Jovanovic T, Kirby LAJ, Kozlowska K, Laureys S, Lowe L, Magee K, Marin M-F, Merner AR, Robinson JL, VanElzakker MB, 2019. Physiological feelings (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 103, 267–304. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.05.002. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  519. Pacherie E, 2007. The sense of control and the sense of agency. Psyche 13 (1), 1. [Google Scholar]
  520. Pacherie E, 2008. The phenomenology of action: a conceptual framework. Cognition 107 (1), 179–217. 10.1016/j.cognition.2007.09.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  521. Pak JH, 2021. Toward Understanding the Psychology of Emotion, Indigenous Spirituality and Christianity in Korea. In: Dueck A (Ed.), Indigenous Psychology of Spirituality: In My Beginning is My End. Springer International Publishing, pp. 203–225. 10.1007/978-3-030-50869-2_9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  522. Palacios ER, Razi A, Parr T, Kirchhoff M, Friston K, 2020. On Markov blankets and hierarchical self-organisation. J. Theor. Biol 486, 110089 10.1016/j.jtbi.2019.110089. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  523. Panksepp J, 1998. The periconscious substrates of consciousness: Affective states and the evolutionary origins of the self. Journal of consciousness studies 5 (5–6), 566–582. [Google Scholar]
  524. Panksepp J, 2004. Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions. Oxford University Press, USA. [Google Scholar]
  525. Panksepp J, 2005. Affective consciousness: core emotional feelings in animals and humans. Conscious. Cogn 14 (1), 30–80. 10.1016/j.concog.2004.10.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  526. Panksepp J, 2008. The affective brain and core consciousness: How does neural activity generate emotional feelings? In Handbook of emotions, 3rd ed. The Guilford Press, pp. 47–67. [Google Scholar]
  527. Panksepp J, 2010. Affective neuroscience of the emotional BrainMind: Evolutionary perspectives and implications for understanding depression. Dialog-. Clin. Neurosci 12 (4), 533–545. 10.31887/DCNS.2010.12.4/jpanksepp. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  528. Panksepp J, Watt D, 2011. What is basic about basic emotions? Lasting lessons from affective neuroscience. Emot. Rev 3 (4), 387–396. 10.1177/1754073911410741. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  529. Paolo ED, Buhrmann T, Barandiaran X, 2017. Sensorimotor Life: An enactive proposal. Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198786849.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  530. Papineau D, 1984. Representation and Explanation. Philos. Sci 51 (4), 550–572. [Google Scholar]
  531. Parkes CM, 2013. Love and Loss: The Roots of Grief and its Complications. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  532. Parr T, Pezzulo G, Friston KJ, 2022. Active Inference: The Free Energy Principle in Mind, Brain, and Behavior. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  533. Paterson RJ, Neufeld RW, 1987. Clear danger: situational determinants of the appraisal of threat. Psychol. Bull 101 (3), 404–416. 10.1037/0033-2909.101.3.404. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  534. Paul ES, Sher S, Tamietto M, Winkielman P, Mendl MT, 2020. Towards a comparative science of emotion: Affect and consciousness in humans and animals. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 108, 749–770. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.11.014. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  535. Paul LA, 2012. Metaphysics as modeling: the handmaiden’s tale. Philos. Stud 160, 1–29. [Google Scholar]
  536. Peacocke C (2006). Mental Action and Self-Awareness. https://philpapers.org/rec/PEAMAA.
  537. Pereira A, 2021. Developing the concepts of homeostasis, homeorhesis, allostasis, elasticity, flexibility and plasticity of brain function. Article 4 NeuroSci 2 (4). 10.3390/neurosci2040027. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  538. Pernau M, 2021. Studying emotions in South Asia. South Asian Hist. Cult 12 (2–3), 111–128. 10.1080/19472498.2021.1878788. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  539. Perniss P, Vigliocco G, 2014. The bridge of iconicity: from a world of experience to the experience of language. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci 369 (1651), 20130300. 10.1098/rstb.2013.0300. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  540. Pessiglione M, Heerema R, Daunizeau J, Vinckier F, 2023. Origins and consequences of mood flexibility: a computational perspective. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 147, 105084 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2023.105084. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  541. Peters A, McEwen BS, Friston K, 2017. Uncertainty and stress: why it causes diseases and how it is mastered by the brain. Prog. Neurobiol 156, 164–188. 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2017.05.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  542. Petzschner FH, Weber LAE, Gard T, Stephan KE, 2017. Computational psychosomatics and computational psychiatry: toward a joint framework for differential diagnosis. Biol. Psychiatry 82 (6), 421–430. 10.1016/j.biopsych.2017.05.012. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  543. Pezzulo G, Levin M, 2016. Top-down models in biology: explanation and control of complex living systems above the molecular level. Journal of The Royal Society Interface 13 (124), 20160555. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  544. Pezzulo G, Rigoli F, Friston K, 2015. Active Inference, homeostatic regulation and adaptive behavioural control. Prog. Neurobiol 134, 17–35. 10.1016/j.pneurobio.2015.09.001. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  545. Pezzulo G, Parr T, Friston K, 2021. The evolution of brain architectures for predictive coding and active inference. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci 377 (1844), 20200531. 10.1098/rstb.2020.0531. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  546. Pezzulo G, Parr T, Friston K, 2022. The evolution of brain architectures for predictive coding and active inference. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 377 (1844), 20200531. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  547. Pfeifer R, Bongard J, 2006. How the Body Shapes the Way We Think: A New View of Intelligence. The MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/3585.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  548. Pham MT, 1998. Representativeness, relevance, and the use of feelings in decision making. Journal of consumer research 25 (2), 144–159. [Google Scholar]
