Abstract
A major goal in evolutionary biology is to elucidate common principles that drive human and other animal societies to adopt either a warlike or peaceful nature. One proposed explanation for the variation in aggression between human societies is the democratic peace hypothesis. According to this theory, autocracies are more warlike than democracies because autocratic leaders can pursue fights for private gain. However, autocratic and democratic decision-making processes are not unique to humans and are widely observed across a diverse range of non-human animal societies. We use evolutionary game theory to evaluate whether the logic of democratic peace may apply across taxa; specifically adapting the classic Hawk-Dove model to consider conflict decisions made by groups rather than individuals. We find support for the democratic peace hypothesis without mechanisms involving complex human institutions and discuss how these findings might be relevant to non-human animal societies. We suggest that the degree to which collective decisions are shared may explain variation in the intensity of intergroup conflict in nature.
Subject terms: Evolutionary theory, Behavioural ecology, Computational models, Dynamical systems
The democratic peace hypothesis suggests that autocracies are more warlike than democracies. Here, the authors use evolutionary game theory to test this hypothesis across taxa, finding that democratic peace can emerge without the need for complex human institutions.
Introduction
The tendency to organise into groups and engage in collective violence against other groups is a striking and destructive feature of human behaviour1–3. Such intergroup conflicts have persisted for many tens or hundreds of thousands of years, and continue take a tremendous toll on human life4–7. Therefore, understanding the root causes of intergroup conflict is an issue of significant and urgent importance. Until recently, intergroup conflict was seen as a particularly human phenomenon, predicated on uniquely human cultural traits2,3,8,9. Now, however, our increasing understanding of intergroup conflict in other animals has helped to illuminate the evolutionary forces that may have shaped this phenomenon10,11. Across taxa there is great variation in the severity and frequency of intergroup conflict12–14, which provides an opportunity to identify shared traits which drive societies towards war or peace.
In human societies, a dominant explanation for variation in interstate conflict is the democratic peace hypothesis, which proposes that democracies are less prone to initiating interstate conflicts than autocracies because shared decision-making acts as a restraint on warmongering (or exploitative) leaders8,13,15–20. This hypothesis has received widespread empirical support21–24. For example, a recent analysis of patterns of conflict among 186 countries over a 42-year period found the statistical link between democracy and peace to be five times stronger than that between smoking and lung cancer24. Until now it has been assumed that democratic peace relies on uniquely human institutions25–27. However, in principle the logic of democratic peace could apply to intergroup conflict among any biological groups that exhibit shared or collective decision making, suggesting that the hypothesis may have much broader scope across other taxa.
Here, we use evolutionary game theory to explore the whether the logic of democratic peace can be used to explain variation in intergroup conflict in animal societies, in the absence of uniquely human institutions. A large body of literature now demonstrates that collective movement decisions in animal societies can vary on a continuum from being unshared (i.e., dictated by leaders28–34;) or shared across the group (i.e., democratic34–41). These democratic decisions are observed when the majority can influence group movements more than any one individual or subset of individuals. Shared and unshared collective movement decisions could translate into collective decisions to initiate conflict too. For example, if a leader was motivated to fight another group, it could lead its group in a hostile move towards that rival’s territory. Equally, in a shared decision-making context, if the majority of a group prefer to avoid a fight, they may collectively form a consensus to retreat and evade the rival. Both intergroup conflict and collective movement decisions are observable across many taxa, from bacteria42,43 to primates33,35,44, and therefore collectively deciding whether to fight could be, in theory, achievable by a wide range of social organisms.
Results and discussion
Model Overview
Given that many social organisms have the necessary prerequisites for democratic peace, we explore whether evolution would favour such a relationship in an evolutionary game theoretical model (based upon the Hawk Dove game45) in which collectives rather than pairs compete over resources. In an infinite population, groups of size N engage in random pairwise encounters, in which each group collectively decides to play either a peaceful (Dove) or aggressive (Hawk) strategy. Upon meeting, two groups playing a Dove strategy will share a resource, V, equally. If a Dove playing group meets a Hawk playing group it will concede the resource to the Hawk (Hawk = V, Dove = 0). However, the disadvantage to playing Hawk is that when two Hawk playing groups meet, they will fight, resulting in costly losses, C, for one group (and C > V), so playing Dove can be advantageous. Within each group, individuals are divided into two distinct classes: a proportion ε (chosen at random) are assigned the role of leader, and the remaining proportion 1-ε are assigned the role of follower. The social structure of each group within the population (i.e., the proportion of leaders vs followers) is the same and is defined at the outset of the model. Leaders and followers differ in i) their influence on the group’s collective decision, and ii) in the individual costs and benefits that they obtain as a result intergroup interactions, as described in the following two sections. See Table 1 for a summary of all model parameters.
