Skip to main content
American Journal of Public Health logoLink to American Journal of Public Health
. 2005 Jan;95(1):35–41. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.2003.025734

Community Involvement in Developing Policies for Genetic Testing: Assessing the Interests and Experiences of Individuals Affected by Genetic Conditions

Sarah E Gollust 1, Kira Apse 1, Barbara P Fuller 1, Paul Steven Miller 1, Barbara B Biesecker 1
PMCID: PMC1449847  PMID: 15623855

Abstract

Because the introduction of genetic testing into clinical medicine and public health creates concerns for the welfare of individuals affected with genetic conditions, those individuals should have a role in policy decisions about testing. Mechanisms for promoting participation range from membership on advisory committees to community dialogues to surveys that provide evidence for supporting practice guidelines.

Surveys can assess the attitudes and the experiences of members of an affected group and thus inform discussions about that community’s concerns regarding the appropriate use of a genetic test. Results of a survey of individuals affected with inherited dwarfism show how data can be used in policy and clinical-practice contexts.

Future research of affected communities’ interests should be pursued so that underrepresented voices can be heard.


Scholars increasingly argue that the public should participate in policymaking decisions, particularly policies related to health,1 because the public has a huge stake in health policy: it is likely to both reap the benefits and pay the costs.2 Public involvement also realizes the goals of a participatory democracy3 and may create more representative and accountable policies.4 Furthermore, involving the public may foster community engagement and may eliminate exclusion or elitism on the part of policymakers.1,5 Values are often involved in health-related policy decisions that both the public and the “experts” can deliberate.6,7

Mechanisms for engaging the public in specific policymaking activities have become common and have been employed in the United Kingdom,4,8,9 Canada,10 and most notably the United States during the priority-setting experience in Oregon.11 While there are many possible methods for engaging the public, these mechanisms have not been adequately evaluated. There are still conceptual problems with articulating the goals of public participation, with defining the relevant “publics,” and with using public attitudes to inform policy decisions.12–14

Including public perspectives is similarly important, but no less problematic, to establishing public health policy about genetic testing.15–17 Screening-policy guidelines describe “acceptability to the population” as one important criterion for assessing the appropriateness of a screening program, along with considerations about the impact of the condition, the cost-effectiveness, and the validity and reliability of the test.18,19 Burris and Gostin emphasize “acceptability to the population” as 1 of 3 ethical principles for deciding whether a genetic test should be used in a public health screening program.20

Childress et al. consider public participation, including that of “affected parties,” an important moral consideration for public health.21 Indeed, involving and engaging the relevant communities has proved to be essential for good screening-program outcomes, as the carrier screening for sickle cell anemia and the more successful screening for Tay–Sachs disease during the 1970s made evident.22

Community input can have value throughout the process of developing a genetic test for clinical and public health applications. For example, particular communities can be involved in mobilizing the initial genetics research that may lead to a test.23 Additionally, an assessment of a community’s attitudes toward a genetic test may elucidate the ethical acceptability of making that test available. Moreover, an empirical assessment of community demand may suggest how profitable a given commercial test might be, which is of importance to the laboratories that may consider offering such a test. Finally, once a test becomes available, community interest and concerns may shape practice guidelines that surround the incorporation of that test into routine clinical care.

We review reasons why affected community member concerns about genetic tests in general and prenatal tests in particular are especially salient, and it describes some methods for including these perspectives in the development of genetics policy. As an example of research that can be applied to policy, we discuss our survey that assessed the attitudes of a sample of individuals who have achondroplasia—the most common type of dwarfism—toward prenatal testing for this condition.

