Skip to main content
EMBO Reports logoLink to EMBO Reports
editorial
. 2005 Feb;6(2):98–102. doi: 10.1038/sj.embor.7400339

Who wants to live forever?

Jayne C Lucke 1, Wayne Hall 1
PMCID: PMC1299249  PMID: 15689934

Summary

Real anti-ageing therapies may soon become reality. But, as yet, no one has asked the general public what they think about life extension


For millennia, human civilization has been fascinated with overcoming death. Immortality, eternal youth or at least the prospect of reaching biblical age have had a strong lure for religion, art and popular beliefs. Life after death, which is, in essence, eternal life, is the one central element of nearly all religions since Ancient Egypt. If we believe the Old Testament, some of the patriarchs lived for several hundreds of years. In the medieval ages, the fountain of youth was a popular myth, often illustrated in paintings, such as Lucas Cranach's The Fountain of Youth (Fig 1). And society today has not lost its fascination with immortality, as seen in Hollywood movies such as the Highlander films (1986–2000), The 6th Day (2000) or Indiana Jones and the Last Crusade (1989), and novels such as H. Rider Haggard's She. But for the first time, modern science may provide the knowledge and tools to interfere with the ageing processes and fulfil this age-old dream. This possibility has triggered an intense debate among scientists and ethicists about the potential of anti-ageing therapies and their ethical and social consequences. Given that anti-ageing therapies could dramatically change the social fabric of modern societies, it is quite astonishing that these debates have neglected the views of the larger public.

...intervening in the biological process of ageing is now discussed in the scientific literature as a real future possibility

Extending both the average and the maximum human lifespan even further will have immense social and political consequences

Figure 1.

Figure 1

Lucas Cranach d.f. “Der Jungbrunnen” (The Fountain of Youth) 1546, oil on canvas. Courtesy of Staatliche Museen zu Berlin—Preussischer Kulturbesitz, Gemäldegalerie. Photo by Jörg P. Anders.

The prospect of halting or at least slowing down the body's ageing processes is not so far-fetched. Several promising scientific developments may lead to interventions that could extend human life expectancy beyond the longest lifespan observed so far: 122 years, a record held by a French woman. Researchers are trying to use the enzyme telomerase to overcome the limit of somatic cell divisions to stop or slow cell senescence (Flanary, 2002; Hayflick, 2003). Others are searching for substances that mimic the effects of caloric restriction, which has been shown to extend the lifespan of mice by up to 30% (Ingram et al, 2004). The Human Genome Project has also provided new targets for pharmaceutical therapies that could slow ageing or prevent various age-related diseases (Guarente, 2003). On the basis of such developments, intervening in the biological process of ageing is now discussed in the scientific literature as a real future possibility (Aaron & Schwartz, 2004; de Grey et al, 2002a). As a result, scientists, ethicists and demographers have begun to consider the probable outcomes of life extension research. Some, such as the transhumanists, believe that humans may attain immortality in the near future and that this is a goal worth pursuing (Elliot, 2003). At the opposite end of the spectrum, critics of life extension research doubt that even small increases in the maximum human lifespan would be possible (Olshansky & Carnes, 2001) and argue that we should focus our efforts on increasing average lifespan instead.

In the absence of scientific evidence and experience, researchers have used mathematical models based on demographic trends to argue both for and against a theoretical maximum lifespan for humans, but there is no consensus on these predictions (Aaron & Harris, 2004). Although some models suggest that humans may be able to extend their maximum lifespan beyond the current limit of about 120 years (Vaupel et al, 1998; Vaupel, 2003), others argue that it will be difficult to achieve any gains in life expectancy in a long-lived population because human biology eventually puts a limit on the body's ability to carry on (Carnes et al, 2003; Olshansky & Carnes, 2001). In addition, it is not clear how broader societal contexts, such as developments in medicine and public health, will contribute to life expectancy (Carey, 2003). In fact, some researchers have observed a trend towards increasing maximum life-span among advanced societies (Oeppen & Vaupel, 2002). Medical advances during the past century and reduced childhood mortality, which takes away the pressure to produce progeny, are not only increasing the average but also pushing the maximum life expectancy, because our bodies adapt to this new environment by investing more resources into maintenance and longevity (Westendorp, 2004).