Table 1.
Parameter | Description |
---|---|
Ω | Shared decision parameter – the degree to which collective decisions are shared from 0 = complete control by leaders to 1 = equal share of decisions by leaders and followers |
ε | Proportion of leaders in each group. Proportion of followers = 1– ε |
N | Number of individuals in each group. Note that N is assumed to be sufficiently large such that Nε is an integer. |
V | The value of the contested resource |
C | The total cost of losing a conflict |
dv | Distribution of V across the classes. Higher values indicate leaders monopolising the resources (Fig. S1) |
dc | Distribution of C across the classes. Higher values benefit leaders, in that followers pay the majority of the costs (Fig. S1) |
All of the above are defined and fixed at the outset of the model.
Collective decisions
An individual’s strategy specifies its probability PL of playing Hawk as a leader and its probability PF of playing Hawk as a follower (so that it plays Dove with probability as a leader or as a follower). These individual choices are combined into a single collective decision, whereby the entire group either plays Hawk, with probability P, given in Eq. 1, or Dove, with probability . However, all individuals do not necessarily exert equal influence on this outcome. The leaders’ combined influence on P is proportional to PLε, while the followers’ combined influence is proportional to , where 0 ≤ Ω ≤ 1. and correspond to the mean leader and follower strategy within each group respectively. When , follower strategies are weighted by zero, so only the leaders have influence, and the decision-making structure can be described as an unshared consensus decision46. In contrast, when , any given follower and any given leader both have an equal share of influence, and the decision-making structure can be described as a shared consensus decision46. Note, our model assumes that once a collective decision is made, the whole group abides by the decision. Thus, our model is applicable to societies where the possible benefits of defection are outweighed by the costs of punishment47,48, isolation from the group49,50, or delays in decision-making51.
1 |
Distribution of costs and benefits
Leaders and followers are further differentiated by receiving different shares of the total collective costs, C, and benefits, V, that their group obtains, governed by the parameters dc and dv (where 0 ≤ dc ≤ 1 and 0 ≤ dv ≤ 1; see Table 2 below). All groups in the population are parameterised with the same sharing rules, meaning they use the same values of dc and dv. When dc = 0.5, the individual costs paid by leaders, CL, and followers, CF, are equal. But when dc > 0.5, leaders receive an advantage by avoiding some of the costs of fighting incurred by followers (CL < CF) (Supplementary Fig. 1). This could be because leaders are larger, tougher, better armoured, or able to take up safer positions during the fight such as at the back of the group7,13,20. Likewise, when dv > 0.5 leaders’ share of the benefit VL, is greater than that of the groups’ followers, VF. This represents cases where leaders are socially dominant to followers and able to displace them from contested resources such as food or mates that obtained as a reward after victory33,34,52,53. We also consider cases where followers pay lower costs, dc < 0.5, or gain more reward, dv < 0.5, following the literature suggesting that there can be greater costs associated with leadership54–56. We can use the values of CL, CF, VL and VF to calculate the probability of hawk-playing that is evolutionarily stable when only one class of individual, either leaders or followers, control group behaviour. Under leader control, this evolutionary stable strategy is equal to VL/CL (hereafter ṼL), whereas for followers it is equal to VF/CF (hereafter ṼF).
Table 2.
Definition | Equation |
---|---|
Cost paid by leader | |
Cost paid by follower | |
Reward gained by leader | |
Reward gained by follower |
The evolution of democratic peace (or democratic war)
We find that when the leaders are advantaged—meaning that ṼL > ṼF—they exhibit a higher probability of Hawk playing than the followers, who play an overall more peaceful strategy (Fig. 1; Supplementary Fig. 2). In these scenarios, our model supports the core prediction of the democratic peace hypothesis, in that increasing the follower’s share of the collective decision, Ω, results in a decrease in the aggressive Hawk-playing strategy of the population P.
The assumption that the leaders generally benefit more than the followers is well supported in nature, because leadership is often associated with older, dominant, or otherwise privileged individuals who can benefit from priority of access to resources, including those that are gained from fighting33,34. Similarly, leaders may be able to lessen their individual costs of fighting relative to followers on account of being larger, stronger, or being able to occupy safer positions during the fight7,13,20. However, if these assumptions are not met and leadership is instead costly and disadvantageous relative to being a follower53,54,56,57, then increasing shared decision-making can instead increase the hawkishness of the population in a phenomenon we describe as “democratic war” (Supplementary Fig. 3). A key insight from our model is that we find that democratic peace is only upheld when leaders are advantaged relative to followers, otherwise democracy has the opposite effect in increasing aggression in intergroup interactions.