Including Public Perspectives in Genetics Policy

As new genetic tests are introduced into public health and medical practice, there are many medical, scientific, ethical, legal, and social concerns that must be considered.24,25 Predictive genetic testing for adult-onset diseases raises concerns about (1) screening in the absence of effective interventions, (2) the ethical acceptability of screening children,26 and (3) the prospect of complicated decisionmaking and counseling.27 Carrier testing raises concerns about reproductive decisionmaking and psychological effects.28 Any genetic test will invoke complex considerations about privacy, confidentiality, and familial implications29 in the context of information that is challenging to both communicate and understand.30 Prenatal genetic testing raises additional questions: To whom should specific prenatal tests be offered—those who have the condition, those who have a family history of the condition, or the general public? What kind of information and counseling should be available to consumers of prenatal tests? What are the implications of prenatal testing for individuals who have disabilities, and how should their views influence clinical practice? Potential consumers of genetic services, especially those consumers who are affected by genetic conditions, may provide useful guidance about any of these policy issues.31–33

The role of community concerns in genetics research.

The notion that community perspectives should be given special attention in genetics research is the result of research findings within the last decade. In response to research that indicated Ashkenazi Jews have a higher carrier frequency of genes that predispose them to breast and ovarian cancer34 and colorectal cancer,35 Weijer suggested that “respect for communities” should be considered as an ethical principle when evaluating human-subjects research.36 Genetics research introduces novel concerns for communities, notably the potential for stigmatization and discrimination of certain groups on the basis of genetic findings,37–39 which suggests a role for community review or community consent when evaluating genetics research.40–44

“Affected community” concerns.

While community can evoke a range of group characteristics,36 our discussion is focused on the involvement of communities affected by genetic conditions. There are fundamental conceptual challenges associated with defining the community,45 the legitimacy of community representation,43 and deciding which community voices should be solicited—those who have a given condition, those who have a family history of a given condition, or representatives of the general public. Affected individuals who are coping with and adapting to their condition often describe their condition as less serious, and their own quality of life as better, than unaffected individuals perceive it to be.46–49 This phenomenon reflects the ability that affected individuals have to view their condition more favorably in their adaptation to its negative consequences on their lives. Recognition of this bias has resulted in the claim that affected individuals are unable to judge their condition from an objective perspective that is needed to assess public health priorities.50 However, the general public and health care providers may be negatively prejudiced against those who have disabilities; they may overestimate the impact of having a disability because they do not have the condition themselves.51,52 One way to counter any discrimination is to involve underrepresented individuals in the policymaking process.

Affected individuals should be involved not only to counteract discriminatory attitudes but also to share valuable experiences and perspectives that can inform specific policy decisions. The history of the AIDS and breast cancer advocacy movements in the United States shows the critical role that members of affected community groups can play in developing health policy.53,54 These groups have helped to shape policies about clinical trials and consent, access to drugs, and research-funding decisions. Similarly, the expertise of individuals who have genetic conditions can provide critical contributions to genetics-related policies. Affected individuals may be well-equipped by virtue of their experiences to assess the educational and counseling needs of clients who seek genetic testing and thereby provide vital information for shaping policy.55

Disability implications of prenatal genetic testing.

Prenatal genetic testing elicits special concerns for individuals who have genetic conditions. These individuals may perceive the availability of prenatal genetic testing as evidence of pervasive negative attitudes toward life with a disability, because termination of affected fetuses remains the predominant option when a condition is detected.56 Furthermore, affected individuals may believe that health care professionals overemphasize impairment rather than social factors as the defining characteristic of disability and therefore promote eugenic outcomes through their endorsement of prenatal testing.50,57 There is a diversity of views about prenatal testing among the general public, genetic professionals, bioethicists, and disability communities.58 However, there has been little representation of the disabled community’s opinions when developing genetics-related policy about use of prenatal testing.50 As Tom Shakespeare—a sociologist who has achondroplasia—said, “If we are to understand the implications of impairment, and make appropriate decisions about individual and societal screening options, then we need to listen to those people directly affected by genetic conditions . . . Disabled people are not consulted on matters which affect us: professionals, unrepresentative charities, and governments, all make decisions about disability, without considering that the best experts on life as a disabled person are disabled people themselves.”50(p673) Shakespeare concluded that research into the views of disabled individuals and greater participation of the disability community during the policymaking process are important future priorities.