  549. Picard RW, 2000. Affective Computing. MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/1140.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  550. Pinker S, 2010. The cognitive niche: coevolution of intelligence, sociality, and language. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 107 (supplement_2), 8993–8999. 10.1073/pnas.0914630107. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  551. Piredda G, 2020. What is an affective artifact? A further development in situated affectivity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 19, 549–567. [Google Scholar]
  552. Pitcher G, 1965. Emotion. Mind 74 (295), 326–346. [Google Scholar]
  553. Pitt D, 2004. The phenomenology of cognition or “what is it like to think that P?”. Philos. Phenomenol. Res 69 (1), 1–36. [Google Scholar]
  554. Plutchik R, 1982. A psychoevolutionary theory of emotions. Soc. Sci. Inf. /Sur Les. Sci. Soc 21 (4–5), 529–553. 10.1177/053901882021004003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  555. Plutchik R, Kellerman H, 2013. Theories of Emotion. Academic Press. [Google Scholar]
  556. Podilchak W, 1991. Distinctions of fun, enjoyment and leisure. Leis. Stud 10 (2), 133–148. 10.1080/02614369100390131. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  557. Poincaŕe H, 2022. The foundations of science: Science and hypothesis, the value of science, science and method. DigiCat. [Google Scholar]
  558. Popper KR, 1963. Science as falsification. Conjectures Refutations 1 (1963), 33–39. [Google Scholar]
  559. Porges SW, 1997. Emotion: an evolutionary by-product of the neural regulation of the autonomic nervous system. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci 807 (1 Integrative N), 62–77. 10.1111/j.1749-6632.1997.tb51913.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  560. Poria S, Cambria E, Bajpai R, Hussain A, 2017. A review of affective computing: from unimodal analysis to multimodal fusion. Inf. Fusion 37, 98–125. 10.1016/j.inffus.2017.02.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  561. Port RF, Van Gelder T, 1995. Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  562. Posner J, Russell JA, Peterson BS, 2005. The circumplex model of affect: an integrative approach to affective neuroscience, cognitive development, and psychopathology. Dev. Psychopathol 17 (3), 715–734. 10.1017/S0954579405050340. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  563. Pribram KH, McGuinness D, 1975. Arousal, activation, and effort in the control of attention. Psychol. Rev 82 (2), 116–149. 10.1037/h0076780. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  564. Price C, 2006. Affect without object: Moods and objectless emotions. Eur. J. Anal. Philos 2 (1). Article 1. [Google Scholar]
  565. Prokopenko M, Boschetti F, Ryan AJ, 2009. An information-theoretic primer on complexity, self-organization, and emergence. Complexity 15 (1), 11–28. 10.1002/cplx.20249. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  566. Pugmire D, 1998. Rediscovering Emotion: Emotion and the Claims of Feeling, first ed. Edinburgh University Press. [Google Scholar]
  567. Pylyshyn ZW, 1986. Computation and cognition: Toward a foundation for cognitive science, 292. The MIT Press,, p. xxiii. [Google Scholar]
  568. Quadt L, Critchley HD, Garfinkel SN, 2018. The neurobiology of interoception in health and disease. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci 1428 (1), 112–128. 10.1111/nyas.13915. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  569. Quadt L, Critchley H, Nagai Y, 2022. Cognition, emotion, and the central autonomic network. Auton. Neurosci.: Basic Clin 238, 102948 10.1016/j.autneu.2022.102948. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  570. Raber J, Arzy S, Bertolus JB, Depue B, Haas HE, Hofmann SG, Kangas M, Kensinger E, Lowry CA, Marusak HA, Minnier J, Mouly A-M, Mühlberger A, Norrholm SD, Peltonen K, Pinna G, Rabinak C, Shiban Y, Soreq H, Boutros SW, 2019. Current understanding of fear learning and memory in humans and animal models and the value of a linguistic approach for analyzing fear learning and memory in humans (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 105, 136–177. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2019.03.015. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  571. Railton P, 2017. At the core of our production and functionality. Synthesecapacity to act for a reason: the affective system and evaluative model-based learning and control. Emot. Rev 9 (4), 335–342. 10.1177/1754073916670021. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  572. Ramstead MJ, Kirchhoff MD, Friston KJ, 2020. A tale of two densities: active inference is enactive inference. Adapt. Behav 28 (4), 225–239. 10.1177/1059712319862774. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  573. Rapaport WJ, 2012. Semiotic systems, computers, and the mind: how cognition could be computing. Int. J. Signs Semiot. Syst 2 (1), 32–71. 10.4018/IJSSS.2012010102. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  574. Reuter K, forthcoming. Experimental Philosophy of Consciousness, in: Nichols S, Knobe J (Eds.), Oxford Studies of Consciousness. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  575. Reyes J, 2015. Loób and kapwa: an introduction to a filipino virtue ethics. Asian Philos. 25 (2), 148–171. 10.1080/09552367.2015.1043173. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  576. Ringstrom TJ, 2022. Reward is not necessary: how to create a compositional self-preserving agent for life-long learning (arXiv:2211.10851). arXiv. 10.48550/arXiv.2211.10851. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  577. Robbins TW, 1997. Arousal systems and attentional processes. Biol. Psychol 45 (1–3), 57–71. 10.1016/s0301-0511(96)05222-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  578. Robbins TW, Everitt BJ, 1995. Arousal systems and attention. In The cognitive neurosciences. The MIT Press, pp. 703–720. [Google Scholar]