Citizens in the developed world can expect to live much longer than their ancestors a century ago, thanks to modern medicine, sanitation and improved food supplies. In Australia, for instance, life expectancy at birth has increased from 57 at the beginning of the 1900s to 80 in 2000. The population of people older than 80 years is the fastest growing group in the developed world and the worldwide number of people older than 65 years is projected to increase from 249 million in 2000 to 690 million in 2030 (Nass & Thorner, 2004). This is a new challenge for society, and already has a massive impact on national healthcare systems, retirement schemes and the global labour market. Extending both the average and the maximum human lifespan even further will have immense social and political consequences. Modelling has become an important tool for predicting the demographic, social and medical consequences of various life extension scenarios, but no model has yet achieved any reliable forecasts. Whereas the examination of past trends is straightforward, there are ongoing arguments about whether information about past populations can be used to forecast future scenarios, and differing interpretations of this data (Aaron & Schwartz, 2004; Carnes et al, 2003).

Scientists and demographers now predict various scenarios for the future of human ageing based on the ability of biomedical science to improve the body's capacity to maintain and repair itself. The most pessimistic scenario foresees prolonged senescence as an unintended consequence of our efforts to extend lifespan. There would be no increase in maximum life expectancy or quality of life; we would simply age over a longer time than we do now, as modern medicine is increasingly able to keep our bodies alive for longer. Compressed morbidity is another conservative scenario. By delaying the onset of chronic diseases that are associated with old age, this would increase average but not maximum lifespan. People would live longer and healthier lives within the existing maximum lifespan (Fries, 2003) and the result would be a society with more elderly people who are healthy and active up to the time of their death.

Decelerated ageing is a far more ambitious goal. It targets the fundamental processes of ageing to increase both average and maximum lifespan. Under this scenario, people would continue to age, but the process would occur over a longer period and they would have more active years before any decline became evident. Some proponents suggest that a mean life expectancy of around 112 years could be reached and that 90-year olds could be as healthy and active as are today's 50-year olds (Miller, 2002). The most radical scenario is arrested ageing—if we were able to reverse our bodies' ageing processes. Continuous repair of damage caused by basic metabolic processes and environmental factors would result in an indefinite maintenance of function and postponement of ageing, thus allowing people to grow several thousand years old (Post, 2004; de Grey et al, 2002a).

Pessimists doubt that research will ever be able to help us achieve any significant gains in maximum lifespan (Coles, 2004). Those who are more optimistic refrain from making predictions about life expectancy, but they embrace the potential for interventions in the ageing process to reduce the burden of age-related diseases and disorders (Olshansky & Carnes, 2001). More adventurous researchers believe that biomedical research will increasingly provide the tools to control the ageing process with the most optimistic ones suggesting the potential for 'negative senescence' or immortality (Elliot, 2003; Hall, 2003; Vaupel et al, 2004). However, most scientists and ethicists do not regard the possibility of immortality as a realistic outcome of current ageing research (Hall, 2003).

Strangely enough, what have not been heard in these debates are the voices of ordinary people and their attitudes towards life extension research—there are, so far, only assumptions that are not even based on sociological studies. Equally, the scientific community has not made any serious efforts to reach out to the general public. Some scientists have communicated their views on life extension research to a broader audience—various popular books describe the science and implications of life extension (Bova, 1998; Hall, 2003; Guarente, 2003; Olshansky & Carnes, 2001)—but these may not be enough to start a debate. Aubrey de Grey, a biogerontologist at the University of Cambridge, UK, has called for an open debate between scientists and the public to overcome public misperceptions about anti-ageing research and its social implications (de Grey et al, 2002b; de Grey, 2004; Juengst et al, 2003b).

...it is fair to assume that people will take a great interest in biomedical life extension technologies for several reasons...

This may indeed be necessary—some commentators fear that, as with any other new technology, the public could be misled to become gullible victims of unscrupulous 'life extension' entrepreneurs (Vincent, 2003). Others, however, have dismissed the call for an open debate because it would give charlatans an opportunity to promote their useless anti-ageing products (Le Bourg, 2002), which seemingly ignores the fact that there is already a thriving 'life extension industry' (de Grey, 2002). A third group of commentators suggests that people will not be interested in living forever, but will experience the 'wisdom of repugnance' (Turner, 2004b), although this is not supported by any evidence. de Grey also pointed to an apparent paradox: there is huge public interest in and willingness to pay for cosmetic and other interventions that delay at least the appearance of ageing; however, many bioethicists assume that the public will be reluctant to pursue life extension (de Grey, 2004). Again, there are no data on why or how many people hold such paradoxical views. Nevertheless, it is fair to assume that people will take a great interest in biomedical life extension technologies for several reasons, such as fear of death, fear of age-related disabilities and the dying process, and the pursuit of health in old age (Turner, 2004c). The prevalence of these beliefs has not been explored empirically. This neglect of the public's attitudes is astonishing, given that public interest can have far more influence on the direction and application of biomedical research than can scientific evidence (Walker, 2002). As Hall points out, although the initial public reaction to any new, ethically sensitive area of biomedicine is often revulsion or at least unease, public discussion often helps people to become more informed and comfortable with the new technology (Hall, 2003).