The Public and the Genetics Policymaking Process

There are a range of levels of public participation that can be pursued, from information exchange to consultation to decisionmaking authority.6,12 Recent research has focused on the merits of deliberative methods.59,60 Scholars have outlined at least 8 different mechanisms6: voting on particular referenda, public hearings, attitude and opinion surveys,61 negotiated rule making, consensus conferences,62 citizens panels, advisory committees, and focus groups. However, there has been limited empirical evidence to evaluate which of these mechanisms is best for a given policy situation.6 The following describes ways in which some of these mechanisms have been used for genetics policy considerations.

Consultation with, and membership in, policymaking groups.

Public participation was a priority of the former US Department of Health and Human Services Secretary’s Advisory Committee for Genetic Testing, which launched a public consultation effort through targeted mailings, web consultation, and public meetings to hear public perspectives about the oversight of genetic tests.63,64 The active Secretary’s Advisory Committee for Genetics, Health, and Society also seeks public comment. Layperson membership on an advisory committee is another way to achieve a public representation in the policymaking process. However, consumers may be underrepresented on advisory committees that consider genetics-related issues. Of the 73 individuals Ard and Natowicz identified on advisory committees responsible for genetics policy documents created between 1990 and 1995, only 8 were members of the lay public,65 and only 26 of 51 state newborn-screening programs identified in 1995 had consumer representatives on their advisory committees.66 Public representatives on advisory committees are necessary, but this mechanism may not be sufficient because members do not represent a plurality of views, and disability perspectives are unlikely to be adequately represented. Furthermore, these groups are often politically driven, and the members are appointed to represent particular perspectives. These factors limit the effectiveness of this type of participation.

Patient advocacy groups.

These groups and the professional societies that represent consumer groups67 can play a role in promoting the interests of greater numbers of people. One such group is the Little People of America (LPA), a nonprofit support organization that represents individuals who have short stature and their families, including those who have achondroplasia. In 1996, after the development of the genetic test for achondroplasia, the LPA issued a policy statement about genetic discoveries.68 The statement acknowledged the existence of a range of opinions about the appropriate use of the prenatal test, but the LPA evoked a community concern that the prenatal test might be used by all expectant mothers and thereby potentially reduce the number of babies who are born with dwarfism. Policy statements such as this one aim to communicate a collective informed opinion so that voices of the community can be heard. However, these efforts are limited to the contributions of active members of the organization and cannot be generalized to everyone who has a particular condition.

Collaborative efforts.

Policy recommendations also can be created through deliberative efforts with public representatives. For example, the New England Regional Genetics Group (NERGG) produced a “joint consumer-provider document” that outlined optimal genetics services for its region.69 This group of professionals and 4 consumer members held 3 focus groups with consumers. They incorporated the results of these focus groups into the final document, Optimizing Genetics Services in a Social, Ethical, and Policy Context.69 A different approach to engaging the public has been used in Michigan and Alabama.70 The Communities of Color and Genetics Policy Project used community dialogues in cities throughout these 2 states to gather information about the values and the policy recommendations of communities of color. Recommendations covered the areas of trust/distrust, education, privacy, genetic testing, access to genetic testing, genetic research, and concepts about “playing God.”71 The Partnership for Genetic Services Pilot Program, which is affiliated with the Genetic Alliance, is a creative collaborative approach to engaging physicians and medical students around genetics issues. The program introduces families and individuals who have genetic conditions to these medical professionals as a way to expose the professionals to some of the social and quality-of-life issues these individuals and families experience.72 Other Alliance-organized programs are the Consumer Voices Network and the Consumer Indicators of Quality Genetic Services, a program that uses focus groups with consumers to develop a set of consumer priorities for genetic service delivery. These labor-intensive methods, which likely influence local policies and practice, are often confined to particular geographic areas and the demographics of the populations involved. National use of focus groups, while more representative, introduces additional time and costs.

Survey research.