  579. Robinson MD, Clore GL, 2002. Belief and feeling: Evidence for an accessibility model of emotional self-report. Psychol. Bull 128 (6), 934–960. 10.1037/0033-2909.128.6.934. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  580. Roediger HL, 1990. Implicit memory: retention without remembering. Am. Psychol 45 (9), 1043–1056. 10.1037/0003-066X.45.9.1043. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  581. Roessler J, Eilan N, 2003. Agency and Self-Awareness: Issues in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  582. Roseman IJ, Smith CA, 2001. Appraisal theory: overview, assumptions, varieties, controversies. In. Appraisal processes in emotion: Theory, methods, research. Oxford University Press, pp. 3–19. [Google Scholar]
  583. Rosenblueth A, Wiener N, Bigelow J, 1943. Behavior, Purpose and Teleology. Philos. Sci 10 (1), 18–24. 10.1086/286788. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  584. Rosenthal D, 2019. Consciousness and confidence. Neuropsychologia 128, 255–265. 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2018.01.018. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  585. Rosenthal DM, 1991. The independence of consciousness and sensory quality. Philos. Issues 1, 15–36. 10.2307/1522921. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  586. Rošker JS, 2021. Interpreting Chinese Philosophy: A New Methodology. Bloomsbury Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  587. Roth W-M, Jornet A, 2013. Situated cognition. WIREs Cogn. Sci 4 (5), 463–478. 10.1002/wcs.1242. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  588. Rotter JB, 1966. Generalized expectancies for internal versus external control of reinforcement. Psychol. Monogr.: Gen. Appl 80 (1), 1–28. 10.1037/h0092976. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  589. Roy M, Shohamy D, Daw N, Jepma M, Wimmer GE, Wager TD, 2014. Representation of aversive prediction errors in the human periaqueductal gray. Nature neuroscience 17 (11), 1607–1612. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  590. Ruiz-Mirazo K, Moreno A, 2012. Autonomy in evolution: From minimal to complex life. Synthese 185 (1), 21–52. 10.1007/s11229-011-9874-z. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  591. Russell B, 1905. On denoting. Mind 14 (56), 479–493. [Google Scholar]
  592. Russell JA, 1980. A circumplex model of affect. Journal of personality and social psychology 39 (6), 1161. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  593. Russell JA, 2003. Core affect and the psychological construction of emotion. Psychol. Rev 110 (1), 145–172. 10.1037/0033-295X.110.1.145. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  594. Russell JA, Weiss A, Mendelsohn GA, 1989. Affect Grid: a single-item scale of pleasure and arousal. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 57 (3), 493–502. 10.1037/0022-3514.57.3.493. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  595. Rutledge RB, Skandali N, Dayan P, Dolan RJ, 2014. A computational and neural model of momentary subjective well-being. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 111 (33), 12252–12257. 10.1073/pnas.1407535111. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  596. Ryan O, Dablander F, Haslbeck J, 2023. Towards a generative model for emotion dynamics. PsyArXiv. 10.31234/osf.io/x52ns. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  597. Sajid N, Ball PJ, Parr T, Friston KJ, 2021. Active inference: demystified and compared. Neural Comput. 33 (3), 674–712. 10.1162/neco_a_01357. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  598. Sander D, Scherer K, 2014. Oxford Companion to Emotion and the Affective Sciences. OUP, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  599. Sander D, Grafman J, Zalla T, 2003. The human amygdala: An evolved system for relevance detection. Rev. Neurosci 14 (4), 303–316. 10.1515/revneuro.2003.14.4.303. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  600. Sander D, Grandjean D, Scherer KR, 2005. A systems approach to appraisal mechanisms in emotion. Neural Netw. 18 (4), 317–352. 10.1016/j.neunet.2005.03.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  601. Sartre J-P, 2022. Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology. Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
  602. Satpute AB, Lindquist KA, 2021. At the neural intersection between language and emotion. Affect. Sci 2 (2), 207–220. 10.1007/s42761-021-00032-2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  603. Satpute AB, Nook EC, Cakar ME, 2020. The role of language in the construction of emotion and memory: A predictive coding view. In Neuroscience of enduring change: Implications for psychotherapy. Oxford University Press, pp. 56–88. 10.1093/oso/9780190881511.003.0004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  604. Satpute AB, Kragel PA, Barrett LF, Wager TD, Bianciardi M, 2019. Deconstructing arousal into wakeful, autonomic and affective varieties. Neurosci. Lett 693, 19–28. 10.1016/j.neulet.2018.01.042. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  605. Saxe R, 2006. Uniquely human social cogSemiotic systems, computers, and thenition. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol 16 (2), 235–239. 10.1016/j.conb.2006.03.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  606. Scarantino A, 2015. Basic emotions, psychological construction, and the problem of variability, in: The Psychological Construction of Emotion. The Guilford Press, New York, NY, US, pp. 334–376. [Google Scholar]
  607. Scarantino A, 2012. How to define emotions scientifically. Emot. Rev 4 (4), 358–368. [Google Scholar]
  608. Scarantino A, 2014. The motivational theory of emotions. In Moral psychology and human agency: Philosophical essays on the science of ethics. Oxford University Press,, pp. 156–185. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198717812.003.0008. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  609. Scarantino A, 2016. The philosophy of emotions and its impact on affective science. Handb. Emot 4, 3–48. [Google Scholar]
  610. Scarantino A, 2017. How to do things with emotional expressions: the theory of affective pragmatics. Psychol. Inq 28 (2–3), 165–185. 10.1080/1047840X.2017.1328951. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  611. Scherer KR, 1982a. Emotion as a process: function, origin and regulation. Soc. Sci. Inf 21 (4–5), 555–570. 10.1177/053901882021004004. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  612. Scherer KR, 1982b. The nature and function of emotion. Soc. Sci. Inf 21 (4–5), 507–509. 10.1177/053901882021004001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  613. Scherer KR, 1984. Emotion as a multicomponent process: A model and some cross-cultural data. Review of Personality & Social Psychology 5, 37–63. [Google Scholar]
