Abstract
When making risky choices in social contexts, humans typically combine social information with individual preferences about the options at stake. It remains unknown how such decisions are made when these preferences are inaccessible or disrupted, as might be the case for individuals confronting novel options or experiencing cognitive impairment. Thus, we examined participants with lesions in insular or dorsal anterior cingulate cortex, key regions implicated in risky decision-making, as they played a gambling task where choices were made both alone and after observing others’ choices. Participants in both lesion groups showed disrupted use of standard utility-based computations about risky options. For socially situated decisions, these participants showed increased conformity with the choices of others, independent from social utility-based computations. These findings suggest that in social contexts, following others’ choices may be a heuristic for decision-making when utility-based risk processing is disrupted.
Author summary
When humans make decisions in social situations, we typically weigh both our individual preferences and information about what others choose. There are also common circumstances where individual preferences may be unavailable (e.g., when encountering new options or for individuals with certain neuropsychiatric conditions). To understand how choices are made in a social context when individual preferences are unavailable, we evaluated individuals with lesions in brain regions that encode risk preferences while these individuals made risky choices both independently and after viewing others’ choices. We find that when individual risk preferences are not computed, participants use a cognitive shortcut of making the same choices that others make. This shortcut may explain the heightened influence of others on the choices of some vulnerable individuals.
Introduction
In social contexts, decision-makers sometimes follow a crowd despite their own preferences toward a different course of action [1,2]. This phenomenon has been documented in various forms in humans [3] and in nonhuman primates [4]. Recent studies indicate that when making socially situated choices, humans combine individual preferences for the options at stake with individual valuation of social information; contributions from each of these determine when choices made in a social context diverge (or not) from that which one’s preferences outside a social context would predict [5–11]. These previous studies have largely focused on understanding how social information contributes to choices with respect to individuals’ preferences about risk.
Here, we investigated how risky decisions in social contexts are made when utility-based risk preferences are disrupted or inaccessible, as might be the case for individuals with certain psychopathologies or who are confronting novel options (e.g., Gershman & Niv [12]). Specifically, previous literature on decision-making in humans and non-human primates indicates that when individuals have a limited amount of private information, they tend to use various cognitive shortcuts or heuristics (e.g., mimicking other agents) to simplify decision processes [13–16]. In the current study, we use a risky decision-making task and examine whether such heuristics facilitate socially situated decision-making about risk when utility processing is disrupted.
Previous work has shown that individual preferences and information from others are combined during risky decision-making under social influence [7,8,11,17]. Neurally, the insular and dorsal anterior cingulate cortices (dACC) have been shown to encode an interaction between one’s own risk preference and information from others. As such, these regions show greater hemodynamic responses when an individual’s preference differs from the observed choices of others [8]. The insula and dACC have also been consistently implicated in decision-making about risky options in non-social contexts, via lesion (insula only), functional neuroimaging (insula and dACC), and electrophysiology (insula) studies [18–23]. Thus, in situations where the structural or functional integrity of these regions is disrupted (e.g., in some neurological or psychiatric disorders) or where insufficient information or differing abilities impose constraints, individual computations and decisions about risky options may be disrupted, leaving open the question of how socially informed decision-making occurs in those cases. To examine this question, we administered a gambling task in both social and non-social contexts to individuals with focal insula or dACC lesions and tested models that measured the degree to which utility-based or heuristic-based processes were implemented during decision-making.
Individuals with focal insula (N = 10) or dACC lesions (N = 6) and non-lesioned control participants (NCs; N = 28) made a series of choices between pairs of gambles alone (‘Solo’ trials) and after observing two others’ choices (‘Info’ trials; Fig 1A–1C; task developed in our previous work [7,8]). Trials comprised four distinct types: Solo, where participants did not see others’ choices; Info: ‘safe’, in which both of the two social others’ choices that the participant observed were the safer (i.e., lower payoff variance) gamble; Info: ‘risky’, in which the two social others’ choices were the riskier (i.e., higher payoff variance) gamble; and Info: ‘mix’, where one social other’s choice was the safer gamble, and one other’s choice was the riskier gamble. Info and Solo trials were intermixed throughout the task.
Results
Disrupted utility-based decision-making about risky options
To first evaluate non-social decision-making under risk in our participants, we examined how well a standard utility model (i.e., power utility function [24]) and softmax choice rule [25]; see Materials and Methods for model specifications) explained behavioral choices in Solo trials. Per economic utility theory [24], individuals’ preferences about risk can be captured by the concavity (ρ) of power utility functions (U(x) = xρ) that reflect individuals’ utility computations about risky options. We thus used a goodness-of-fit metric of the power utility model for explaining individual participants’ decisions about risky options as an indication of the extent to which utility-based decision-making was used. Specifically, we used the median negative log likelihood as it reflects the fit at the median parameter estimates which we use throughout the paper (see Methods: Behavioral model specifications and model comparison). As expected, participants with insula or dACC lesions showed worse model fit compared with NCs [i.e., comparisons of negative log likelihood (−LL) in Solo trials, P = 0.0072; see also [18–21] reporting insula or dACC involvement in utility-based decision-making under risk. This remained true after controlling for individuals’ risk preference (P = 0.0019). Post-hoc analyses by lesion area indicated that compared with NCs, participants with insula lesions showed worse model fit while participants with dACC lesions trended toward worse model fit (P = 0.032 and P = 0.073, respectively; Fig 1d; see Materials and Methods for full details and S1 Fig for model-agnostic choice behaviors). Participants with insula lesions and participants with dACC lesions did not differ in model fit (P = 0.87, Bayes factor (BFnull) = 2.27).
Socially situated decision-making about risk
Using these participants with insula or dACC lesions as exemplars, we next sought to examine whether heuristics may facilitate socially situated decision-making when utility-based risk processing is disrupted. Previously, we developed an ‘other-conferred utility (OCU)’ model and showed that the impact of social information on decisions about risky options is captured by increased utility to the option chosen by others and thus, increased likelihood of choosing this option [8]; we refer to this type of social information use as ‘OCU-based’ or ‘utility-based.’ This model, along with its modified version, has been validated in independent simulations showing both model and parameter recovery [7,26]. Here, to accommodate the possibility of incorporating social information into decisions independent of utility computations (i.e., ‘heuristic-based’ or ‘OCU-free’ use of social information), we extend our previous OCU model [8] and introduce weight parameters that allow a mixture between OCU-based and OCU-free contributions of social information to participants’ decisions (‘hybrid model’ hereafter). The OCU-free parameters allow the initial testing of zeroth order social heuristics that have been previously shown to affect decision-making [13]; in the present work, these choices are either in alignment with or in opposition to the choices made by others [8,9]. We subsequently call these choices that ‘follow’ or ‘oppose,’ respectively, those of social others. In this mixture model, weight parameters ωutility, ωfollow, and ωoppose capture the degree to which social information is incorporated into decision-making, dependent upon (ωutility) or independent from (ωfollow and ωoppose) social utility-based processes (Figs 2, S2, S3, and S4 for further model description and validation information). Note that if an individual uses social information in a way that fully relies on other-conferred utility (i.e., ωutility = 1), the mixture model prediction is equivalent to that of the original OCU model [8]; if an individual uses social information in a manner that is fully free from other-conferred utility (OCU-free; i.e., ωfollow + ωoppose = 1), their choices would be consistent with the simple heuristics of fully following or opposing those of social others, regardless of the gamble options. See S5 Fig for model comparison of the hybrid model against an only OCU-free heuristic model, an only OCU-based model, and a Solo risk preference model, showing best fit of the hybrid model for explaining participants’ choices.
