That antenatal experience could have dire consequences is ancient folklore. In 1921 Stockard gave scientific form to the idea in the “critical period” hypothesis: failure of a developing organism to progress from one stage of development to the next within preset time limits could lead to a permanent deficit. Since then several studies have addressed related hypotheses, though mostly in animals. From the 1950s human observational studies reported effects in later life of various exposures—for example, to radiation,1–3 famine,4 and viruses.5 In a large number of more recent publications, Barker has elaborated the idea that fetal experience might “programme” cardiovascular health states in adult life. He has been ingenious in seeking out birth records of cohorts of a half century ago and more. Studies using such sources face some irreparable difficulties—for instance, incomplete samples and attrition on follow up with selective bias, inadequate as well as missing records, and the absence of data crucial for controlled analysis.
Some of these problems are being better resolved in later datasets assembled for long continued longitudinal studies. An analysis from one such birth cohort study in New Zealand appears in this week’s issue.6 This analysis also addresses a second—entirely reparable—problem previously discussed by one of us.7 This is the observation that Barker’s studies, fertile as they have been in stimulating life course studies, do not meet Galileo’s crucial scientific requirement that a hypothesis should be subjected to an ordeal. In other words, science requires the framing of refutable questions.
The authors of this week’s study have followed the editorial injunction and pursued some of the ordeals suggested. They report on systolic blood pressure at the ages of 9 and 18 in a cohort followed from birth. Losses at follow up were remarkably few, with missing data at a minimum and enough variables to control for confounding. For most important variables—exposures, outcomes, and covariates—standard measures were used. The hypothesis drawn from Barker is that undernutrition, manifest in slow growth and consequent low birth weight, programmes the fetus for high blood pressure in later life. The authors’ refutable formulation is that low birth weight due to known and clearly specified antecedents—namely, twinning, maternal smoking, and maternal size—should result in raised systolic blood pressure.
The results for twinning and maternal height, the authors conclude, are in the main contrary to the hypothesis: the low birth weights of twins were associated with lower average systolic blood pressure and, conversely, the higher birth weights accompanying mother’s height with higher pressure. Maternal smoking was associated with lower birth weight—an effect consistent with the hypothesis, but only on the assumption that the mechanism is indeed nutritional.
The authors rely on path analysis to elaborate these results. Path analysis is a clever way to organise causal thinking that is seldom seen in the medical literature. Invented in the 1920s by Sewall Wright,8 a founder of population genetics, it was little used until in the 1960s it was revived in population genetics and became a vogue in the social sciences. To see how it works, take the underlying statistical method of multiple linear regression. Between a presumed antecedent variable x and a presumed outcome variable y one can obtain the result that a unit of x “accounts” for a given amount of change in y. When multiple variables serve as antecedents, the multiple linear regression method apportions the contributions of each of the many x’s to the variance in the outcome y. In essence, path analysis assembles the variables usually seen in an unstructured form in multiple regression analysis into a structure of presumed causal paths between the variables. The variables thus form a set of presumed causal sequences, and are laid out in a path diagram for clarity.
Given such a presupposed causal model, path analysis allows one to estimate the relative strengths of relations between the variables in the model. This it does in two ways. One estimate expresses the variance of the key outcomes as a sum of all the components that are the presumed causal antecedents of those outcomes. A second estimate “decomposes” the correlations between variables—that is, distributes them—in terms of the model among their causal antecedents.
Each connection between the variables is assigned a path coefficient, (a value expressing how many standard deviation units the variables at the head of an arrow change in association with a one standard deviation change in the variable at the tail, other causes held fixed). The path coefficient corresponding to a multilink causal pathway between two variables is obtained by multiplying path coefficients along the links, and the overall correlation between two variables is the sum of the path coefficients over all such causal pathways, direct and indirect.9
The method has the advantage of prior commitment to hypotheses about the appropriate causal ordering of all the variables included. It follows that the presumed links between variables are thereby tested and can sometimes be refuted. If not refuted, they stand as compatible with the hypotheses, although not proved by such a result standing alone. In short, path analysis does not prove the validity of a causal model. Many such models can be fitted to the same data, and each will produce an associated path analysis. Path analysis quantifies, and thereby illuminates, sequences among variables which, for the purposes of the model, the analyst must already assume do in fact hold.
The caveat about proof is important because the language of the method invokes causality in speaking of “causal” paths and the like. This is especially the case in analyses using the simultaneously collected cross sectional data of surveys when, between many variables linked in the path model, even time order remains unascertainable and hypothetical. In the study by Williams et al,6 however, the method is given greater cogency by the longitudinal design. Hence the time order of many path sequences is known and not assumed, with considerable advantage for causal inference.
In Williams et al’spaper a modest negative correlation between birth weight and systolic blood pressure is compatible, though weakly, with the fetal programming hypothesis.6 The path diagram shows this correlation to be composed of a larger, direct negative effect between these two variables, together with two positive indirect effects (through child’s height and body mass index), and several joint antecedent causes of both birth weight and systolic pressure with positive contributions (in particular, twinning, maternal height, and maternal smoking).
The causal model in the diagram is complex. If correct, it suggests that the fetal origins hypothesis, if it is indeed represented by the direct, inverse effect of birth weight that lowers blood pressure, competes with other causal pathways with important, indirect, countervailing influences that raise blood pressure. In particular, if the low birth weights of twins are taken to be the result of impaired fetal nutrition, as the Barker formulation has generally done, the model falls on the side of refutation.
Papers p 897
References
- 1.Stewart A, Webb J, Hewitt DA. A survey of childhood malignancies. BMJ. 1958;i:1445–1508. doi: 10.1136/bmj.1.5086.1495. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.MacMahon B. Prenatal X ray exposure and childhood cancer. J Natl Cancer Inst. 1962;28:1173–1191. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Otake M, Schull J. In utero exposure to A-bomb radiation: A reassessment. Br J Radiol. 1984;57:409–414. doi: 10.1259/0007-1285-57-677-409. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Stein Z, Susser M, Saenger G, Marolla F. New York: Oxford University Press; 1975. Famine and human development: the Dutch hunger winter of 1944-45. [Google Scholar]
- 5.Chess S, Korn SJ, Frenandez PB. New York: Brunner-Mazel; 1971. Psychiatric disorders of children with congenital rubella. [Google Scholar]
- 6.Williams S, Poulton R. Twins and maternal smoking: ordeals for the fetal origins hypothesis? A cohort study. BMJ. 1999;318:897–900. doi: 10.1136/bmj.318.7188.897. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Paneth N, Susser M. Early origin of coronary artery disease. BMJ. 1995;310:411–412. doi: 10.1136/bmj.310.6977.411. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Wright S. The application of path analysis to etiology. In: Morton NE, Chung CS, editors. Genetic epidemiology. New York: Academic Press; 1978. pp. 13–54. [Google Scholar]
- 9.Li CC. Pacific Grove: CA Boxwood Press; 1975. Path analysis: a primer. [Google Scholar]