To better understand whether democratic peace or war is more likely in a given biological system, it is useful to quantify the inter-individual distribution of the costs and benefits (represented by the dc and dv parameters). For example, one could measure whether proxies for the costs of fighting, such as mortalities or injuries, are distributed evenly among group members or are biased either towards or against individuals with more decision-making responsibility. Similarly, empiricists could measure how resources, such as food or reproductive opportunities, are shared after the conflict to approximate the division rules used to determine how the benefits of fighting are shared. An example of estimating these parameters in practice comes from banded mongooses, where researchers observed that females, who often act as leaders, are disproportionately less likely to die from intergroup fighting (high dc) and are also more likely to gain from mating opportunities (high dv)13. Given the females have both greater decision-making influence and are advantaged (Supplementary Fig. 2), the high levels of violent conflict observed in this system are consistent with the predictions from our model (and that of ref. 13).
Loudest voice prevails
A key finding from our model is that when followers have sufficient influence, they can control the collective decision completely in their favour, not because each follower has more influence than each leader, but because followers are in the majority. When ε < 0.5 (as in Fig. 1) the combined influence of followers can outweigh the leaders’ strategy. Intuitively, the control of leaders can be overturned by smaller values of follower influence Ω when the proportion of leaders ε is small, but require much larger values of shared decision-making parameter Ω, or may not be overturned at all, when the proportion of leaders ε is large (Fig. 2; also see Supplementary Fig. 4 for model outcomes over a broader parameter space).
At both low and high levels of shared decision-making (Ω) there is a conspicuous absence of compromise, and outcomes are in favour of either leader’s control or follower’s control respectively. This result emerges because of a “loudest voice prevails” dynamic58,59, in which both classes adopt obligate Hawk or Dove playing across much of the parameter space, yet one class is unable to prevent the other from achieving control. The loudest voice prevails outcome is similar to the predicted resolution in other evolutionary conflicts. In models of genomic imprinting, paternal and maternal genes may evolve all-or-nothing expression to either be active or completely silenced58,59. In eusocial Hymenoptera, colonies are observed to produce a majority of males or females60, which has the effect of driving the population ratio of males to females towards their optima61. Further parallels can be found in humans, where political party members are known to elect leaders with more extreme views than themselves to negotiate with rivals because extreme views act as better negotiation anchors and more often succeed in passing moderate legislation that is closer to the party member’s original preference62.
The success of extreme strategies in anchoring and controlling the collective decision in our model is determined by the difference between the extreme strategy (P = 1 for Hawk or P = 0 for Dove) and the stable outcome under control of a given class (ṼL or ṼF). When this difference is low – i.e., the extreme strategy closely resembles the stable outcome for a class – then that player class will be less successful in controlling the decision outcome in their favour. For example, if a class’ stable probability of Hawk playing was equal to 0.2, an extreme strategy for Dove (PL or PF = 0) would only have limited impact, whereas an extreme strategy for Hawk (PL or PF = 1) would be more effective at anchoring and controlling the collective decision. Importantly, in our model strategies are bounded between 1 and 0, as a group cannot play Hawk or Dove more than 100% of the time. This represents an important distinction between models of collective decision-making with bounded actions (as here) to models with continuous actions (e.g., decisions over the time to depart a foraging patch – as in ref. 63).
Interpretation for empirical systems
In our model, the empirical interpretation of the shared decision-making parameter Ω is intentionally left unspecified. This is because we imagine different possible ways in which Ω might vary both within, and between, species. Firstly, we propose that Ω could be a species-specific parameter, in that it describes the distribution of decision-making influence within a given animal society. In line with this, many recent studies and comparative analyses have described the variation in decision-making between different taxa as being more shared34–41, or unshared28–34, which would correspond to higher and lower values of Ω respectively. For example, olive baboons (Papio anubis) make shared consensus decisions when deciding where to travel as a group (Ω ≈ 1)35, whereas bottlenose dolphins (Tursiops sp.) make unshared consensus decisions where males have disproportionate influence relative to the rest of the group (Ω < 1)29. It is important to note that much of the research in collective decision-making in animals has thus far focused on group movement and foraging decisions31,33,36,37,39,64. It is largely unknown to what extent the same decision-making rules, and therefore Ω values, are generalisable across different contexts (but see ref. 34). For example, meerkats (Suricata suricatta) initially share the decision of when to stop foraging39, but dominant females then dictate the decision of which burrow they go home to32. Leadership dynamics in chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) are similarly fluid with different individuals wielding influence depending on the context of group movement, within-group conflict resolution or between group aggression65–67. As our model is focused on intergroup conflict, it is important that future work considers the distribution of decision-making (Ω) within an intergroup conflict context, which may not be the same as during other contexts (e.g., group foraging34,68).