Compared with non-lesion controls, participants with insula or dACC lesions as a combined group showed significantly larger following weights (ωfollow; Fig 3A; P = 0.014). This group difference result remained consistent after controlling for individuals’ risk preference (P = 0.0074). Post-hoc analyses by lesion area indicated that relative to the non-lesion controls, participants with insula lesions (P = 0.036) and with dACC lesions (P = 0.025) also both showed significantly larger ωfollow. These results indicate that individuals with focal lesions in insula or dACC implement a ‘follow others’ choices’ heuristic during decision-making in a social context, which behaviorally manifests as increased conformity with the choices of others.
Model-agnostic measures of participants’ tendency to follow the choices of others were correlated with the model-derived ωfollow (S2C and S2D Fig; for complete mixture model details, see S2A Fig). Tendencies for choices to oppose those of social others (captured in the ωoppose parameter) did not differ between participants with insula or dACC lesions and controls (Fig 3B, P = 0.20, BFnull = 1.64). A post-hoc analysis additionally shows comparable ωoppose parameters between insula lesion and dACC lesion groups (P = 0.28, BFnull = 1.48). As we hypothesized, participants with insula or dACC lesions, relative to non-lesion control participants, had diminished ωutility (Fig 3C; P = 0.0041), indicating less use of utility-based risk processing. This remained the case after controlling for individuals’ risk preference (P = 0.0018). Post-hoc analyses by lesion area indicated that participants with insula lesions had diminished ωutility (P = 0.0043); participants with dACC lesions did not differ from control participants or participants with insula lesions (dACC vs NCs: P = 0.14, BFnull = 1.17; dACC vs insula: P = 0.36, BFnull = 1.71). See S3 Fig for individual ω estimates and further examination of model weights.
If individuals with impairments in utility-based risky decision-making indeed rely on conformity to a greater extent, we may expect a parametric relationship between degree of impairment and use of the ‘follow others’ choices’ heuristic. In this case, across both lesion and control groups, individuals who are most disrupted in utility-based risky decision-making would be expected to show greater use of this heuristic when making decisions under risk in a social context. To evaluate this possibility, we used model fit (negative log likelihood; −LL) calculated for choices in Solo trials (data presented in Fig 1D) as a measure of disruption in utility-based risky decision-making and examined the association of model fit with individuals’ model-derived following weights (ωfollow). Across all three groups, individuals’ tendencies to follow the choices of social others (ωfollow) were significantly correlated with greater −LL in Solo trials (greater −LL indicating more disrupted utility-based risk processing; Pearson’s r = 0.52, P = 2.7e−04, robust correlation; Fig 3D). This relationship was consistent after controlling for individuals’ risk preference (Pearson’s r = 0.52, P = 3.0e−04, robust correlation). That is, individuals whose utility-based risky decision-making was most disrupted conformed the most with the choices of others. This relationship was replicated in an independent sample of control participants (S5B Fig), providing convergent evidence supporting the notion that there is a trade-off between utility-based processes and cognitively less demanding heuristics that facilitates decisions about risky options in a social context.
Discussion
Humans use social information in different ways to guide decision-making [27,28]. The present results provide a model-based explanation for how in social situations, individuals with disrupted utility-based risk processing may make choices about risky options. Using individuals with insula or dACC lesions as exemplars, we show that these individuals exhibit disrupted utility-based risk processing and use social information independent from utility computation to guide decisions about risky options. These findings suggest social conformity can serve as a heuristic alternative to using social information in a utility-based way during socially situated decision-making when individuals’ risk processing is impaired.
In previous studies using the same task, we have shown that when making decisions under risk, individuals combine social information with personal preferences and do so by adding other-conferred utility to the option that others choose [7,8]. Here, we identify an alternative heuristic path of using the same type of social information when personal preferences are not computed. This discovery was made possible by examining participants with lesions in insula and dACC (regions that have been consistently implicated in functional neuroimaging studies of risk processing) as exemplars of individuals with disrupted risk processing [18,19,29,30]. Our post-hoc analyses examined whether insula and dACC participants differed with regard to disruptions in risk processing; we found no evidence of group differences between insula and dACC participants in power-utility model fit to their choices on Solo trials. While to our knowledge, this work is among the first to show evidence of disrupted risk processing in participants with dACC lesions, it is perhaps unsurprising, given that dACC and insula frequently co-activate in functional neuroimaging studies of risk-related decision-making [18,19,29,30]. We also considered our work in the context of prior work implicating dMFC (often extending into dACC) in social processes [7,26,31–33]; while we did not observe social-specific differences in our dACC vs insula participants, this is an area of relevant future study.
We emphasize that the ‘follow others’ choices’ heuristic identified in the current study is consistent with a ‘copy-when-uncertain’ strategy previously demonstrated in perceptual decision-making, such that individuals are more likely to rely on the behaviors of others when they are less confident about their own decisions [34–36]. The present study adds to this literature by demonstrating that a copy-when-uncertain strategy extends to socially situated decision-making about risky options. Of note, although a ‘follow others’ choices’ heuristic seems qualitatively different from utility-based use of social information, one framework that captures both paths is a Bayesian-like update framework, in which individuals use social information to update their likelihood of choosing the safe gamble [37–40]. That is, the utility difference between gamble options may serve as a Bayesian prior, updated by novel information contained in social others’ choices. The extent to which an individual combines their priors with the novel social information depends on the relative uncertainty between the gamble utility difference and the social information where the information with lower uncertainty contributes more to the final decision (i.e., the posterior). In this framework, individuals who have disrupted utility-based risky decision-making (e.g., the lesion group herein) would be expected to have a relatively flat prior for the utility difference of gamble options. Starting with this flat prior, a Bayesian process would indicate that any subsequent choices made under social influence would be primarily driven by the social information because the social information carries more certainty than does the individuals’ computed utility difference between the choices at hand. By comparison, individuals with intact utility-based risk processing (e.g., NCs) would have relatively sharper priors for utility differences between gambles and the social information would subsequently carry less impact for participants’ decisions.