All of the aforementioned approaches promote public involvement in the development of genetics-related policies and should continue to be pursued. Additionally, carefully designed surveys can represent the opinions of large numbers of affected individuals and can play a role in communicating the views of particular communities about genetic testing. Survey data provide broader representation of community views than representatives of advisory committees, advocacy groups, or those involved in collaborative policy discussions do—many views can be assessed, not just the views of those who are the “loudest” or the most politically powerful. While surveys may represent a more inclusive way to assess community attitudes toward a particular test, they are not a substitute for more deliberative public debates.6

Surveys have been conducted to assess community attitudes toward prenatal testing and reproductive decisionmaking within communities of family members, patients, or both who have genetic conditions, including cystic fibrosis,55,73 Parkinson’s disease,74 Huntington’s disease,75 neurofibromatosis,76 hereditary deafness,77,78 bipolar disorder,79 Charcot–Marie–Tooth syndrome,80 retinitis pigmentosa,81 Alport syndrome,82 and hereditary ataxia.83 Results from these and similar studies should be routinely considered when developing evidence-based clinical-practice guidelines. These data will allow for the prediction of the potential use of genetic testing and whether genetic testing or prenatal diagnosis is a valuable option for patients and families who have experience with a given condition. Data also may help to assess the counseling and educational needs for others who know less about living with one of these conditions. Such information also is important for professional societies, such as the American Society of Human Genetics84,85 or the American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists,86 to consider when developing practice guidelines about the implementation of particular genetic or reproductive technologies into public health and clinical practice.

Attitudes of Individuals With Achondroplasia

Shortly after the 1994 discovery of the genetic mutation that causes achondroplasia, prenatal testing for the condition became available. This relatively simple test could be particularly useful for couples wherein both individuals have achondroplasia. These couples have a 25% risk for having a child who has homozygous achondroplasia, a condition that is fatal within the first months of life.87 Within the community of adults who have achondroplasia, it is not uncommon for affected individuals to marry and have children and thus face this risk. Prenatal testing allows parents to consider termination of an affected fetus. The research team that discovered the point mutation responsible for achondroplasia predicted that prenatal diagnosis would become relatively facile; however, these researchers, seemingly wary of the implications of identifying fetuses that have achondroplasia in the general population, stated that any use of the prenatal test “other than for the screening of at-risk pregnancies” should be “prohibited.”88(p341)

In response to this discovery, we administered a survey to (1) assess the level of awareness of and interest in prenatal genetic testing for achondroplasia, (2) assess attitudes toward population use of the test, (3) identify factors associated with intentions to undergo prenatal genetic testing, and (4) assess the quality of life, self-esteem, and perception of the condition among individuals who have achondroplasia and the parents and siblings of those affected.89,90 The study population consisted of 189 individuals who had achondroplasia and 136 first-degree relatives. The goal of the research was to explore the needs and concerns of the individuals who are most likely to use prenatal testing and who are likely to have an informed opinion about the broader applications of the test. Additionally, the quality-of-life results can be used to help genetics professionals and policymakers consider whether the impact of achondroplasia on the life of affected individuals justifies population screening of pregnancies. Finally, the research can help genetics professionals and policy-makers understand the educational and counseling needs of other potential users of the test.

Our study results were limited by a low response rate and an ethnically homogenous sample. However, the study suggested that most participants were aware of the availability of prenatal testing, although less than 10% had used it.90 While 87% of the 325 respondents would support the use of prenatal screening by affected parents at risk for carrying a fetus that has homozygous achondroplasia, only 29% would support populationwide prenatal screening for achondroplasia.91 Overall, neither affected individuals nor relatives were interested in using the test to terminate pregnancies on the basis of a diagnosis of achondroplasia or average stature, but they would use the test to diagnose homozygous achondroplasia.90 Individuals’ perception of the condition was related to their attitudes toward screening, with those individuals who judged the condition as more severe being more likely to agree that the prenatal test for achondroplasia should be available for general population use.91 Individuals who had lower quality of life were more likely to support the use of prenatal testing by affected individuals. While our data suggest that practice guidelines should endorse making prenatal testing for homozygous achondroplasia generally available to couples who have achondroplasia, the variation in views and experiences among our sample suggest conflict with populationwide prenatal screening for achondroplasia. Policies that support improving the quality of life for people who have achondroplasia are more in keeping with the survey results than are practice guidelines that endorse population screening for the condition.