  614. Scherer KR, 2005. What are emotions? And how can they be measured? Soc. Sci. Inf 44 (4), 695–729. [Google Scholar]
  615. Scherer KR, 2009. The dynamic architecture of emotion: evidence for the component process model. Cogn. Emot 23 (7), 1307–1351. 10.1080/02699930902928969. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  616. Scherer KR, Coutinho E, 2013. How music creates emotion: a multifactorial process approach. In: Cochrane T, Fantini B, Scherer KR (Eds.), The Emotional Power of Music: Multidisciplinary perspectives on musical arousal, expression, and social control. Oxford University Press, p. 0. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199654888.003.0010. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  617. Scherer KR, Moors A, 2019. The emotion process: event appraisal and component differentiation. Annu. Rev. Psychol 70, 719–745. 10.1146/annurev-psych-122216-011854. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  618. Scherer KR, Bänziger T, Roesch E, 2010. A Blueprint for Affective Computing: A Sourcebook and Manual. OUP; Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  619. Schindler S, 2018. Theoretical virtues in science: Uncovering reality through theory. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  620. Schlosser G, 1998. Self-re-production and functionality. Synthese 116 (3), 303–354. 10.1023/A:1005073307193. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  621. Schuler GD, Boguski MS, Stewart EA, Stein LD, Gyapay G, Rice K, White RE, Rodriguez-Tomé P, Aggarwal A, Bajorek E, Bentolila S, Birren BB, Butler A, Castle AB, Chiannilkulchai N, Chu A, Clee C, Cowles S, Day PJR, Hudson TJ, 1996. A gene map of the human genome. Science 274 (5287), 540–546. 10.1126/science.274.5287.540. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  622. Schulkin J, 2011. Social allostasis: anticipatory regulation of the internal milieu. Frontiers in evolutionary neuroscience 2, 111. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  623. Schulkin J, Sterling P, 2019. Allostasis: a brain-centered, predictive mode of physiological regulation. Trends Neurosci. 42 (10), 740–752. 10.1016/j.tins.2019.07.010. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  624. Schwarz N, 1999. Self-reports: how the questions shape the answers. Am. Psychol 54 (2), 93–105. 10.1037/0003-066X.54.2.93. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  625. Schwarz N, 2012. Feelings-as-information theory. Handb. Theor. Soc. Psychol 1, 289–308. [Google Scholar]
  626. Schwarz N, Clore GL, 1983. Mood, misattribution, and judgments of well-being: Informative and directive functions of affective states. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 45 (3), 513. [Google Scholar]
  627. Schwarz N, Clore GL, 1996. Feelings and phenomenal experiences. In. Social psychology: Handbook of basic principles. The Guilford Press,, pp. 433–465. [Google Scholar]
  628. Schwarz N, Strack F, 1999. Reports of subjective well-being: judgmental processes and their methodological implications. In Well-being: The foundations of hedonic psychology. Russell Sage Foundation, pp. 61–84. [Google Scholar]
  629. Schwarz N, Clore GL, 2003. Mood as Information: 20 Years Later. Psychol. Inq 14 (3–4), 296–303. 10.1080/1047840X.2003.9682896. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  630. Schwarz N, Clore GL, 2007. Feelings and phenomenal experiences, in: Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles, 2nd Ed. The Guilford Press, New York, NY, US, pp. 385–407. [Google Scholar]
  631. Schwarz N, Clore G, 1988. How do I feel about it? Informative functions of affective states, in: Affect, Cognition, and Social Behavior: New Evidence and Integrative Attempts. C.J. Hogrefe, Toronto, pp. 44–62. [Google Scholar]
  632. Seager W, 1999. Conscious intentionality. In: Fisette D (Ed.), Consciousness and Intentionality: Models and Modalities of Attribution. Springer, Netherlands, pp. 33–49. 10.1007/978-94-015-9193-5_2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  633. Searle JR, 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  634. Searle JR, 1992, 1st ed.. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Bradford Books, Cambridge, MA. [Google Scholar]
  635. Sebeok TA, 2001. Signs: An Introduction to Semiotics. University of Toronto Press. [Google Scholar]
  636. Sel A, 2014. Predictive codes of interoception, emotion, and the self. Front. Psychol 5. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00189. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  637. Sennesh E, Theriault J, Brooks D, van de Meent J-W, Barrett LF, Quigley KS, 2022. Interoception as modeling, allostasis as control. Biol. Psychol 167, 108242 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2021.108242. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  638. Sequeira P, Melo FS, Paiva A, 2011. Emotion-Based Intrinsic Motivation for Reinforcement Learning Agents. In: D’Mello S, Graesser A, Schuller B, Martin J-C (Eds.), Affective Computing and Intelligent Interaction, Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer, Berlin, Heidelber, pp. 326–336. 10.1007/978-3-642-24600-5_36. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  639. Seth AK, 2013. Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends Cogn. Sci 17 (11), 565–573. 10.1016/j.tics.2013.09.007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  640. Seth AK, Friston KJ, 2016. Active interoceptive inference and the emotional brain. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci 371 (1708), 20160007. 10.1098/rstb.2016.0007. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  641. Shargel D, Prinz J, 2017. An Enactivist Theory of Emotional Content. In: Teroni F, Naar H (Eds.), The Ontology of Emotions. Cambridge University Press, pp. 110–129. 10.1017/9781316275221.007. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  642. Shear K, Shair H, 2005. Attachment, loss, and complicated grief. Dev. Psychobiol 47 (3), 253–267. 10.1002/dev.20091. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  643. Shiffman S, Stone A, Hufford M, 2008. Ecolocial momentary assessment. Annu. Rev. Clin. Psychol 4, 1–32. 