Broadly, these results have important implications for circumstances associated with suboptimal risky decision-making, such as during neurodevelopment in adolescents [41,42] or in individuals with neurological and psychiatric disorders characterized by altered decision-making [43–46]. This disrupted utility-based risk processing may in-turn play a role in the particularly prominent influence of social others in adolescent decision-making [47,48] and also in the onset and maintenance of substance misuse and related psychopathology [49,50]. In these cases, disruption to utility-based risk processing may lead to heightened influence of other people in socially situated decision-making. The presence of heuristic and utility-based processes for incorporating information from social others into risky decision-making thus suggests distinct avenues for addressing maladaptive decision-making (e.g., enhancing preferences vs changing social group composition).
The limitations of the present study suggest some avenues for future investigations. First, although the information being shown to participants in this study is social information (i.e., choices of others), it is possible that influences on participant choices may be due to a more general visual or information effect, whereby merely seeing other information (regardless of its source) may influence behavioral choices. While we previously demonstrated in non-lesioned adults using the same task that effects on participants’ behavior was indeed ‘social’ (i.e., no influence on participants choices were observed in a non-social visually controlled experiment; Supplemental Fig 8 from [8]), this may not extend to individuals with insula and/or dACC lesions. Further work is necessary to test whether the ‘follow others’ choices’ effect when risk processing is disrupted is specific to social information or more general to any type of information. Second, we combined participants with dACC or insula lesions into a single ‘lesion group’ because of the common role of these regions in risk processing [18–23] and to maximize power for our primary intention of examining socially situated decision-making under risk. Still, it is worth noting the unique roles of these regions in other cognitive processes. For example, dACC is strongly implicated in social cognition [28] and social learning [51], while insula is more strongly implicated in interoception [52]. Future studies with larger samples ought to examine specificity of foci in these regions against more nuanced decision-making models and distinct social cognitive processes. We might expect relatively stronger impairment in social information processing in individuals with dACC lesions (and potentially stronger use of heuristics), whereas we might see stronger effects of risk processing (where interoception is thought to be a key component [53]) or dissociation of different risk models (e.g., [54]) in those with insula lesions. Third, we note that the perceptual ‘copy when uncertain’ strategy has exceptions (e.g., [55]) and similarly, the use of a ‘follow others’ choices’ heuristic may not be universally implemented in individuals for whom utility-based risk preferences may be disrupted, inaccessible, or otherwise not present (e.g., during substance misuse, individuals with certain psychopathologies, adolescents confronting novel options). We look forward to future studies examining these possibilities. Lastly, we point out that the model comparison analyses indicate that the Hybrid model was not well dissociable from the OCU-based, OCU-free, and Solo RP models, perhaps due in part to the nested nature of these models or the presence of multiple overlapping processes during socially-situated decision making about risky options. While our primary findings are based on robust parameter estimates of heuristic processes within the Hybrid model, the model comparison analyses indicate that the Hybrid model alone is unlikely to capture the range of social influences on risky decision-making; future studies are necessary to implement study designs that allow these processes to be detangled (see S4 Fig for further discussion).
Social contexts affect the decisions we make [56] and information received from others governs if and how one’s decisions are influenced by social others [57, 8]. Administering a risky decision-making task to participants with insula or dACC lesions revealed contributions of social information to decision-making that are independent from those relying on individuals’ utility-based computations about risk. Our model-based analytic approach and lesion data point to social conformity as a heuristic alternative in the absence of deliberative utility-based computation, during socially-situated decision making about risky options.
Materials and methods
Ethics statement
All participants provided written informed consent and were paid for their participation. The study was approved by the Institutional Review Boards of Virginia Tech and Tiantan Hospital of Capital University of Medical Sciences, Beijing, China.
Experimental model and subject details
Participants
Forty-six neurologically intact non-lesioned control (NC) subjects (male/female = 27/19, age = 44.28±7.63), 11 with focal insula lesions (male/female = 5/6, age = 44.00±11.85), and 13 with focal dorsal anterior cingulate cortex (dACC) lesions (male/female = 8/5, age = 38.38±11.43) participated in the current study. All participants reported no previous or current psychiatric conditions; all controls reported no previous or current neurological conditions. All participants with lesions were recruited from the Patient’s Registry of Beijing Tiantan Hospital, Beijing, China. NCs were recruited in local Beijing communities and were matched with patients for age, sex, and education.
Participants who showed choices that met a priori–defined behavioral exclusion criteria were excluded from all analyses. Specifically, 11 NCs, one participant with an insula lesion, and three participants with dACC lesions who chose the option with greater high payoff value less frequently as the probability of winning increased (comparing average gamble choices between winning probabilities of 40% to 90%) were excluded. Seven NCs and two participants with dACC lesions who always chose the safer or riskier gamble on all 24 Solo trials were additionally excluded. These exclusionary criteria are necessary to ensure that there are enough trials for accurate parameter estimation and that the assumptions underlying model estimation are met. We note that we excluded these participants from estimation because for participants who choose all risky or all safe, bi-directional social influence is not possible. That is, participants who always chose the risky option cannot be influenced to make riskier choices; similarly, participants who always chose the safe option cannot be influenced to make safer decisions. Finally, two additional participants from the dACC lesion group whose lesions were not localized within the dACC region were excluded from all analyses. Therefore, the analyzed sample included 28 NCs (male/female = 17/11, age = 42.82 ± 8.09), 10 participants with insula lesions (male/female = 4/6, age = 43.10 ± 12.09), and 6 participants with dACC lesions (male/female = 4/2, age = 34.33 ± 6.74; see S7 Fig for evaluation and confirmation of our main results across different exclusion criteria and further discussion).
Groups were well matched in sex (P = 0.59; NC vs insula: P = 0.28; NC vs dACC: P = 0.80; dACC vs insula: P = 0.34), lesion laterality (P = 0.54), education (P = 0.18; NC vs insula: P = 0.18; NC vs dACC: P = 0.34; dACC vs insula: P = 0.97), days since surgery (P = 0.37), lesion size (P = 0.92), and handedness (P = 0.74; NC vs insula: P = 0.44; NC vs dACC: P = 0.14; dACC vs insula: P = 0.12). Age was comparable between lesion and control groups (P = 0.31), between NCs and participants with insula lesions (P = 0.93) and between the two lesion groups (P = 0.13), whereas those with dACC lesions were significantly younger than NCs (P = 0.024). The lesion group had significantly lower Mini-Mental State Examination (MMSE [58]) scores than NCs (P = 0.0005; NC vs insula: P = 0.0013; NC vs dACC: P = 0.0091). However, the two lesion groups had comparable MMSE scores (P = 0.97). Because MMSE and age were different between at least one lesion group and NCs, we examined whether disrupted utility-based risky decision-making (Fig 1D) still differed between the lesion group and NCs after accounting for variation due to these demographics and whether the correlation between model fit and social heuristic remained significant (Fig 3D). Specifically, we first regressed out age or MMSE in separate multiple linear regression models and then performed either a group comparison or robust correlation test on those residuals to confirm lesion group or omega follow, respectively remained a significant predictor of disruption in utility-based risky decision-making. Indeed the lesion group was a significant predictor of disruption in utility-based risky decision-making after regressing out either age (P = 0.0072) or MMSE (P = 0.0094) and omega follow was significantly correlated with disruption in utility-based risky decision-making after regressing out either age (r = 0.46, P = 0.0016) or MMSE (r = 0.43, P = 0.0038) (Table 1).