Similarly, the large amount of literature on the concept of 'quality of life' for people with disabilities (Schalock, 2004) and older people (Bowling et al, 2003; Kahana et al, 2002) is not reflected in the debate about life extension, which has resulted in unfounded arguments. Harris (2004), for example, suggests that people would be willing to exchange quality of life for longevity, whereas Gregory Stock claims that most people would prefer both a healthier and longer life (Stock, 2004). There is no empirical data to support either claim, but a recent study suggests that interest in prolonging life may depend on a person's health status. Using prospect theory, Winter and colleagues (2003) found that frail participants expressed a desire to prolong life under more debilitating conditions than did healthy people. These findings seem to indicate that the choices people make about life extension may change over time as their health status deteriorates.

The media are equally important players in shaping public opinion about these issues. Hall (2003) noted that under the guise of 'balance', media outlets often simply report the most extreme and competing views under a sensational headline rather than critically assessing competing arguments and discussing realistic possibilities. This type of media coverage may have important adverse effects on public policy when politicians respond to the furore raised by unbalanced reporting of extreme views. It arguably occurred, for example, in the stem-cell debate with the disproportionate media coverage given to a few maverick scientists and religious adherents who proposed cloning a human being. The media have already started to focus their attention on life extension research. Newspaper coverage in the UK of the publication of the first draft of the human genome focused on the prospects of longevity (Smart, 2003), with some journalists suggesting that advances in molecular bioscience would allow us to live forever. Others painted a less favourable picture of interminable old age; few gave serious consideration to the social, psychological and economic costs of increasing trends towards longer lives. This media ambivalence may mirror public opinion but again there is no empirical data to determine whether this is the case.

This neglect of the public's attitudes is astonishing, given that public interest can have far more influence on the direction and application of biomedical research than can scientific evidence

One of the few examples of research on public attitudes towards life extension suggests that it makes a lot of sense to survey the public. The International Longevity Center (New York, NY, USA) conducted a telephone survey of US adults that examined attitudes towards anti-ageing products (Harris Interactive Inc., 2003). It found that most people believe mistakenly that the US government regulates vitamins, minerals and food supplements because they assume that these products were approved by a government agency, such as the Food and Drug Administration, in much the same way as pharmaceuticals. Although more than half of the respondents said they had seen, heard or read something about anti-ageing medicine, the majority did not believe that taking vitamins or other supplements could prevent or halt the ageing process. Only 2% had had any personal experience with anti-ageing medicines or knew someone who had and most believed them to be beneficial. Although there is research on public beliefs about complementary and alternative therapies (Brownie & Myers, 2003; Willison & Andrews, 2004), there is, as yet, no coherent picture of public beliefs and attitudes towards real life extension strategies.

At the same time, there is a rapidly increasing demand for products that claim to delay ageing, now that the post-World-War II baby-boomer generation nears retirement age. The demand for anti-ageing products may indicate an obsession with living longer, but it may also be a fascination with appearing youthful or with health and fitness that is driving consumer interest. Until empirical evidence about these issues is available, it is hard to draw meaningful conclusions about public opinion. What is clear, however, is that this interest among a largely affluent generation of people has created a huge market for products, services and interventions that all claim to overcome the effects of ageing and even prolong life. Post (2004) estimated that by 2003 around 2,500 physicians in the USA had established practices that specialized in longevity medicine to cater for the elderly.

The Internet has further enhanced the ability of companies to meet this demand with a wide range of products and services (Turner, 2004a). Many companies and organizations now promote a vast array of anti-ageing products, but there is no scientific evidence that any of these interventions actually delay or reverse ageing. Most of these products target only the effects of the ageing process, rather than ageing itself, but consumers are not always aware of the difference. Given the increasing demand for anti-ageing therapies and products, there is a huge potential for consumer fraud and exploitation by companies that promote their anti-ageing products using unscientific and unsubstantiated claims (Dangour et al, 2004; Perls, 2004). Some have therefore argued that scientists have a responsibility to inform the public and present 'the real story' about anti-ageing interventions (Juengst et al, 2003a). But the question remains as to how effective such public education campaigns will be if the temptation for many journalists to sensationalize minor scientific discoveries seems irresistible (Turner, 2004a).