10.1146/annurev.clinpsy.3.022806.091415. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  644. Shin LM, Liberzon I, 2010. The neurocircuitry of fear, stress, and anxiety disorders. Article 1 Neuropsychopharmacology 35 (1). 10.1038/npp.2009.83. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  645. Shoemaker S, 2003. Identity, Cause, and Mind: Philosophical Essays. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  646. Siddharthan A, Cherbuin N, Eslinger PJ, Kozlowska K, Murphy NA, Lowe L, 2018. WordNet-feelings: a linguistic categorisation of human feelings (arXiv: 1811.02435). arXiv. 10.48550/arXiv.1811.02435. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  647. Siewert C, 2012. On the Phenomenology of Introspection. In: Smithies D, Stoljar D (Eds.), Introspection and Consciousness. Oxford University Press, p. 0. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199744794.003.0005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  648. Siewert CP, 1998. The Significance of Consciousness. Princeton University Press. https://www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt7sjtf. [Google Scholar]
  649. Silva L, 2021. Anger and its desires. Eur. J. Philos 29 (4), 1115–1135. 10.1111/ejop.12628. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  650. Silva L, 2023. Towards an affective quality space. J. Conscious. Stud 30 (7–8), 164–195. 10.53765/20512201.30.7.164. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  651. Silvia PJ, 2005. Cognitive appraisals and interest in visual art: exploring an appraisal theory of aesthetic emotions. Empir. Stud. Arts 23 (2), 119–133. 10.2190/12AV-AH2P-MCEH-289E. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  652. Silvia PJ, 2008. Interest: the curious emotion. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci 17 (1), 57–60. [Google Scholar]
  653. Simon HA, 1967. Motivational and emotional controls of cognition. Psychol. Rev 74 (1), 29–39. 10.1037/h0024127. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  654. Slaby J, Wüschner P, 2014. Emotion and agency. In: Roeser S, Todd C (Eds.), Emotion and Value. Oxford University Press, p. 0. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199686094.003.0014. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  655. Smith A, 2006. Cognitive empathy and emotional empathy in human behavior and evolution. Psychol. Rec 56 (1), 3–21. 10.1007/BF03395534. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  656. Smith R, Parr T, Friston KJ, 2019. Simulating emotions: an active inference model of emotional state inference and emotion concept learning. Front. Psychol 10, 2844. 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.02844. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  657. Smith R, Badcock P, Friston KJ, 2021. Recent advances in the application of predictive coding and active inference models within clinical neuroscience. Psychiatry Clin. Neurosci 75 (1), 3–13. 10.1111/pcn.13138. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  658. Smith R, Varshney LR, Nagayama S, Kazama M, Kitagawa T, Ishikawa Y, 2022. A computational neuroscience perspective on subjective wellbeing within the active inference framework. Article 4 Int. J. Wellbeing 12 (4). 10.5502/ijw.v12i4.2659. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  659. Sober E, 2015. Ockham’s razors. Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
  660. Solomon RC, 1978. Emotions and anthropology: the logic of emotional world views. Inquiry 21 (1–4), 181–199. 10.1080/00201747808601841. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  661. Solomon RC, 1993. The Passions: Emotions and the Meaning of Life. Hackett Publishing. [Google Scholar]
  662. Solomon RC, 2008. The philosophy of emotions. In Handbook of emotions, 3rd ed.,. The Guilford Press, pp. 3–16. [Google Scholar]
  663. Soteriou M, 2013. The Mind’s Construction: The Ontology of Mind and Mental Action. OUP, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  664. Sporns O, Tononi G, Kötter R, 2005. The human connectome: a structural description of the human brain. PLoS Comput. Biol 1 (4), e42. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  665. Stefanova E, Dubljevic O, Herbert C, Fairfield B, Schroeter ML, Stern ER, Urben S, Derntl B, Wiebking C, Brown C, Drach -Zahavy A, Kathrin Loeffler LA, Albrecht F, Palumbo R, Boutros SW, Raber J, Lowe L, 2020. Anticipatory feelings: neural correlates and linguistic markers (this issue). Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 113, 308–324. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.02.015. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  666. Stein NL, Trabasso T, Liwag M, 1993. The representation and organization of emotional experience: unfolding the emotion episode. In Handbook of emotions. The Guilford Press,, pp. 279–300. [Google Scholar]
  667. Stephan A, Walter S, 2020. Situated affectivity. In: Szanto T, Landweer H (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion, 1st ed. Routledge, pp. 299–311. 10.4324/9781315180786-29. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  668. Stephan KE, Manjaly ZM, Mathys CD, Weber LAE, Paliwal S, Gard T, Tittgemeyer M, Fleming SM, Haker H, Seth AK, Petzschner FH, 2016. Allostatic self-efficacy: a metacognitive theory of dyshomeostasis-induced fatigue and depression. Front. Hum. Neurosci 10. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2016.00550. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  669. Sterling P, 2012. Allostasis: a model of predictive regulation. Physiol. Behav 106 (1), 5–15. 10.1016/j.physbeh.2011.06.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  670. Sterling P, 2020. What Is Health?: Allostasis and the Evolution of Human Design. MIT Press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  671. Sterling P, Eyer J, 1988. Allostasis: A new paradigm to explain arousal pathology. In Handbook of life stress, cognition and health. John Wiley & Sons,, pp. 629–649. [Google Scholar]
  672. Sterling P, Laughlin S, 2015. Principles of Neural Design. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  673. Stewart J, 2010. Foundational Issues in Enaction as a Paradigm for Cognitive Science: From the Origin of Life to Consciousness and Writing. In: Stewart J, Gapenne O, Di Paolo EA (Eds.), Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. The MIT Press, p. 0. 10.7551/mitpress/9780262014601.003.0002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  674. Stillings NA, Chase CH, Weisler SE, Feinstein MH, Rissland EL, 1995. Cognitive Science: An Introduction. MIT Press,. [Google Scholar]