Table 1. Participant characteristics.
Non-lesion control (N = 28) |
Insula lesion (N = 10) |
dACC lesion (N = 6) |
|
---|---|---|---|
Male/Female | 17/11 | 4/6 | 4/2 |
Age (years)a | 42.82 ± 8.09 | 43.10 ± 12.09 | 34.33 ± 6.74 |
Handedness (R/L) | (27/1) | (10/0) | (5/1) |
Education (years) | 12.43 ± 1.95 | 11.4 ± 2.37 | 11.33 ± 4.63 |
MMSE | 29.57 ± 0.79 | 28.30 ± 1.42 | 28.33 ± 1.51 |
Days since surgery | — | 555.90 ± 560.31 | 815.33 ± 520.95 |
Laterality (R/L) | — | 5/5 | 4/2 |
Lesion size (ml) | — | 44.93 ± 34.12 | 46.89 ± 41.73 |
L, left; R, right; MMSE, Mini-Mental State Examination [58]; aThe age at the testing date; Regression analysis confirmed that our main findings were not affected by group demographic differences (see Materials and Methods for statistical comparison details). Data are represented as mean ± SD.
Method details
Lesion reconstruction
Lesion reconstruction was performed by a research assistant who was blind to the study design and behavioral results (C.T.) and was confirmed by a senior researcher (X.G.). In brief, lesions evident on T1- and T2- weighted MRI scans were identified and transcribed onto corresponding sections of a template to create a volume of interest (.voi) file. The template was derived from an MRI volume of a normal control (ch2.nii) created by Christopher Rorden (University of South Carolina, Columbia, SC) and provided for use with MRIcron [59]. This.voi file was used to measure the location (MNI coordinates) and volume (in ml) of individual lesions and to create within group overlaps of multiple lesions using the MRIcron program.
Experimental procedures
Participants were asked to make a series of choices between two risky gambles alone (Solo trials) and after observing others’ choices (Info trials) (Fig 1A) [8]. In each pair of gambles, one gamble was always riskier than the other gamble; the two gambles had the same high- and low- payoff probabilities, but the riskier gamble had greater payoff variance. Participants were instructed that they were playing within a group of five others and that two other players’ choices would be randomly selected and shown on some trials. To ensure participants’ understanding, a brief quiz was administered following the task instruction and any erroneous answers were addressed. Unbeknownst to participants, for the purpose of the current study, Info trials were drawn without replacement from a uniform distribution that comprised equal numbers of trials where both other players chose the safe gamble (Info: ‘safe’), both others chose the risky gamble (Info: ‘risky’), or one player chose the safe and the other player chose the risky gamble (Info: ‘mix’). Gambles used in the current study were developed to optimally observe risky decision-making under social influence, as detailed in Chung et al. [8]. In brief, we developed eight unique lottery menus adapted from Holt and Laury [60]. For each participant, four lottery menus were randomly selected among the eight lottery menus and paired with six levels of payoff probabilities (probability of high-payoff: 40, 50, 60, 70, 80, and 90%). These 24 unique pairs of gambles (one safer and one riskier gamble) were used in each trial type (Solo; Info: ‘safe’; Info: ‘risky’; and Info: ‘mix’), so in total, each participant had 96 trials (4 lottery menus × 6 probabilities × 4 trial types). The trial order was randomized for menu × probability × trial type with a unique order per participant. Participants were informed that their final payment was not dependent on any other players’ choices and would be paid at the end of the task based on their choices. At the end of the task, one of the participants’ choices was randomly selected and carried out to determine their final payment.
We note that we have previously shown that the present task captures a social influence process (as opposed to a more general visual information effect or non-social influence). Specifically, in our previously published work [8], we introduced the task used here and also enrolled a separate cohort of N = 30 participants in a non-social condition designed to evaluate the ‘social’ nature of the social influence effect. In the non-social control task, participants were instructed that the two other ‘players’ were computers choosing between the gamble options, and the players were labeled as such on the display; all other task aspects were identical to the social version. In this non-social control, no effect of the computer chosen options on participants’ choices were observed (see S8, reprinted with permission from [8], for further information).
Quantification and statistical analysis
Statistical analyses
All statistical tests, except where indicated otherwise, were analyzed using a non-parametric bootstrapping method [61]. For each test, the data from all groups were drawn with replacement and assigned to groups that each had equal size as the original groups. For 10,000 iterations, the statistical test of interest was then performed on this ‘resampled’ data to obtain the null distribution. Specifically, for comparison between groups (t-tests and F-tests), a null test statistic distribution was obtained by randomly selecting data points from a set of pooled data points from all participants in each group being compared. For within-group analysis (correlation and regression tests), data were ‘unpaired’ by independently drawing the dependent and independent variables for each subject from the set of group values for that given variable. For the categorical demographics data, a chi-squared bootstrapped test was used; this test has been shown to be more accurate than the chi-square test on its own and has been suggested to be better than Fisher’s exact test which has been criticized for being overly conservative [62]. For all tests, once the null distribution of the test statistic was obtained, significance could be assessed by comparison with the actual test statistic. Specifically, test statistics whose absolute value was greater than 9,500 of the absolute value of the null samples were considered significant (the equivalent of a two-tailed test with alpha level of 0.05). P values were calculated by getting the total percentage of null samples (absolute value) whose test statistics were greater than the absolute value of the test statistic of the actual data set. All statistical analysis was done using MATLAB R2015a (Mathworks) and R 3.3.0 [63]. To test our main hypotheses, we combined the dACC and insula lesion groups. When significant differences were observed, to assess robustness of differences to individual risk preferences, we performed the same statistical test again but on the residuals of the variable of interest after regressing out individuals’ risk preference. Additionally, we proceeded with post-hoc analyses comparing dACC and insula lesion groups separately to explore the possibility of lesion-specific differences. When non-significant results were observed, we followed up with Bayesian null hypothesis testing (using the bayesFactor package in MATLAB) to quantify the extent of evidence (BFnull) that the groups being compared were similar (for t-tests) or that the variables being compared were unrelated (for correlation tests).