One Community, Many Experiences

Our data suggest that to speak of any single achondroplasia view toward prenatal testing would be inaccurate. Like any heterogeneous group, individuals who have achondroplasia experience a range in their quality of life and have differing views about prenatal genetic testing. The data support a concept Shakespeare described, which reinforces the value of eliciting the interests of affected individuals: “Disabled individuals will have different views on genetics, depending on their own experiences and outlooks: some will welcome screening, because of the suffering they have personally experienced. Others will oppose screening, because it is very difficult to support a practice which would have prevented one’s own existence. It is important . . . to develop rational arguments about the value of disabled people’s lives and their views, which are likely to be varied and reflective.”50(p674)

Individuals who experience greater difficulty in their lives because of a condition may be more supportive of the use of prenatal testing for their condition by other future parents. Variability in the experiences of individuals who have disabilities creates variable perspectives toward use of prenatal testing, which is a fact policymakers must recognize. As Davis said in describing another heterogeneous community, “One cannot speak quickly about inviting participation from ‘the deaf community’ without taking seriously its many facets.”43(p42) The same is true of the achondroplasia community and their many perspectives toward genetic testing: there is no single achondroplasia view toward testing that may be captured by a single policy statement or by a representative of the community. Moreover, the concerns of individuals who have achondroplasia will not be representative of the concerns of other groups that have genetic conditions of varying severity and complexity. While our study illuminates the ways in which survey data can provide evidence about the range of attitudes toward genetic testing within one particular community, other communities will have different attitudes, issues, and perspectives that researchers must assess before developing policies relevant to those communities.

Capturing a Spectrum of Community Perspectives

Because of the challenges inherent in defining a community and describing its views, methods for assessing affected community attitudes must be thoughtfully pursued. To elicit generalizable findings, studies should strive to include large samples and to aim for high participation rates. Data about the quality of life of individuals who have genetic conditions and their interests related to genetic testing should be used to inform policy decisions. Policies, such as clinical-practice guidelines, should not be based on potentially erroneous assumptions about how populations would use genetic testing. For example, in our study population, few affected individuals would use prenatal testing to terminate normal pregnancies, despite common assumptions to the contrary.92 Such data is imperative when developing guidelines about which individuals should be offered prenatal genetic testing.

Research findings also could be used to better inform clinical practice. The type of information clinicians provide to parents who are considering prenatal testing is likely to shape their reproductive decisions.93–97 Providers should offer information about the quality of life of affected individuals to couples who are considering prenatal screening. The information provided to parents about prenatal tests should be based on evidence94 and should reflect data obtained from affected individuals and parents and others who have experience with the condition. Quality-of-life data may better inform providers and avoid reliance on misguided assumptions or anecdotal evidence about what having a genetic condition is like. Asch has called for a consistent educational approach in the prenatal context: “Everyone obtaining testing or seeking information about genetic or prenatally diagnosable disability [should] receive sufficient information about predictable difficulties, supports, and life events associated with a disabling condition. Such information . . . should include, at a minimum, a detailed description of the biological, cognitive, or psychological impairments associated with specific disabilities, and what those impairments imply for day-to-day function.”57(p1655)

Empirical descriptions of affected individuals’ quality of life—elicited from participatory research mechanisms—should be the first step toward the degree of comprehensive educational information that Asch demands. Evidence-based educational information is especially important because of the marketing pressures98 and the social and clinical pressures99 to pursue testing that individuals may experience.

Balanced data that represent the perspectives of individuals who have genetic conditions can guide policy decisions and also can contribute to making health care providers and the general public more informed about the variable experiences of affected individuals. Survey research and other participatory mechanisms, such as membership on advisory committees, policy statements by advocacy groups, and collaborative policy efforts, should be pursued so that affected individuals’ voices will be considered during policy development. Finally, there is a concurrent need for additional conceptual analyses to clarify which communities should be included and how to balance their contributions with competing policy considerations.