...the absence of empirical research on the community's acceptance of, and broader attitudes towards, different types of life extension technology is a crucial gap in this policy debate...

Growing old is not made easier by hucksters and charlatans who sell all kinds of products that claim to alleviate the ageing process or extend life expectancy. Conversely, biomedical research will probably provide new therapies and drugs that could ease the burden of growing old and enable longer lives, if the optimists have it right. Furthermore, the populations of developing countries already enjoy much longer average and maximum lifespans, which puts their social security systems under increasing pressure. These trends support calls for an open debate among scientists, politicians and the general public. However, the absence of empirical research on the community's acceptance of, and broader attitudes towards, different types of life extension technology is a crucial gap in this policy debate, and there is a pressing need for interdisciplinary research to examine public assumptions (Barzilai et al, 2004; Inui, 2003; Turner, 2004c; Wick, 2004). In the absence of better knowledge, critics and supporters just assume that the general populace will enthusiastically embrace or reject life extension technology—whatever suits their arguments best. There is insufficient evidence to support either claim. It is time that social scientists begin to collect some.

graphic file with name 6-7400339i1.jpg

graphic file with name 6-7400339i2.jpg

Acknowledgments

We thank S. Yeates for her editorial assistance and help with locating literature.

References

  1. Aaron HJ, Harris BH (2004) Our uncertain demographic future. In Aaron HJ, Schwartz WB (eds), Coping with Methuselah: The Impact of Molecular Biology on Medicine and Society. Brookings Institution Press, Washington, DC, USA [Google Scholar]
  2. Aaron HJ, Schwartz WB (eds) (2004) Coping with Methuselah: The Impact of Molecular Biology on Medicine and Society. Brookings Institution Press, Washington, DC, USA [Google Scholar]
  3. Barzilai N, Rossetti L, Lipton RB (2004) Einstein's Institute for Aging Research: collaborative and programmatic approaches in the search for successful aging. Exp Gerontol 39: 151–157 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  4. Bova B (1998) Immortality: How Science is Extending Your Life Span—And Changing the World. Avon Books, New York, NY, USA [Google Scholar]
  5. Bowling A, Gabriel Z, Dykes J, Dowding LM, Evans O, Fleissig A, Banister D, Sutton S (2003) Let's ask them: a national survey of definitions of quality of life and its enhancement among people aged 65 and over. Int J Aging Hum Dev 56: 269–306 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  6. Brownie S, Myers S (2003) Dietary and health supplement use among older Australians: results from a national survey. Australasian J Ageing 22: 171–178 [Google Scholar]
  7. Carey JR (2003) Life span: a conceptual overview. Popul Dev Rev 29: S1–S18 [Google Scholar]
  8. Carnes BA, Olshansky SJ, Grahn D (2003) Biological evidence for limits to the duration of life. Biogerontology 4: 31–45 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Coles LS (2004) Demography of human supercentenarians. J Gerontol A Biol Sci Med Sci 59: B579–B586 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Dangour AD, Sibson VL, Fletcher AE (2004) Micronutrient supplementation in later life: limited evidence for benefit. J Gerontol A Biol Sci Med Sci 59: 659–673 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. de Grey AD (2002) Fear of misrepresentation cannot justify silence about foreseeable life-extension biotechnology. Bioessays 25: 94–95 [Google Scholar]
  12. de Grey AD (2004) Biogerontologists' duty to discuss timescales publicly. Ann NY Acad Sci 1019: 542–545 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. de Grey AD, Ames BN, Andersen JK, Bartke A, Campisi J, Heward CB, McCarter RJ, Stock G (2002a) Time to talk SENS: critiquing the immutability of human aging. Ann NY Acad Sci 959: 452–462 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  14. de Grey AD, Baynes JW, Berd D, Heward CB, Pawelec G, Stock G (2002b) Is human aging still mysterious enough to be left only to scientists? Bioessays 24: 667–676 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Elliot C (2003) Humanity 2.0. Wilson Quart Autumn: 13–20 [Google Scholar]
  16. Flanary B (2002) The quest to extend life and overcome aging and death: past, present, and future attempts. J Anti Aging Med 5: 161–172 [Google Scholar]
  17. Fries JF (2003) Measuring and monitoring success in compressing morbidity. Ann Intern Med 139: 455–459 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Guarente L (2003) Ageless Quest: One Scientist's Search for Genes that Prolong Youth. Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press, New York, NY, USA [Google Scholar]
  19. Hall SS (2003) Merchants of Immortality: Chasing the Dream of Human Life Extension. Houghton Mifflin, New York, NY, USA [Google Scholar]