  675. Storbeck J, Clore GL, 2007. On the interdependence of cognition and emotion. Cogn. Emot 21 (6), 1212–1237. 10.1080/02699930701438020. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  676. Strack F, Argyle M, Schwarz N (Eds.), 1991. Subjective Well-Being: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, 1st ed. Pergamon Press, Oxford; New York. [Google Scholar]
  677. Strawson G, 2004. Real intentionality. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 3 (3), 287–313. 10.1023/B:PHEN.0000049306.63185.0f. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  678. Strevens M, 2013. No understanding without explanation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. Part A 44 (3), 510–515. [Google Scholar]
  679. Strigo IA, Craig ADB, 2016. Interoception, homeostatic emotions and sympathovagal balance. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 371 (1708), 20160010. 10.1098/rstb.2016.0010. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  680. Sundararajan L, 2015. Understanding Emotion in Chinese Culture: Thinking Through Psychology. Springer. [Google Scholar]
  681. Suppes P, 1969. Models of Data. In: Suppes P (Ed.), Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science: Selected Papers from 1951 to 1969. Springer; Netherlands, pp. 24–35. 10.1007/978-94-017-3173-7_2. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  682. Suri G, Gross JJ, 2022. What is an emotion? A connectionist perspective. Emot. Rev 14 (2), 99–110. 10.1177/17540739221082203. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  683. Sutton RS, Barto AG, 2018. Reinforcement Learning, second edition: an Introduction. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  684. Synofzik M, Vosgerau G, Newen A, 2008. I move, therefore I am: a new theoretical framework to investigate agency and ownership. Conscious. Cogn 17 (2), 411–424. 10.1016/j.concog.2008.03.008. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  685. Synofzik M, Vosgerau G, Voss M, 2013. The experience of agency: an interplay between prediction and postdiction. Front. Psychol 4. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00127. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  686. Szanto T, Landweer H (Eds.), 2020. The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology of Emotion. Routledge. 10.4324/9781315180786. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  687. Sznycer D, Lukaszewski AW, 2019. The emotion–valuation constellation: Multiple emotions are governed by a common grammar of social valuation. Evol. Hum. Behav 40 (4), 395–404. 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2019.05.002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  688. Tabery J, 2014. Beyond Versus: The Struggle to Understand the Interaction of Nature and Nurture. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  689. Tabery J, Preda A, Longino H, 2014. Pluralism, social action and the causal space of human behavior. Metascience 23 (3), 443–459. 10.1007/s11016-014-9903-x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  690. Tangney JP, Stuewig J, Mashek DJ, 2007. Moral emotions and moral behavior. Annu. Rev. Psychol 58, 345–372. 10.1146/annurev.psych.56.091103.070145. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  691. Tappolet C, 2022. Philosophy of emotion: A contemporary introduction. Taylor & Francis. [Google Scholar]
  692. Tenenbaum JB, Kemp C, Griffiths TL, Goodman ND, 2011. How to grow a mind: statistics, structure, and abstraction. Science 331 (6022), 1279–1285. 10.1126/science.1192788. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  693. Teoh YY, Cunningham WA, Hutcherson CA, 2023. Framing subjective emotion reports as dynamic affective decisions. Affect. Sci 10.1007/s42761-023-00197-y. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  694. Teroni F, 2007. Emotions and Formal Objects. Dialectica 61 (3), 395–415. 10.1111/j.1746-8361.2007.01108.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  695. Teroni F, 2017. The phenomenology of memory. In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Memory. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  696. Teroni F, 2023. Evaluative theories in psychology and philosophy of emotion. Mind Lang. 38 (1), 81–97. 10.1111/mila.12374. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  697. Thagard P, 2005. Mind, second edition: Introduction to Cognitive Science. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  698. Thayer RE, 1978. Toward a psychological theory of multidimensional activation (arousal. Motiv. Emot 2 (1), 1–34. 10.1007/BF00992729. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  699. Thelen E, Smith LB, 1994. A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. MIT Press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  700. Thompson E, Lutz A, Cosmelli D, 2005. Neurophenomenology: An Introduction for Neurophilosophers. In Cognition and the brain: The philosophy and neuroscience movement. Cambridge University Press,, pp. 40–97. 10.1017/CBO9780511610608.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  701. Tomasello M, 2020. The moral psychology of obligation. Behav. Brain Sci 43, e56 10.1017/S0140525X19001742. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  702. Tomasello M, 2022. The Evolution of Agency: Behavioral Organization from Lizards to Humans. The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  703. Tooby J, Cosmides L, 1990. On the universality of human nature and the uniqueness of the individual: the role of genetics and adaptation. J. Personal 58 (1), 17–67. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.1990.tb00907.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  704. Trofimova I, 2018. Functionality versus dimensionality in psychological taxonomies, and a puzzle of emotional valence. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci 373 (1744), 20170167. 10.1098/rstb.2017.0167. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  705. Tsakiris M, Preester HD, 2018. The Interoceptive Mind: From Homeostasis to Awareness. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  706. Tschantz A, Barca L, Maisto D, Buckley CL, Seth AK, Pezzulo G, 2022. Simulating homeostatic, allostatic and goal-directed forms of interoceptive control using active inference. Biol. Psychol 169, 108266 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2022.108266. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  707. Tsikandilakis M, Bali P, Yu Z, Karlis A-K, Tong EMW, Milbank A, Mevel P-A, Derrfuss J, Madan C, 2023. “The many faces of sorrow”: An empirical exploration of the psychological plurality of sadness. Curr. Psychol 10.1007/s12144-023-04518-z. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  708. Tulving E, 1987. Life after Kant: Natural purposesmory systems and consciousness. Hum. Neurobiol 6 (2), 67–80. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  709. Tuske J, 2021. The Concept of Emotion in Classical Indian Philosophy. In: Zalta EN (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/concept-emotion-india/. [Google Scholar]