Acknowledgments

The survey described in this article was administered within an intramural National Human Genome Research Institute protocol (#96-HG-0123).

Human Participant Protection…The survey was approved by the institutional review board of the National Human Genome Research Institute.The study also was reviewed and was approved by the medical advisory board of the Little People of America.

Note. This article represents the views of the authors and not necessarily those of the National Human Genome Research Institute, the National Institutes of Health, the US Department of Health and Human Services, or the US Equal Employment Opportunity Commission.

Contributors…S. E. Gollust led the research, analysis, and writing of the article. K. Apse helped originate the article, contributed to the initial writing, and reviewed all drafts. B. P. Fuller and P. S. Miller provided policy expertise and reviewed drafts. B. B. Biesecker originated this article and the associated empirical studies and assisted with all aspects of the writing.

Peer Reviewed

References

  • 1.Morone JA, Kilbreth EH. Power to the people? Restoring citizen participation. J Health Polit, Policy, Law. 2003; 28:271–288. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.analysis Laird FN. Participatory, democracy, and technological decision-making. Sci Technol Hum Values. 1993; 18(3):341–361. [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Morone JA. The Democratic Wish. New Haven, Conn: Yale University Press; 1998.
  • 4.Litva A, Coast J, Donovan J, et al. “The public is too subjective”: public involvement at different levels of health-care decision making. Soc Sci Med. 2002;54:1825–1837. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Goggin ML. The life sciences and the public: is science too important to be left to the scientist? Polit Life Sci. 1984;3:28–75. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Rowe G, Frewer LJ. Public participation methods: a framework for evaluation. Sci Technol Hum Values. 2000;25: 3–29. [Google Scholar]
  • 7.DeSario J, Langton S. Citizen participation and technocracy. In: DeSario J, Langton S, eds. Citizen Participation in Public Decision Making. Westport, Conn: Greenwood Press; 1987.
  • 8.Bowie C, Richardson A, Sykes W. Consulting the public about health service priorities. BMJ. 1995;311:1155–1158. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Quennell P. Getting their say, or getting their way? Has participation strengthened the patient “voice” in the National Institute for Clinical Excellence? J Manag Med. 2001;15:202–219. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Martin DK, Abelson J, Singer PA. Participation in health care priority-setting through the eyes of the participants. J Health Serv Res Policy. 2002;7: 222–229. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Hadorn DC. The Oregon priority-setting exercise: quality of life and public policy. Hastings Cent Rep. 1991;21: S11–S16. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Charles C, DeMaio S. Lay participation in health care decision making: a conceptual framework. J Health Polit Policy Law. 1993;18:881–904. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Barnes M, Newman J, Knops A, Sullivan H. Constituting “the public” in public participation. Public Adm. 2003; 81:379–399. [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Ubel PA. The challenge of measuring community values in ways appropriate for setting health care priorities. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1999;9:263–284. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Garl and MJ. Experts and the public: a needed partnership for genetic policy. Public Underst Sci. 1999;8:241–254. [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Kerr A, Cunningham-Burley S, Amos A. The new genetics and health: mobilizing lay expertise. Public Underst Sci. 1998;7:41–60. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Schibeci R, Barns I, Shaw R, Davison A. Genetic medicine: an experiment in community-expert interaction. J Med Ethics. 1999;25:335–339. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Wilson J, Jungner G. Principles and Practice of Screening for Disease. Geneva, Switzerland: World Health Organization; 1968.
  • 19.Troop P. Screening: general principles. In: Bradley P, Burls A, eds. Ethics in Public and Community Health. London, England: Routledge; 2000:81–93.
  • 20.Burris S, Gostin LO. Genetic screening from a public health perspective: three “ethical” principles. In: Burley J, Harris J, eds. A Companion to GenEthics. Malden, Mass, and Oxford, UK: Black-well Publications; 2002:455–464.