  20. Harris Interactive Inc. (2003) Anti-aging medicine, vitamins, minerals and food supplements: a public opinion survey conducted for the International Longevity Center. J Anti Aging Med 6: 83–90 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  21. Harris J (2004) Immortal ethics. Ann NY Acad Sci 1019: 527–534 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Hayflick L (2003) Living forever and dying in the attempt. Exp Gerontol 38: 1231–1241 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  23. Ingram DK, Anson RM, De Cabo R, Mamczarz J, Zhu M, Mattison JA, Lane MA, Roth GS (2004) Development of calorie restriction mimetics as a prolongevity strategy. Ann NY Acad Sci 1019: 412–423 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Inui TS (2003) The need for an integrated biopsychosocial approach to research on successful aging. Ann Intern Med 139: 391–394 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Juengst ET, Binstock RH, Mehlman M, Post SG, Whitehouse P (2003a) Biogerontology, “anti-aging medicine,” and the challenges of human enhancement. Hastings Cent Rep 33: 21–30 [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Juengst ET, Binstock RH, Mehlman MJ, Post SG (2003b) Antiaging research and the need for public dialogue. Science 299: 1323. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Kahana E, Lawrence RH, Kahana B, Kercher K, Wisniewski A, Stoller E, Tobin J, Stange K (2002) Long-term impact of preventive proactivity on quality of life of the old-old. Psychosom Med 64: 382–394 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  28. Le Bourg E (2002) A public debate about the feasibility of reversing human ageing could be detrimental. Bioessays 25: 93–94 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  29. Miller RA (2002) Extending life: scientific prospects and political obstacles. Milbank Quart 80: 155–174 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  30. Nass R, Thorner MO (2004) Life extension versus improving quality of life. Best Pract Res Clin Endocrinol Metab 18: 381–391 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  31. Oeppen J, Vaupel JW (2002) Broken limits to life expectancy. Science 296: 1029–1031 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Olshansky SJ, Carnes BA (2001) The Quest for Immortality: Science at the Frontiers of Aging. Norton & Co, New York, NY, USA [Google Scholar]
  33. Perls TT (2004) Anti-aging quackery: human growth hormone and tricks of the trade—more dangerous than ever. J Gerontol A Biol Sci Med Sci 59: 682–691 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Post SG (ed.) (2004) Encyclopedia of Bioethics. Macmillan, New York, NY, USA [Google Scholar]
  35. Schalock RL (2004) The concept of quality of life: what we know and do not know. J Intellect Disabil Res 48: 203–216 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Smart A (2003) Reporting the dawn of the post-genomic era: who wants to live forever? Sociol Health Illn 25: 24–29 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Stock GB (2004) The pitfalls of planning for demographic change. Ann NY Acad Sci 1019: 546–551 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Turner L (2004a) Biotechnology, bioethics and anti-aging interventions. Trends Biotechnol 22: 219–221 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  39. Turner L (2004b) Is repugnance wise? Visceral responses to biotechnology. Nat Biotechnol 22: 269–270 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. Turner L (2004c) Life extension research: health, illness, and death. Health Care Anal 12: 117–129 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Vaupel JW (2003) The future of human longevity—how important are markets and innovation? Sci Aging Knowl Environ 26: 18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  42. Vaupel JW et al. (1998) Biodemographic trajectories of longevity. Science 280: 855–860 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  43. Vaupel JW, Baudisch A, Dolling MA, Roach D, Gampe J (2004) The case for negative senescence. Theor Popul Biol 65: 339–351 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Vincent J (2003) What is at stake in the 'war on anti-ageing medicine'? Ageing Soc 23: 675–684 [Google Scholar]
  45. Walker RF (2002) Anti-aging medicine: collecting data or collecting fees? J Anti Aging Med 5: 243–246 [Google Scholar]
  46. Westendorp RG (2004) Are we becoming less disposable? EMBO Rep 5: 2–6 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  47. Wick G (2004) Gerontology and the issue of transdisciplinary research. Exp Gerontol 39: 1 [Google Scholar]
  48. Willison KD, Andrews GJ (2004) Complementary medicine and older people: past research and future directions. Complement Ther Nurs Midwifery 10: 80–91 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Winter L, Lawton MP, Ruckdeschel K (2003) Preferences for prolonging life: a prospect theory approach. Int J Aging Hum Dev 56: 155–170 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from EMBO Reports are provided here courtesy of Nature Publishing Group

RESOURCES