Secondly, we consider the possibility that Ω might vary within social groups of the same species, based on the group’s unique composition of individuals. Leadership is often governed by the phenotypes of individuals, such as their age30,31,34,44,64, sex31,44,64,68–71, or personality72–74, and therefore the distribution of decision-making (Ω) within a social group may vary over time with changes to group composition. For example, in a chimpanzee troop, their propensity to engage in collective hunts declined after the death of an “impact hunter”75,76, which may reflect resultant changes to the decision-making dynamics within the group. Although group hunting is different to intergroup conflict, there are similarities between the two behaviours77,78, and this example demonstrates how demographic changes can influence collective decision-making and ultimately group-level behaviours. Demographic changes might have the most impact on the decision-making parameter (Ω) when they involve the presence or absence of key individuals in the group77. Such key individuals are known to catalyse intergroup violence, and the concentration of leadership towards key individuals may restrict the influence that others have and result in more unshared decisions (low Ω)77.
Model assumptions
Our model relies on a number of simplifying assumptions. A first assumption is that the way costs and benefits are divided among individual group members is the same for every group in the population. In nature, however, animal groups will vary widely in size and composition, which may impact their collective decision-making in ways described above. More dominant leaders, for instance, may be better able to monopolise resources within their group 33,34. This will likely result in intergroup variation in the parameters dv and dc, which determine the bias in the division of the costs and benefits of fighting. Such heterogeneity among groups would alter our results, potentially favouring a more complex strategy in which both leaders and followers adjust their level of aggression in response to the social structure and composition of their current group (and potentially to the structure of an opposing group as well, if they are able to assess this). A second assumption is that the shared decision-making parameter (Ω) and the proportion of leaders in each group (ε) are fixed and defined at the outset of the model. An alternative approach could be to allow these parameters to co-evolve with aggression as an emergent property of the group. For example, an extended model might allow individuals in a group to pay personal costs in return for more influence over the group’s collective strategy. Such a model could represent animal societies in which individuals engage in costly within-group competition to earn promotion to positions of leadership and influence34. However, note that there are arguments against assuming that there is an intrinsic link between dominance and leadership33,35. In contrast, animal societies in which leadership is determined by traits such as sex31,44,64,68–71 or age30,31,34,44,64 and in which groups exhibit a stable demography, may better be represented by our current model in which social and decision-making structures are pre-defined at the outset.
We have shown that the sharing or decentralisation of collective decision-making can promote more peaceful intergroup interactions without the presence or requirement for complex human institutions. This is not to say that institutions cannot or do not play a crucial role in human societies, but they are not a prerequisite for democratic peace to emerge in the biological systems we have modelled. Democratic peace can emerge from mechanisms of collective decision making between individuals with varying levels of influence and incentives, which are intrinsic properties of groups of humans and many other social organisms, from microbes to primates.
Methods
Derivation of the model solution
We consider an infinite population whose members engage in collective, agonistic encounters. In each such encounter, two groups of size N are assembled at random from the population. Within each group, a fraction ϵ of the individuals, chosen at random, are assigned the role of leader, while the remaining fraction 1 − ϵ are assigned the role of follower (we assume that ϵN is an integer). Each individual then chooses for its group to play Hawk or Dove, and these individual decisions are combined into a single collective choice for each group, as described in the main text (with the decisions of followers being weighted by a factor Ω (≤ 1) relative to those of leaders).
A strategy in this context, denoted (PL, PF), specifies an individual’s probability of choosing Hawk as a leader and as a follower. We model the evolution of this strategy using an adaptive dynamic approach, based on the assumption that the population is typically monomorphic, but that evolution proceeds through the successive substitution of mutations of small effect, each of which sweeps to fixation after successfully invading.
Consider a rare mutant type that adopts the strategy (, ), in an otherwise monomorphic population that adopts the strategy (PL, PF). Given our assumptions about the process of collective decision making (described above in the main text), the probability that a group of typical individuals in this population collectively choose to play Hawk is given by:
while the probability that a group containing a focal mutant individual plays Hawk is given by
2 |
if the focal individual is chosen as a leader, and
3 |
if it is chosen as a follower.
Making use of the above expressions, we can write the expected payoff to an individual of the mutant type, denoted as
4 |
where VL and CL denote the individual benefits or costs obtained by a leader if its group wins or loses an encounter (as defined in the main text), and VF and CF are the corresponding values for a follower. In the above expression, the first term, weighted by , deals with the case in which the focal mutant is assigned the role of leader, and the second term, weighted by (1- ), the case in which the focal mutant is assigned the role of follower. In the former case, the probability that the focal group collectively plays Hawk is QL, while the probability that the opposing group (composed of typical individuals) collectively plays Hawk is P. Thus with probability QLP there is an escalated fight in which each group obtains an expected collective payoff of (V - C)/2, and the focal mutant leader an expected individual payoff of (VL – CL)/2; with probability QL(1-P) the focal group plays collectively plays Hawk and claims the contested resource from the opposing group which collectively plays Dove, yielding a payoff of VL for the focal mutant leader; with probability (1-QL)P the focal group plays Dove against the opposing group’s Hawk and concedes the contested resource, so that the focal mutant gains a payoff of 0; lastly, with probability (1-QL) (1-P) both groups play Dove and share the resource, with a payoff of VL/2 for the focal mutant. The case in which the focal mutant is assigned the role of follower can be analysed in a similar way.