Computational modeling
The full model used in this paper is labeled as the Hybrid model. This model is a mixture of two different models: OCU-based and OCU-free models. Below, we first define these models separately, then specify the full model. Note that because the full model is a mixture model, the OCU-based and OCU-free models are both nested within this full model. We additionally use the following nested models in a formal model comparison: (i) Solo risk preference, (ii) OCU-based, and (iii) OCU-free (S4 Fig).
1) Solo risk preference. This model is a standard power utility model used to explain utility-based risky-decision making. We use this model to test whether insula and dACC lesion groups had disrupted utility-based risky decision-making on Solo trials. Note that this model is a nested model of the OCU model (where OCU = 0).
where Phigh is the probability of high-payoff, V is the value of the high- and low- payoffs (as indicated) in the safe and risky gambles, and α is risk preference where α = 1 indicates risk neutrality, α > 1 indicates risk seeking, and 0 < α < 1 indicates risk aversion. β is the sensitivity to utility differences between the safe and risky gambles (inverse temperature) where high value indicates less noisy behavior. The model includes four free parameters (two hyperparameters [mean, variance] × two parameters): β and α.
2) OCU-based model. The OCU-based model adds utility (positive or negative) to the option chosen by others, and thus modifies one’s original subjective valuation of the option that was computed based on their own risk preference:
where OCU is an additional utility added to the gamble chosen by others, and δ is an indicator where δ = 1 for Info: ‘safe’ trials, δ = –1 for Info: ‘risky’ trials, and δ = 0 otherwise. The model includes six free parameters (two hyperparameters [mean, variance] × three parameters): β, α, and OCU.
3) OCU-free model. This model assumes that individuals have a mixed tendency to follow others’ unanimous choices, and that they use their own risk preference on Solo and Info: ‘mix’ trials (i.e., Psafe = [1 + exp(−β (Usafe − Urisky))]−1).
ωfollow: This ‘follow others’ choices’ weight captures participants’ tendency to select the same option as chosen by others (the safe or risky gamble), independent of utility computations.
ωoppose: This ‘oppose others’ choices’ weight captures participants’ tendency to choose the different option from the choice of others independent of utility computations.
Note that Pfollow and Poppose are defined as probabilities of choosing the safe gamble, following and opposing others’ choices, respectively.
Two normalizing weights—ωfollow and ωoppose—determine a relative relationship. Note that ωfollow + ωoppose = 1 in this model and that each Info: ‘safe’ and Info: ‘risky’ trial choice is assumed to arise from a combination of the mixture weights. The model includes five free parameters (two hyperparameters [mean, variance] × two parameters + two weights minus one): β, α, and one ω. Note that although there are two weights in this model, only one is considered a free parameter; the second can only take on only one value since they must add to unity.
4) Social: Hybrid model. We constructed a hybrid model of OCU-based and OCU-free models, which extends our previously suggested ‘other-conferred utility (OCU)’ model [8]. The extended mixture model uses weights, combining the three weights described above as follows:
Note that POCU on Solo and Info: ‘mix’ trials is equivalent to one’s probability of choosing the safe gamble based on utility differences between the safe and risky gambles (P(safe) = POCU = [1 + exp(−β (Usafe− Urisky))]−1). The Hybrid model includes eight free parameters (two hyperparameters [mean, variance] × three parameters + three weights minus one): inverse temperature β, risk preference α, OCU, and two ωs.
We extended this model to include the possibility that social information is used in the decision-making process independently of utility computation. This mixture model (‘Hybrid’ model) consists of three probability weights, including: (i) probability of choosing the same gamble as others independent of the gamble information, (ii) probability of choosing the different option from others independent of the option information, and (iii) probability of choosing the safe option determined based on the expected utility [24] difference between the two options after taking into account the additional utility added to the option chosen by others (OCU). Three normalizing weights—ωfollow, ωoppose, and ωutility—determine a relative relationship. Note that ωfollow + ωoppose + ωutility = 1 and that each choice on Info: ‘safe’ and Info: ‘risky’ trials is represented as a mixture. The OCU weight (ωutility) specifies how much one uses social information following the OCU-based computation, while the ‘follow others’ choices’ weight (ωfollow) specifies the extent to which one uses the OCU-free heuristic (Fig 2). Alternative models for risk and social influence are discussed in S1 Text.
Behavioral model specifications and model comparison
For each model, unless otherwise specified, all 96 trials per participant were used for parameter estimations. Each model was constructed in a hierarchical structure where individuals were assumed to be sampled from a common group level distribution [64], aside from the weight parameters. For all hierarchical parameters, the group level distributions were defined as Gaussian with free group-level mean (μ), SD (σ), and a standard normal distribution (Normal(0, 1)) following non-centered parameterization [65]. We specified one group level distribution for each parameter across the lesion and control groups. For inverse temperature, an additional ‘group difference’ parameter was estimated separately for both the insula and dACC lesion groups, as these groups differed from NCs in their inverse temperature estimates in preliminary analyses examining Solo trials using the solo risk preference model. For inverse temperature β and risk preference α, we applied an exponential transformation. We estimated the hyperparameters (i.e., group-level priors) for β, α, and OCU using weak priors: μ ~ Normal(0, 10) and σ ~ half-Cauchy(0, 2.5). Sets of ω were defined as simplex, so that the sum of weights was always 1. We applied a group-level uniform distribution to ωs, thus the weights were only estimated at an individual-level.
For all parameter estimations, we used Markov chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) with the No-U-Turn Sampler (NUTS) [66] variant of Hamiltonian Monte Carlo implemented in Stan [67] in its R interface [65]. A total of four chains were run where each drew 5000 samples, discarding the first 2000 samples for burn-in (giving a total of 12,000 post-burn-in draws). All values of the potential scale reduction factor () were below 1.1 and we visually inspected the chains for parameter convergence and good mixing [68].
As specified above, the Hybrid model is the most general model. That is, other models can be represented as a special case of the general model (nested models). When comparing model fits between participant groups, we calculated the median negative log likelihood (–LL). To formally compare fits between models including penalties for model complexity, we computed an integrated Bayesian Information Criteria (iBIC) [69] per model. Note that iBIC evaluates model fit not just at point estimates, but across the whole posterior distribution [69].
Parameter comparison
Because individuals’ estimated parameters using hierarchical Bayesian estimation are dependent on the group posterior, to allow for group differences to be identified (if they are present), we estimated two additional group-level mean difference parameters for both the inverse temperature and risk preference parameters; statistical tests were conducted by examining whether or not the 95% credible interval (CI) for each group-level parameter crosses zero. Because we found inverse temperature, but not risk preference, differences between groups in the Solo trials, all models presented here (unless otherwise specified) were estimated using an inverse temperature mean difference parameter for each lesion group.