  710. Tye M, 1995. Ten Problems of Consciousness: A Representational Theory of the Phenomenal Mind. MIT Press. 10.7551/mitpress/6712.001.0001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  711. Tye M, 2003. Consciousness and persons: Unity and identity. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, US. [Google Scholar]
  712. Tye M, 2014. Transparency, qualia realism and representationalism. Philos. Stud 170 (1), 39–57. 10.1007/s11098-013-0177-8. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  713. Uexküll J. von, 2013. A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Humans: With A Theory of Meaning. U of Minnesota Press. [Google Scholar]
  714. Van de Cruys S, 2017. Affect. Value Predict. Mind 10.15502/9783958573253. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  715. Van de Cruys S, Bervoets J, Moors A, 2022. Preferences need inferences: Learning, valuation, and curiosity in aesthetic experience. In The Routledge International Handbook of Neuroaesthetics. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  716. Van Dyck E, Burger B, Orlandatou K, 2017a. The Communication of Emotions in Dance. The Routledge Companion to Embodied Music Interaction. 10.4324/9781315621364-14. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  717. Van Fraassen BC, 1980. The scientific image. Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  718. Van Gelder T, 2022. Chapter Eight: Wooden Iron? Husserlian Phenomenology Meets Cognitive Science, in: Naturalizing Phenomenology: Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, Writing Science. Stanford University Press, pp. 245–265. 10.1515/9781503617421-011. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  719. van Hooff JARAM, Aureli F, 1994. Social homeostasis and the regulation of emotion. In Emotions: Essays on emotion theory. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc, pp. 197–217. [Google Scholar]
  720. van Swieten MMH, Manohar SG, Bogacz R, 2021. Eff. Hunger Model-Based Model-Free Decis. -Mak https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:1b99b295-430c-4896-b5e3-29ea9741760f.
  721. Vardi MY, 2012. What is an algorithm. Commun. ACM 55 (3), 5. 10.1145/2093548.2093549. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  722. Varela FG, Maturana HR, Uribe R, 1974. Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. Biosystems 5 (4), 187–196. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  723. Varela FJ, 1979. Principles of Biological Autonomy. North-Holland. [Google Scholar]
  724. Varela FJ, 1996. Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. J. Conscious. Stud 3 (4), 330–349. [Google Scholar]
  725. Varela FJ (1997). The naturalization of phenomenology as the transcendence of nature: Searching for generative mutual constraints. https://philpapers.org/rec/VARTNO-2.
  726. Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E, 2017. The Embodied Mind, revised edition: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  727. Vazard J, 2022. Feeling the unknown: emotions of uncertainty and their valence. Erkenntnis. 10.1007/s10670-022-00583-1. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  728. Vessel E, Starr GG, Rubin N, 2012. The brain on art: Intense aesthetic experience activates the default mode network. Front. Hum. Neurosci 6. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fnhum.2012.00066. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  729. Viinikainen M, Jääskeläinen IP, Alexandrov Y, Balk MH, Autti T, Sams M, 2010. Nonlinear relationship between emotional valence and brain activity: evidence of separate negative and positive valence dimensions. Hum. Brain Mapp 31 (7), 1030–1040. 10.1002/hbm.20915. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  730. Villalobos M, Ward D, 2015. Living Systems: Autonomy, Autopoiesis and Enaction. Philos. Technol 28 (2), 225–239. 10.1007/s13347-014-0154-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  731. Vogl E, Pekrun R, Murayama K, Loderer K, 2020. Surprised–curious–confused: Eepistemic emotions and knowledge exploration. Emotion 20 (4), 625–641. 10.1037/emo0000578. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  732. Walter S, 2014. Situated cognition: a field guide to some open conceptual and ontological issues. Rev. Philos. Psychol 5 (2), 241–263. 10.1007/s13164-013-0167-y. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  733. Ward D, Silverman D, Villalobos M, 2017. Introduction: the varieties of enactivism. Topoi 36 (3), 365–375. 10.1007/s11245-017-9484-6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  734. Watson D, Clark LA, Tellegen A, 1988. Development and validation of brief measures of positive and negative affect: The PANAS scales. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol 54 (6), 1063–1070. 10.1037//0022-3514.54.6.1063. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  735. Weber A, Varela FJ, 2002. Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci 1 (2), 97–125. 10.1023/A:1020368120174. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  736. Weiskrantz L, 1999. Consciousness Lost and Found: A Neuropsychological Exploration, Revised Edition. Oxford University Press, Oxford. [Google Scholar]
  737. Weisman K, Dweck CS, Markman EM, 2017. Rethinking people’s conceptions of mental life. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci 114 (43), 11374–11379. 10.1073/pnas.1704347114. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  738. Wharton T, de Saussure L, 2023. Pragmatics and Emotion. Cambridge University Press. https://uk.bookshop.org/p/books/pragmatics-and-emotion-tim-wharton/7439831. [Google Scholar]