We assume a simple adaptive dynamic under which the rate of evolutionary change in either component of the population strategy (PL, PF) is proportional the partial derivative of mutant fitness with respect to that component where these derivatives are evaluated at , so that when and .
5 |
and
6 |
Hence , when , and when , while when , and when .
Recalling the definitions and from the main text, we see that if then the nullclines for PL and PF coincide, and the model yields a continuum of possible equilibria at which (as this same collective probability of playing Hawk can be achieved through many different combinations of leader and follower aggression – see salmon coloured outcomes in Fig. S4). Otherwise, the null-clines do not intersect, so that no interior equilibrium is possible at which and . Instead, the model yields a unique stable equilibrium at which either PL or PF or both take an extreme value of 0 or 1 (see Supplementary Fig. 5 for an illustration of these outcomes), as detailed below:
If , so that leaders are advantaged, then:
7 |
Such that:
8 |
Conversely, if , so that followers are advantaged, then:
9 |
Such that:
10 |
We also provide the same model presented as a simulation (Supplementary Methods, Supplementary Fig. 6) that produces identical results as those presented in the manuscript using the analytical approach.
Reporting summary
Further information on research design is available in the Nature Portfolio Reporting Summary linked to this article.
Supplementary information
Acknowledgements
Work was funded by a NERC standard grant awarded to M.A.C., D.P.C., F.J.T., D.W.F., and R.A.J. entitled Leaders of war: the evolution of collective decision-making in the face of intergroup conflict. Grant Reference NE/S009914/1. F.J.T. is additionally funded by a NERC Independent Research Fellowship NE/V014471/1. We would like to thank the University of Exeter’s Behavioural Discussion Group and Mike Cant’s Socialis Lab for insightful discussions. We would also like to thank Liz Greenyer for useful discussion and Hattie Lavender for proof-reading.
Author contributions
Conceptualisation by K.L.H. and D.W.E.S. with support from M.A.C. Writing the manuscript: K.L.H. and D.W.E.S., with input from M.P., D.P.C., D.W.F., P.A.G., F.J.T., M.A.C., and R.A.J. Coding and data analysis: D.W.E.S. and K.L.H., with input from M.P., M.A.C., and R.A.J.
Peer review
Peer review information
Nature Communications thanks Cameron Hall and the other, anonymous, reviewer(s) for their contribution to the peer review of this work. A peer review file is available.
Data availability
Scripts, including those used to produce the model and generate the data used in this manuscript, are all publicly available to download from https://github.com/sankeydan/demoPeace2/.
Code availability
Scripts, including those used to produce the model and generate the data used in this manuscript, are all publicly available to download from https://github.com/sankeydan/demoPeace2/.
Competing interests
The authors declare no competing interests.
Footnotes
Publisher’s note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Contributor Information
K. L. Hunt, Email: klh238@exeter.ac.uk
D. W. E. Sankey, Email: Dan.Sankey@newcastle.ac.uk
Supplementary information
The online version contains supplementary material available at 10.1038/s41467-024-50621-5.
References
- 1.Choi, J.-K. & Bowles, S. The coevolution of parochial altruism and war. Science318, 636–640 (2007). 10.1126/science.1144237 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Gat, A. War in Human Civilisation. (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2008).
- 3.Keeley, L. H. War Before Civilization: The Myth of the Peaceful Savage. (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1996).
- 4.Rummel, R. J. Death by Government. (Transaction Publishers, 1997).