Bootstrapped t-tests were used to compare weights among groups. Note that the weights are not dependent on the group distribution (because they were not part of a hierarchical structure), and thus, classical t-tests can be used to examine individual differences (Fig 3A–3C). To examine the correlation between model fit (−LL) and ωfollow, −LL was estimated from the Solo risk preference model using only Solo trials and ωfollow was estimated from the Hybrid model (Fig 3D).
Parameter recovery
To confirm that the task design is sensitive enough to capture individual differences within the model structure, we sampled 44 sets (the same as our sample size) of parameters (α and OCU for 44 simulated subjects; ‘true parameters’ hereafter) using the mean and standard deviation for the estimated group-level distributions (estimated from individuals’ raw choice data). Actual β parameters were used from each subject. For the three weights (ωfollow, ωoppose, and ωutility), we sampled the weights uniformly from a unit simplex, satisfying ωfollow + ωoppose + ωutility = 1 and restricting values between minimum and maximum values of subject ωs. Using the same gamble sequences that were presented to participants, we simulated individual choice data, and examined whether the true parameters were recovered or not. Because simulated choices are subject to some randomness, some simulated choice sets generated sequences that did not meet inclusion criteria for the study. As specified earlier (in Participants), this can lead to estimation issues. Thus, simulated behaviors went through the same exclusionary criteria as actual participants’ behavior (see Participants for exclusion criteria). If a simulated participant’s behavior was excluded, a new set of parameters was generated and used to re-simulate behavioral choices. The same parameter estimation procedure was used as described above. All estimated parameters were significantly correlated with the true parameters used to generate simulated data (inverse temperature (log transform): Pearson’s r = 0.81, P = 1.86e−11; risk preference: Pearson’s r = 0.86, P = 7.32e−14; OCUnormalized: Pearson’s r = 0.76, P = 2.75e−09; ωfollow: Pearson’s r = 0.88, P = 4.38e−15; ωoppose: Pearson’s r = 0.90, P = 1.46e−16; ωutility: Pearson’s r = 0.73, P = 2.44e−08). Note that the OCU parameter was normalized to show the actual contribution of OCU to the utility function, as follows:
Stan makes it possible to efficiently estimate models with multiple hierarchical levels and many parameters. It does so by using a Hamiltonian Monte Carlo algorithm to move quickly through the posterior distribution with minimal correlation between parameters. To efficiently sample from the posterior distribution, it simulates a Hamiltonian ‘trajectory.’ Comparing the initial and final Hamiltonian values in a given iteration provides a straightforward way to detect potential sampling errors. Specifically, these are detected when Stan’s approximation of a Hamiltonian trajectory deviates significantly from the true Hamiltonian trajectory, called a ‘divergent transition.’ In practice, when these ‘divergent transitions’ occur, it can bias the posterior distribution. To be clear, none of the models estimated on participant data had any divergent transitions. However, in model recovery for the Hybrid model, approximately 1.05% of iterations had divergent transitions. Because we know the actual estimates that the simulated data was generated from, we can directly test if the divergent transitions biased the recovery results. To determine this, we compare the estimates to the true parameters. By definition, if the divergent transitions bias the posterior, it would push the estimates away from the true parameters. As we see strong correlations between the true parameters and parameter estimates from simulated data, we conclude that the divergent transitions did not bias the posterior estimates and that the model is sensitive enough to capture individual differences within the model structure. Similar model estimation issues and logic apply to the model recovery (S4) and exclusion criteria analyses (S7).
Model recovery
In addition to parameter recovery, we performed model recovery to assess whether the four models used and tested in this paper are dissociable [70]. To do so, we simulated participant choices using each of the four models: Hybrid, Solo risk preference, OCU-based, and OCU-free. We simulated choice data according to each model for 44 subjects (referred to as ‘Simulated model’ hereafter). These data were created based on parameters drawn from the actual distribution of estimated parameters for each model, restricted to be within the range of parameter estimates. Actual β parameters were used for each model (in the same way as Parameter recovery). The data generated from each Simulated model was then used to fit all four models. We then calculated how well each of these models (Fit model) fit the data using iBIC. The fits are calculated at the group level as total iBIC (S4a) and at an individual level using participant counts of best fit for each model, calculated as a proportion summing to 100% for each Simulated model to calculate a confusion matrix (S4b) or calculated as a proportion summing to 100% for each Fit model to calculate the inversion matrix (S4c). We note that these analyses indicate that these models are not well-dissociable. Thus, while our main results are based on robust parameter estimates of the Hybrid model, it is important to keep in mind that the Hybrid model alone is unlikely to fully and uniquely capture the range of social influences on risky decision-making. See S4 for further discussion of this point.
Supporting information
Acknowledgments
We thank J. Lee for his research support and J. Shin for his technical assistance.
Data Availability
De-identified data and custom code are available on Virginia Tech GitLab (https://code.vt.edu/maorloff/insula-lesions-and-social-heuristic.git).
Funding Statement
This work was supported in part by the National Institutes of Health (AA029222 to P.H.C.; DA036017, DA122948, DA061024 to B.C.; DA051573 to P.H.C & B.C.; DA042274 to P.H.C. & D.C.), the Virginia Tech College of Science Faculty Fellowship to B.C, the Virginia Tech Patricia Caldwell Faculty Fellowship to P.H.C., and the National Research Foundation of Korea (NRF-2020S1A3A2A02097375 to D.C.). X.G. was supported in part by the National Institute on Drug Abuse (DA043695, DA049243) and National Institute of Mental Health (MH120789, MH124115, MH122611, MH123069). The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.