  739. Wharton T, Bonard C, Dukes D, Sander D, Oswald S, 2021. Relevance and emotion. J. Pragmat 181, 259–269. 10.1016/j.pragma.2021.06.001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  740. Whewell W, 1858. Novum Organon Renovatum. J. W. Parker and son. [Google Scholar]
  741. Whissell CM, 1989. Chapter 5—The Dictionary of Affect in Language. In: Plutchik R, Kellerman H (Eds.), The Measurement of Emotions. Academic Press, pp. 113–131. 10.1016/B978-0-12-558704-4.50011-6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  742. Wiener N, 2019. Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine, Reissue of the 1961 second edition. MIT Press,. [Google Scholar]
  743. Wiener N, Hill D, Mitter S, 2019. Cybernetics or Control and Communication in the Animal and the Machine, Reissue of the 1961, second edition (Reprint edition. The MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  744. Wiering M, Van Otterlo M (Eds.), 2012. Reinforcement Learning: State-of-the-Art, Vol. 12. Springer. 10.1007/978-3-642-27645-3. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  745. Wilhelm FH, Grossman P, 2010. Emotions beyond the laboratory: theoretical fundaments, study design, and analytic strategies for advanced ambulatory assessment. Biol. Psychol 84 (3), 552–569. 10.1016/j.biopsycho.2010.01.017. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  746. Williams D, Colling L, 2018. From symbols to icons: the return of resemblance in the cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese 195 (5), 1941–1967. 10.1007/s11229-017-1578-6. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  747. Williams JHG, Huggins CF, Zupan B, Willis M, Van Rheenen TE, Sato W, Palermo R, Ortner C, Krippl M, Kret M, Dickson JM, Li CR, Lowe L, 2020. this issue). A sensorimotor control framework for understanding emotional communication and regulation. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 112, 503–518. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.02.014. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  748. Williams R, 2017. Anger as a basic emotion and its role in personality building and pathological growth: the neuroscientific, developmental and clinical perspectives. Front. Psychol 8, 1950. 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01950. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  749. Williams R, 2020. Culture and Materialism. Verso Books. [Google Scholar]
  750. Wilson TD, 1994. The proper protocol: validity and completeness of verbal reports. Psychol. Sci 5 (5), 249–252. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.1994.tb00621.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  751. Winkielman P, Berridge KC, 2004. Unconscious Emotion. Curr. Dir. Psychol. Sci 13 (3), 120–123. 10.1111/j.0963-7214.2004.00288.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  752. Wittgenstein L, 1953. Philosophical investigations. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Macmillan, Oxford, England. [Google Scholar]
  753. Wittgenstein L, 1958. The Blue and Brown Books: Preliminary Studies for the “Philosophical Investigations”. Harper & Row, pp. 12–13. [Google Scholar]
  754. Wollheim R, 1999. On the Emotions, 1st ed. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT. [Google Scholar]
  755. Wolpert DM, Ghahramani Z, Jordan MI, 1995. An Internal Model for Sensorimotor Integration. Science 269 (5232), 1880–1882. 10.1126/science.7569931. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  756. Woodward J, 2014. A functional account of causation; or, a defense of the legitimacy of causal thinking by reference to the only standard that matters—Usefulness (as opposed to metaphysics or agreement with intuitive judgment). Philos. Sci 81 (5), 691–713. [Google Scholar]
  757. Wray KB, 2002. The epistemic significance of collaborative research. Philos. Sci 69 (1), 150–168. 10.1086/338946. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  758. Yik M, 2010. How unique is Chinese emotion? In: Bond MH (Ed.), Oxford Handbook of Chinese Psychology. Oxford University Press, p. 0. 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199541850.013.0015. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  759. Yik M, Mues C, Sze INL, Kuppens P, Tuerlinckx F, De Roover K, Kwok FHC, Schwartz SH, Abu-Hilal M, Adebayo DF, Aguilar P, Al-Bahrani M, Anderson MH, Andrade L, Bratko D, Bushina E, Choi JW, Cieciuch J, Dru V, Russell JA, 2023. On the relationship between valence and arousal in samples across the globe. Emot. (Wash., D. C.) 23 (2), 332–344. 10.1037/emo0001095. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  760. Zahavi D, Kriegel U, 2015. For-Me-Ness: What It Is and What It Is Not. In Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology. Routledge. [Google Scholar]
  761. Zajonc RB, Pietromonaco P, Bargh J, 1982. Independence and Interaction of Affect and Cognition. In. Affect and Cognition. Psychology Press. [Google Scholar]
  762. Zajonc RB, Pietromonaco P, Bargh J, 2014. Independence and interaction of affect and cognition. In Affect and cognition. Psychology Press, pp. 211–227. [Google Scholar]
  763. Zeelenberg M, van Dijk WW, Manstead ASR, van der Pligt J, 2000. On bad decisions and disconfirmed expectancies: the psychology of regret and disappointment. Cogn. Emot 14 (4), 521–541. 10.1080/026999300402781. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  764. Zhou P, Critchley H, Garfinkel S, Gao Y, 2021. The conceptualization of emotions across cultures: a model based on interoceptive neuroscience. Neurosci. Biobehav. Rev 125, 314–327. 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2021.02.023. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  765. Zoltowski AR, Failla MD, Cascio CJ, 2022. Social touch and allostasis. Curr. Opin. Behav. Sci 43, 69–74. 10.1016/j.cobeha.2021.08.005. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  766. Zuckerman M, 1971. Physiological measures of sexual arousal in the human. Psychol. Bull 75 (5), 297–329. 10.1037/h0030923. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Associated Data

This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

Data Availability Statement

No data was used for the research described in the article.

RESOURCES