- 5.Allen, M. W., Bettinger, R. L., Codding, B. F., Jones, T. L. & Schwitalla, A. W. Resource scarcity drives lethal aggression among prehistoric hunter-gatherers in central California. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci.113, 12120–12125 (2016). 10.1073/pnas.1607996113 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Lahr, M. M. et al. Inter-group violence among early Holocene hunter-gatherers of West Turkana, Kenya. Nature529, 394–398 (2016). 10.1038/nature16477 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Buzzell, E. & Preston, S. H. Mortality of American troops in the Iraq war. Popul. Dev. Rev.33, 555–566 (2007). 10.1111/j.1728-4457.2007.00185.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Fearon, J. D. Rationalist explanations for war. Int. Organ.49, 379–414 (1995). 10.1017/S0020818300033324 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Hames, R. Cultural and reproductive success and the causes of war: a Yanomamö perspective. Evol. Hum. Behav.41, 183–187 (2020). 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2020.02.008 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Durrant, R. Collective violence: an evolutionary perspective. Aggress. Violent Behav.16, 428–436 (2011). 10.1016/j.avb.2011.04.014 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Glowacki, L., Wilson, M. L. & Wrangham, R. W. The evolutionary anthropology of war. J. Econ. Behav. Organ178, 963–982 (2020). 10.1016/j.jebo.2017.09.014 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Goncalves, I. B., Morris-Drake, A., Kennedy, P. & Radford, A. N. Fitness consequences of outgroup conflict. Elife11, e74550 (2022). 10.7554/eLife.74550 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Johnstone, R. A., Cant, M. A., Cram, D. & Thompson, F. J. Exploitative leaders incite intergroup warfare in a social mammal. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci.117, 29759–29766 (2020). 10.1073/pnas.2003745117 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Wrangham, R. W., Wilson, M. L. & Muller, M. N. Comparative rates of violence in chimpanzees and humans. Primates47, 14–26 (2006). 10.1007/s10329-005-0140-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Kant, I. To perpetual peace: a philosophical sketch (ed T. Humphrey) (Hackett, 2003).
- 16.Paine, T. Rights of Man, Common Sense, and Other Political Writings. (Oxford University Press, 2008).
- 17.Tocqueville, A. Democracy in America: And Two Essays on America. (Penguin UK, 2003).
- 18.Mello, P. A. Democratic peace theory from Kant’s ‘Perpetual Peace’ to democratic peace theoretical explanations for the democratic peace (The SAGE Encyclopedia of War: Social Science Perspective, 2014).
- 19.Ray, J. L. Democracy and international conflict: an evaluation of the democratic peace proposition (University of South Carolina Press, 1995).
- 20.Sankey, D. W. E. et al. Leaders of war: modelling the evolution of conflict among heterogeneous groups. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B377, 20210140 (2022). 10.1098/rstb.2021.0140 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Rummel, R. J. Democracies are less warlike than other regimes. Eur. J. Int. Relat.1, 457–479 (1995). 10.1177/1354066195001004003 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Benoit, K. Democracies really are more pacific (in general) reexamining regime type and war involvement. J. Confl. Resolut.40, 636–657 (1996). 10.1177/0022002796040004006 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Dafoe, A., Oneal, J. R. & Russett, B. The democratic peace: weighing the evidence and cautious inference. Int. Stud. Q.57, 201–214 (2013). 10.1111/isqu.12055 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Imai, K. & Lo, J. Robustness of empirical evidence for the democratic peace: a nonparametric sensitivity analysis. Int. Organ.75, 901–919 (2021). 10.1017/S0020818321000126 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Russett, B. M. & Oneal, J. R. Triangulating Peace: Democracy, Interdependence, and International Organizations. (WW Norton & Company Incorporated, 2001).
- 26.Gartzke, E. The capitalist peace. Am. J. Pol. Sci.51, 166–191 (2007). 10.1111/j.1540-5907.2007.00244.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Simpson, S. Making liberal use of Kant? Democratic peace theory and perpetual peace. Int. Relat.33, 109–128 (2019). 10.1177/0047117818811463 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Smith, J. E. et al. Collective movements, leadership and consensus costs at reunions in spotted hyaenas. Anim. Behav.105, 187–200 (2015). 10.1016/j.anbehav.2015.04.023 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Lusseau, D. & Conradt, L. The emergence of unshared consensus decisions in bottlenose dolphins. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol.63, 1067–1077 (2009). 10.1007/s00265-009-0740-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 30.McComb, K. et al. Leadership in elephants: the adaptive value of age. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B: Biol. Sci.278, 3270–3276 (2011). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Brent, L. J. N. et al. Ecological knowledge, leadership, and the evolution of menopause in killer whales. Curr. Biol.25, 746–750 (2015). 10.1016/j.cub.2015.01.037 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Strandburg-Peshkin, A., Clutton-Brock, T. & Manser, M. B. Burrow usage patterns and decision-making in meerkat groups. Behav. Ecol.31, 292–302 (2020). [Google Scholar]