References
- 1.Banerjee AV. A Simple Model of Herd Behavior. Q J Econ. 1992;107: 797–817. doi: 10.2307/2118364 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Rook L. An Economic Psychological Approach to Herd Behavior. J Econ Issues. 2016;40: 75–95. doi: 10.1080/00213624.2006.11506883 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Raafat RM, Chater N, Frith C. Herding in humans. Trends Cogn Sci. 2009;13: 420–428. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.08.002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Waal E van de, Borgeaud C, Whiten A. Potent Social Learning and Conformity Shape a Wild Primate’s Foraging Decisions. Science. 2013;340: 483–485. doi: 10.1126/science.1232769 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Campbell-Meiklejohn DK, Bach DR, Roepstorff A, Dolan RJ, Frith CD. How the Opinion of Others Affects Our Valuation of Objects. Curr Biol. 2010;20: 1165–1170. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2010.04.055 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Charpentier CJ, Moutsiana C, Garrett N, Sharot T. The Brain’s Temporal Dynamics from a Collective Decision to Individual Action. J Neurosci. 2014;34: 5816–5823. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.4107-13.2014 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Chung D, Orloff MA, Lauharatanahirun N, Chiu PH, King-Casas B. Valuation of peers’ safe choices is associated with substance-naïveté in adolescents. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2020;117: 31729–31737. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Chung D, Christopoulos GI, King-Casas B, Ball SB, Chiu PH. Social signals of safety and risk confer utility and have asymmetric effects on observers’ choices. Nat Neurosci. 2015;18: 912–916. doi: 10.1038/nn.4022 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Izuma K, Adolphs R. Social Manipulation of Preference in the Human Brain. Neuron. 2013;78: 563–573. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2013.03.023 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Klucharev V, Hytönen K, Rijpkema M, Smidts A, Fernández G. Reinforcement learning signal predicts social conformity. Neuron. 2009;61: 140–151. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2008.11.027 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Suzuki S, Jensen ELS, Bossaerts P, O’Doherty JP. Behavioral contagion during learning about another agent’s risk-preferences acts on the neural representation of decision-risk. Proc National Acad Sci. 2016;113: 3755–3760. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1600092113 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Gershman SJ, Niv Y. Novelty and Inductive Generalization in Human Reinforcement Learning. Top Cogn Sci. 2015;7: 391–415. doi: 10.1111/tops.12138 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Gigerenzer G, Gaissmaier W. Heuristic Decision Making. Annu Rev Psychol. 2011;62: 451–482. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-120709-145346 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Hertwig R, Herzog SM. Fast and Frugal Heuristics: Tools of Social Rationality. Soc Cognition. 2009;27: 661–698. doi: 10.1521/soco.2009.27.5.661 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Kendal RL, Coolen I, Laland KN. The role of conformity in foraging when personal and social information conflict. Behav Ecol. 2004;15: 269–277. doi: 10.1093/beheco/arh008 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Kendal R, Hopper LM, Whiten A, Brosnan SF, Lambeth SP, Schapiro SJ, et al. Chimpanzees copy dominant and knowledgeable individuals: implications for cultural diversity. Evol Hum Behav. 2015;36: 65–72. doi: 10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2014.09.002 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Sip KE, Smith DV, Porcelli AJ, Kar K, Delgado MR. Social closeness and feedback modulate susceptibility to the framing effect. Soc Neurosci. 2014;10: 35–45. doi: 10.1080/17470919.2014.944316 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Brown JW, Braver TS. Risk prediction and aversion by anterior cingulate cortex. Cognitive, Affective, & Behavioral Neuroscience. 2007;7: 266–277. doi: 10.3758/cabn.7.4.266 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Christopoulos GI, Tobler PN, Bossaerts P, Dolan RJ, Schultz W. Neural Correlates of Value, Risk, and Risk Aversion Contributing to Decision Making under Risk. J Neurosci. 2009;29: 12574–12583. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2614-09.2009 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Clark L, Bechara A, Damasio H, Aitken MRF, Sahakian BJ, Robbins TW. Differential effects of insular and ventromedial prefrontal cortex lesions on risky decision-making. Brain. 2008;131: 1311–1322. doi: 10.1093/brain/awn066 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Weller JA, Levin IP, Shiv B, Bechara A. The effects of insula damage on decision-making for risky gains and losses. Soc Neurosci. 2009;4: 347–358. doi: 10.1080/17470910902934400 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Cecchi R, Collomb-Clerc A, Rachidi I, Minotti L, Kahane P, Pessiglione M, et al. Direct stimulation of anterior insula and ventromedial prefrontal cortex disrupts economic choices. Nat Commun. 2024;15: 7508. doi: 10.1038/s41467-024-51822-8 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Cecchi R, Vinckier F, Hammer J, Marusic P, Nica A, Rheims S, et al. Intracerebral mechanisms explaining the impact of incidental feedback on mood state and risky choice. Elife. 2022;11: e72440. doi: 10.7554/eLife.72440 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Bernoulli D. Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk. Econometrica. 1954;22: 23. doi: 10.2307/1909829 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 25.McKelvey RD, Palfrey TR. Quantal Response Equilibria for Normal Form Games. Games and Economic Behavior. 1995;10: 6–38. [Google Scholar]
- 26.Ciranka S, Bos W van den. Social Influence in Adolescent Decision-Making: A Formal Framework. Front Psychol. 2019;10: 1915. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.01915 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Lee H, Chung D. Characterization of the Core Determinants of Social Influence From a Computational and Cognitive Perspective. Frontiers Psychiatry. 2022;13: 846535. doi: 10.3389/fpsyt.2022.846535 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Apps MAJ, Rushworth MFS, Chang SWC. The Anterior Cingulate Gyrus and Social Cognition: Tracking the Motivation of Others. Neuron. 2016;90: 692–707. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2016.04.018 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Mohr PNC, Biele G, Heekeren HR. Neural Processing of Risk. J Neurosci. 2010;30: 6613–6619. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.0003-10.2010 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Wu S, Sun S, Camilleri JA, Eickhoff SB, Yu R. Better the devil you know than the devil you don’t: Neural processing of risk and ambiguity. NeuroImage. 2021;236: 118109. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2021.118109 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Somerville LH, Jones RM, Ruberry EJ, Dyke JP, Glover G, Casey BJ. The Medial Prefrontal Cortex and the Emergence of Self-Conscious Emotion in Adolescence. Psychol Sci. 2012;24: 1554–1562. doi: 10.1177/0956797613475633 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Christopoulos GI, King-Casas B. With you or against you: Social orientation dependent learning signals guide actions made for others. Neuroimage. 2015;104: 326–335. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2014.09.011 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Schiller D, Freeman JB, Mitchell JP, Uleman JS, Phelps EA. A neural mechanism of first impressions. Nat Neurosci. 2009;12: 508–514. doi: 10.1038/nn.2278 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Toelch U, Bach DR, Dolan RJ. The neural underpinnings of an optimal exploitation of social information under uncertainty. Soc Cogn Affect Neur. 2014;9: 1746–1753. doi: 10.1093/scan/nst173 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Morgan TJH, Rendell LE, Ehn M, Hoppitt W, Laland KN. The evolutionary basis of human social learning. Proc Royal Soc B Biological Sci. 2011;279: 653–662. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2011.1172 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Laland KN. Social learning strategies. Anim Learn Behav. 2004;32: 4–14. doi: 10.3758/bf03196002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Charpentier CJ, O’Doherty JP. The application of computational models to social neuroscience: promises and pitfalls. Soc Neurosci. 2018;13: 637–647. doi: 10.1080/17470919.2018.1518834 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Martino BD, Bobadilla-Suarez S, Nouguchi T, Sharot T, Love BC. Social Information Is Integrated into Value and Confidence Judgments According to Its Reliability. Journal of Neuroscience. 2017;37: 6066–6074. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3880-16.2017 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Park SA, Goïame S, O’Connor DA, Dreher J-C. Integration of individual and social information for decision-making in groups of different sizes. Plos Biol. 2017;15: e2001958. doi: 10.1371/journal.pbio.2001958 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Toelch U, Dolan RJ. Informational and Normative Influences in Conformity from a Neurocomputational Perspective. Trends Cogn Sci. 2015;19: 579–589. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.007 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Defoe IN, Dubas JS, Figner B, Aken MAG van. A Meta-Analysis on Age Differences in Risky Decision Making: Adolescents Versus Children and Adults. Psychol Bull. 2015;141: 48–84. doi: 10.1037/a0038088 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Paulsen DJ, Platt ML, Huettel SA, Brannon EM. Decision-Making Under Risk in Children, Adolescents, and Young Adults. Front Psychol. 2011;2: 72. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00072 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Balconi M, Finocchiaro R, Campanella S. Reward Sensitivity, Decisional Bias, and Metacognitive Deficits in Cocaine Drug Addiction. J Addict Med. 2014;8: 399–406. doi: 10.1097/ADM.0000000000000065 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Chen S, Yang P, Chen T, Su H, Jiang H, Zhao M. Risky decision-making in individuals with substance use disorder: A meta-analysis and meta-regression review. Psychopharmacology. 2020;237: 1893–1908. doi: 10.1007/s00213-020-05506-y [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Giorgetta C, Grecucci A, Zuanon S, Perini L, Balestrieri M, Bonini N, et al. Reduced Risk-Taking Behavior as a Trait Feature of Anxiety. Emotion. 2012;12: 1373–1383. doi: 10.1037/a0029119 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Paulus MP, Rogalsky C, Simmons A, Feinstein JS, Stein MB. Increased activation in the right insula during risk-taking decision making is related to harm avoidance and neuroticism. Neuroimage. 2003;19: 1439–1448. doi: 10.1016/s1053-8119(03)00251-9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Blakemore S-J. The social brain in adolescence. Nat Rev Neurosci. 2008;9: 267–277. doi: 10.1038/nrn2353 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Steinberg L. A social neuroscience perspective on adolescent risk-taking. Developmental review. 2008;28: 78–106. doi: 10.1016/j.dr.2007.08.002 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.King-Casas B, Chiu PH. Understanding Interpersonal Function in Psychiatric Illness Through Multiplayer Economic Games. Biol Psychiat. 2012;72: 119–125. doi: 10.1016/j.biopsych.2012.03.033 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Strickland JC, Smith MA. The Effects of Social Contact on Drug Use: Behavioral Mechanisms Controlling Drug Intake. Exp Clin Psychopharm. 2014;22: 23–34. doi: 10.1037/a0034669 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Zhang L, Gläscher J. A brain network supporting social influences in human decision-making. Sci Adv. 2020;6: eabb4159. doi: 10.1126/sciadv.abb4159 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Wang X, Wu Q, Egan L, Gu X, Liu P, Gu H, et al. Anterior insular cortex plays a critical role in interoceptive attention. eLife. 2019;8: e42265. doi: 10.7554/eLife.42265 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Loewenstein GF, Weber EU, Hsee CK, Welch N. Risk as feelings. Psychol Bull. 2001;127: 267. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.127.2.267 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.d’Acremont M, Bossaerts P. Neurobiological studies of risk assessment: A comparison of expected utility and mean-variance approaches. Cogn, Affect, Behav Neurosci. 2008;8: 363–374. doi: 10.3758/CABN.8.4.363 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Simonsen A, Fusaroli R, Petersen ML, Vermillet A-Q, Bliksted V, Mors O, et al. Taking others into account: combining directly experienced and indirect information in schizophrenia. Brain. 2021;144: 1603–1614. doi: 10.1093/brain/awab065 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Ruff CC, Fehr E. The neurobiology of rewards and values in social decision making. Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 2014;15: 549–562. doi: 10.1038/nrn3776 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Garvert MM, Moutoussis M, Kurth-Nelson Z, Behrens TEJ, Dolan RJ. Learning-Induced Plasticity in Medial Prefrontal Cortex Predicts Preference Malleability. Neuron. 2015;85: 418–428. doi: 10.1016/j.neuron.2014.12.033 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Cockrell JR, Folstein MF. Mini-Mental State Examination (MMSE). Psychopharmacology Bulletin. 1988;24: 689–692. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Rorden C, Karnath H-O, Bonilha L. Improving Lesion-Symptom Mapping. J Cognitive Neurosci. 2007;19: 1081–1088. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2007.19.7.1081 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Holt CA, Laury SK. Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects. Am Econ Rev. 2002;92: 1644–1655. doi: 10.1257/000282802762024700 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Gu X, Gao Z, Wang X, Liu X, Knight RT, Hof PR, et al. Anterior insular cortex is necessary for empathetic pain perception. Brain. 2012;135: 2726–2735. doi: 10.1093/brain/aws199 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Lin J-J, Chang C-H, Pal N. A Revisit to Contingency Table and Tests of Independence: Bootstrap is Preferred to Chi-Square Approximations as Well as Fisher’s Exact Test. J Biopharm Stat. 2013;25: 438–458. doi: 10.1080/10543406.2014.920851 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.R Core Team. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 64.Daw ND. Trial-by-trial data analysis using computational models. Decision making, affect, and learning: Attention and performance XXIII. 2011;23. [Google Scholar]
- 65.Stan Development Team. RStan: the R interface to Stan. 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 66.Hoffman MD, Gelman A. The No-U-Turn Sampler: Adaptively Setting Path Lengths in Hamiltonian Monte Carlo. Journal of Machine Learning Research. 2014; 1593–1623. [Google Scholar]
- 67.Carpenter B, Gelman A, Hoffman M, Lee D, Goodrich B, Betancourt M, et al. Stan: A Probabilistic Programming Language. Journal of Statistical Software. 2017;76. doi: 10.18637/jss.v076.i01 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.Gelman A, Rubin DB. Inference from Iterative Simulation Using Multiple Sequences. Stat Sci. 1992;7: 457–472. doi: 10.1214/ss/1177011136 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 69.Huys QJM, Eshel N, O’Nions E, Sheridan L, Dayan P, Roiser JP. Bonsai Trees in Your Head: How the Pavlovian System Sculpts Goal-Directed Choices by Pruning Decision Trees. Plos Comput Biol. 2012;8: e1002410. doi: 10.1371/journal.pcbi.1002410 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 70.Wilson RC, Collins AG. Ten simple rules for the computational modeling of behavioral data. Elife. 2019;8: e49547. doi: 10.7554/eLife.49547 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Supplementary Materials
Data Availability Statement
De-identified data and custom code are available on Virginia Tech GitLab (https://code.vt.edu/maorloff/insula-lesions-and-social-heuristic.git).