- 33.King, A. J., Douglas, C. M. S., Huchard, E., Isaac, N. J. B. & Cowlishaw, G. Dominance and affiliation mediate despotism in a social primate. Curr. Biol.18, 1833–1838 (2008). 10.1016/j.cub.2008.10.048 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Smith, J. E. et al. Leadership in mammalian societies: emergence, distribution, power, and payoff. Trends Ecol. Evol.31, 54–66 (2016). 10.1016/j.tree.2015.09.013 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Strandburg-Peshkin, A., Farine, D. R., Couzin, I. D. & Crofoot, M. C. Shared decision-making drives collective movement in wild baboons. Science348, 1358–1361 (2015). 10.1126/science.aaa5099 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Papageorgiou, D. & Farine, D. R. Shared decision-making allows subordinates to lead when dominants monopolize resources. Sci. Adv.6, eaba5881 (2020). 10.1126/sciadv.aba5881 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Yomosa, M., Mizuguchi, T., Vásárhelyi, G. & Nagy, M. Coordinated behaviour in pigeon flocks. PLoS ONE10, 1–17 (2015). 10.1371/journal.pone.0140558 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Whitehead, H. Consensus movements by groups of sperm whales. Mar. Mamm. Sci.32, 1402–1415 (2016). 10.1111/mms.12338 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Gall, G. E. C., Strandburg-Peshkin, A., Clutton-Brock, T. H. & Manser, M. B. As dusk falls: collective decisions about the return to sleeping sites in meerkats. Anim. Behav.132, 91–99 (2017). 10.1016/j.anbehav.2017.08.001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Walker, R. H., King, A. J., McNutt, J. W. & Jordan, N. R. Sneeze to leave: African wild dogs (Lycaon pictus) use variable quorum thresholds facilitated by sneezes in collective decisions. Proc. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci.284, 20170347 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- 41.Furuichi, T. Variation in intergroup relationships among species and among and within local populations of African apes. Int. J. Primatol.41, 203–223 (2020). 10.1007/s10764-020-00134-x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Popat, R., Cornforth, D. M., McNally, L. & Brown, S. P. Collective sensing and collective responses in quorum-sensing bacteria. J. R. Soc. Interface12, 20140882 (2015). 10.1098/rsif.2014.0882 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Granato, E. T., Meiller-Legrand, T. A. & Foster, K. R. The evolution and ecology of bacterial warfare. Curr. Biol.29, R521–R537 (2019). 10.1016/j.cub.2019.04.024 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Tokuyama, N. & Furuichi, T. Leadership of old females in collective departures in wild bonobos (Pan paniscus) at Wamba. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol.71, 1–10 (2017). 10.1007/s00265-017-2277-5 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Maynard Smith, J. & Price George, R. The logic of animal conflict. Nature246, 15–18 (1973). 10.1038/246015a0 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Pyritz, L. W., King, A. J., Sueur, C. & Fichtel, C. Reaching a consensus: terminology and concepts used in coordination and decision-making research. Int. J. Primatol.32, 1268–1278 (2011). 10.1007/s10764-011-9524-9 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Mathew, S. & Boyd, R. Punishment sustains large-scale cooperation in prestate warfare. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA108, 11375–11380 (2011). 10.1073/pnas.1105604108 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Arseneau-Robar, T. J. M. et al. Female monkeys use both the carrot and the stick to promote male participation in intergroup fights. Proc. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci.283, 20161817 (2016). 10.1098/rspb.2016.1817 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Kingma, S. A., Santema, P., Taborsky, M. & Komdeur, J. Group augmentation and the evolution of cooperation. Trends Ecol. Evol.29, 476–484 (2014). 10.1016/j.tree.2014.05.013 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Sääksvuori, L. Intergroup conflict, ostracism, and the evolution of cooperation under free migration. Behav. Ecol. Sociobiol.68, 1311–1319 (2014). 10.1007/s00265-014-1741-8 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Gavrilets, S., Auerbach, J., & Van Vugt, M. Convergence to consensus in heterogeneous groups and the emergence of informal leadership. Sci. Rep.6, 1–10 (2016). 10.1038/srep29704 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Glowacki, L. & Wrangham, R. Warfare and reproductive success in a tribal population. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA112, 348–353 (2015). 10.1073/pnas.1412287112 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Gavrilets, S. & Fortunato, L. A solution to the collective action problem in between-group conflict with within-group inequality. Nat. Commun.5, 1–11 (2014). 10.1038/ncomms4526 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Ioannou, C. C., Rocque, F., Herbert-Read, J. E., Duffield, C. & Firth, J. A. Predators attacking virtual prey reveal the costs and benefits of leadership. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci.116, 8925–8930 (2019). 10.1073/pnas.1816323116 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Johnstone, R. A. & Manica, A. Evolution of personality differences in leadership. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA108, 8373–8378 (2011). 10.1073/pnas.1102191108 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Rands, S. A., Cowlishaw, G., Pettifor, R. A., Rowcliffe, J. M. & Johnstone, R. A. Spontaneous emergence of leaders and followers in foraging pairs. Nature423, 432–434 (2003). 10.1038/nature01630 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Heinsohn, R. & Packer, C. Complex cooperative strategies in group-territorial African Lion. Science269, 1260–1263 (1995). 10.1126/science.7652573 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Haig, D. Parental antagonism, relatedness asymmetries, and genomic imprinting. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B Biol. Sci.264, 1657–1662 (1997). 10.1098/rspb.1997.0230 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Haig, D. Placental hormones, genomic imprinting, and maternal—fetal communication. J. Evol. Biol.9, 357–380 (1996). 10.1046/j.1420-9101.1996.9030357.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Pamilo, P. & Rosengren, R. Sex ratio strategies in Formica ants. Oikos40 24–35 (1983).
- 61.Boomsma, J. J. & Grafen, A. Colony‐level sex ratio selection in the eusocial Hymenoptera. J. Evol. Biol.4, 383–407 (1991). 10.1046/j.1420-9101.1991.4030383.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 62.King, D. C. & Zeckhauser, R. J. Punching and counter-punching in the US Congress: why party leaders tend to be extremists. In Presented at the Conference on Leadership 2002: Bridging the Gap Between Theory and Practice (The Center for Public Leadership, 2002).
- 63.Davis, G. H., Crofoot, M. C. & Farine, D. R. Using optimal foraging theory to infer how groups make collective decisions. Trends Ecol. Evol.37, 942–952 (2022). [DOI] [PubMed]
- 64.Lee, H. C. & Teichroeb, J. A. Partially shared consensus decision making and distributed leadership in vervet monkeys: older females lead the group to forage. Am. J. Phys. Anthropol.161, 580–590 (2016). 10.1002/ajpa.23058 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Stanford, C. B. The social behavior of chimpanzees and bonobos: empirical evidence and shifting assumptions. Curr. Anthropol.39, 399–420 (1998). 10.1086/204757 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 66.Wrangham, R. W. & Glowacki, L. Intergroup aggression in chimpanzees and war in nomadic hunter-gatherers. Hum. Nat.23, 5–29 (2012). 10.1007/s12110-012-9132-1 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67.Goodall, J. The chimpanzees of Gombe: Patterns of behavior (Cambridge Mass, 1986).
- 68.Smith, J. E. et al. Sex bias in intergroup conflict and collective movements among social mammals: male warriors and female guides. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B377, 20210142 (2022). 10.1098/rstb.2021.0142 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 69.Smith, J. E., Ortiz, C. A., Buhbe, M. T. & van Vugt, M. Obstacles and opportunities for female leadership in mammalian societies: a comparative perspective. Leadersh. Q31, 101267 (2020). 10.1016/j.leaqua.2018.09.005 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 70.Ceccarelli, E., Rangel Negrín, A., Coyohua‐Fuentes, A., Canales‐Espinosa, D. & Dias, P. A. D. Sex differences in leadership during group movement in mantled howler monkeys (Alouatta palliata). Am. J. Primatol.82, e23099 (2020). 10.1002/ajp.23099 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71.Tecot, S. R. & Romine, N. K. Leading ladies: leadership of group movements in a pair‐living, co‐dominant, monomorphic primate across reproductive stages and fruit availability seasons. Am. J. Primatol.74, 591–601 (2012). 10.1002/ajp.22011 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72.Kurvers, R. H. J. M. et al. Personality differences explain leadership in barnacle geese. Anim. Behav.78, 447–453 (2009). 10.1016/j.anbehav.2009.06.002 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 73.Nakayama, S., Harcourt, J. L. & Johnstone, R. A. Initiative, personality and leadership in pairs of foraging fish. Plos ONE.7, e36606 (2012). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- 74.Sasaki, T. et al. Personality and the collective: Bold homing pigeons occupy higher leadership ranks in flocks. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci.373, 20170038 (2017). [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- 75.Gilby, I. C., Eberly, L. E. & Wrangham, R. W. Economic profitability of social predation among wild chimpanzees: individual variation promotes cooperation. Anim. Behav.75, 351–360 (2008). 10.1016/j.anbehav.2007.06.008 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 76.Gilby, I. C. et al. Impact hunters’ catalyse cooperative hunting in two wild chimpanzee communities. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B: Biol. Sci.370, 20150005 (2015). 10.1098/rstb.2015.0005 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 77.Glowacki, L. & McDermott, R. Key individuals catalyse intergroup violence. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B377, 20210141 (2022). 10.1098/rstb.2021.0141 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 78.Massaro, A. P. et al. Correlates of individual participation in boundary patrols by male chimpanzees. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B377, 20210151 (2022). 10.1098/rstb.2021.0151 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Supplementary Materials
Data Availability Statement
Scripts, including those used to produce the model and generate the data used in this manuscript, are all publicly available to download from https://github.com/sankeydan/demoPeace2/.
Scripts, including those used to produce the model and generate the data used in this manuscript, are all publicly available to download from https://github.com/sankeydan/demoPeace2/.