  • 21.Childress JF, Faden RR, Gaare RD, et al. Public health ethics: mapping the terrain. J Law Med Ethics. 2002;30: 170–178. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Roberts L. One worked; the other didn’t. Science. 1990;247:18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Terry SF, Boyd CD. Researching the biology of PXE: partnering in the process. Am J Med Genet. 2001;106: 177–184. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Gerard S, Hayes M, Rothstein MA. On the edge of tomorrow: fitting genomics into public health policy. J Law Med Ethics. 2002;30(suppl 3):173–176. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Ethical Clayton EW., legal, and social implications of genomic medicine. N Engl J Med. 2003;349:562–569. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26.Nelson RM, Botkin JR, Kodish ED, et al. Ethical issues with genetic testing in pediatrics. Pediatrics. 2001;107: 1451–1455. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Lloyd FJ, Reyna VF, Whalen P. Accuracy and ambiguity in counseling patients about genetic risk. Arch Intern Med. 2001;161:2411–2413. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Marteau TM, Anionwu E. Evaluating carrier testing: objectives and outcomes. In: Marteau TM, Richards M, eds. The Troubled Helix: Social and Psychological Implications of the New Human Genetics. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press; 1996:123–139.
  • 29.Juengst ET. Caught in the middle again: professional ethical considerations in genetic testing for health risks. Genet Testing. 98 1997;1:189–200. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Khoury MJ, Thrasher JF, Burke W, Gettig EA, Fridinger F, Jackson R. Challenges in communicating genetics: a public health approach. Genet Med. 2000;2: 198–202. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Foster MW, Eisenbraun AJ, Carter TH. Genetic screening of targeted sub-populations: the role of communal discourse in evaluating sociocultural implications. Genet Testing. 1997;1: 269–274. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Wertz D. Drawing lines: notes for policymakers. In: Parens E, Asch A, eds. Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press; 2000:261–287.
  • 33.Wilfond BS. Screening policy for cystic fibrosis: the role of evidence. Hastings Cent Rep. 1995;25:S21–S23. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Struewing JP, Abeliovich D, Peretz T, et al. The carrier frequency of the BRCA1 185delAG mutation is approximately 1 percent in Ashkenazi Jewish individuals. Nat Genet. 1995;11: 198–200. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Laken SJ, Petersen GM, Gruber SB, et al. Familial colorectal cancer in Ashkenazim due to a hypermutable tract in APC. Nat Genet. 1997;17:79–83. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36.philosophical Weijer C. Protecting communities in research: and pragmatic challenges. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 1999;8:501–513. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Clayton EW. The complex relationship of genetics, groups, and health: what it means for public health. J Law Med Ethics. 2002;30:290–297. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38.Jews Levin M. Screening and genes: a consideration of the ethics of genetic screening within the Jewish community: challenges and responses. Genet Testing. 1999;3:207–213. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Lehrman S. Jewish leaders seek genetic guidelines. Nature. 1997;389: 322. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Foster MW, Sharp RR. Genetic research and culturally specific risks: one size does not fit all. Trends Genet. 2000; 16:93–95. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Foster MW, Sharp RR, Freeman WL, Chino M, Bernsten D, Carter TH. The role of community review in evaluating the risks of human genetic variation research. Am J Hum Genet. 1999;64: 1719–1727. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 42.can Juengst ET. Commentary: what “community review” and cannot do. J Law Med Ethics. 2000;28:52–54.11067633 [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Groups Davis DS., communities, and contested identities in genetic research. Hastings Cent Rep. 2000;30: 38–45. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.confusing Juengst ET. Groups as gatekeepers to genomic research: conceptually, morally hazardous, and practically useless. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 1998; 8:183–200. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Weijer C, Goldsand G, Emanuel EJ. Protecting communities in research: current guidelines and limits of extrapolation. Nat Genet. 1999;23:275–280. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 46.value Ubel PA. Societal, the person trade-off, and the dilemma of whose values to measure for cost-effectiveness analysis. Health Econ. 2000;9:127–136. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Albrecht GL, Devlieger PJ. The disability paradox: high quality of life against all odds. Soc Sci Med. 1999;48: 977–988. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Dolan P. The effect of experience of illness on health state valuations. J Clin Epidemiol. 1996;49:551–564. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Froberg DG, Kane RL. Methodology for measuring health-state preferences III: population and context effects. J Clin Epidemiol. 1989;42: 585–592. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Choices Shakespeare T. and rights: eugenics, genetics and disability equality. Disabil Soc. 1998;13:665–681. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Hadorn DC. The problem of discrimination in health care priority setting. JAMA. 1992;268:1454–1459. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Asch A. Distracted by disability. The “difference” of disability in the medical setting. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 1998;7:77–87. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53.Epstein S. The construction of lay expertise: AIDS activism and the forging of credibility in the reform of clinical trials. Sci Technol Hum Values. 1995; 20:408–437. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54.Anglin MK. Working from the inside out: implications of breast cancer activism for biomedical policies and practices. Soc Sci Med. 1997;44: 1403–1415. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Henneman L, Bramsen I, Van Os TA, et al. Attitudes towards reproductive issues and carrier testing among adult patients and parents of children with cystic fibrosis (CF). Prenat Diagn. 2001; 21:1–9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Kirschner KL, Ormond K, Gill CJ. The impact of genetic technologies on perceptions of disability. Qual Manage Health Care. 2000;8:19–26. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 57.diagnosis Asch A. Prenatal and selective abortion: a challenge to practice and policy. Am J Public Health. 1999; 89:1649–1657. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58.Parens E, Asch A, eds. Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press; 2000.
  • 59.Abelson J, Forest PG, Eyles J, Smith P, Martin E, Gauvin FP. Deliberations about deliberative methods: issues in the design and evaluation of public participation processes. Soc Sci Med. 2003;57:239–251. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 60.policy Roberts N. Public deliberation: an alternative approach to crafting and setting direction. Public Adm Rev. 1997;57:124–132. [Google Scholar]
  • 61.Watson DJ, Juster RJ, Johnson GW. Institutionalized use of citizen surveys in the budgetary and policymaking processes: a small city case study. Public Adm Rev. 1991;51:232–240. [Google Scholar]
  • 62.Hudspith R. Using a consensus conference to learn about public participation in policymaking in areas of technical controversy. Political Sci Polit. 2001;34:313–317. [Google Scholar]
  • 63.Secretary’s Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing. A Public Consultation on Oversight of Genetic Tests. Bethesda, Md: US Dept of Health and Human Services; 2000.
  • 64.Secretary’s Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing Launches Public Consultation on Oversight of Genetic Tests [press release]. Bethesda, Md: National Institutes of Health, US Dept of Health and Human Services; 1999.
  • 65.Ard CF, Natowicz MR. A seat at the table: membership in federal advisory committees evaluating public policy in genetics. Am J Public Health. 2001;91:787–790. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 66.Hiller EH, Landenburger G, Natowicz MR. Public participation in medical policymaking and the status of consumer autonomy: the example of newborn-screening programs in the United States. Am J Public Health. 1997; 87:1280–1288. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 67.Weiss J, Davidson ME. Objectives and activities of the Genetic Alliance. Am J Public Health. 2000;90: 1477–1478. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 68.Little People of America. Position statement on genetic discoveries in dwarfism. January 1996. Available at: http://www.lpaonline.org/resources_faq.html. Accessed January 9, 2004. [PubMed]
  • 69.Wertz DC, Gregg R. Genetics services in a social, ethical and policy context: a collaboration between consumers and providers. J Med Ethics. 2000;26: 261–265. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 70.Genome Technology and Reproduction: Values and Public Policy and Communities of Color and Genetics Policy Project. Available at: http://www.sph.umich.edu/genpolicy/ for more information. Accessed March 6, 2004.
  • 71.Communities of Color and Genetics Policy Project. Policy Reports and Recommendations. Ann Arbor, Mich: University of Michigan School of Public Health; 2001.
  • 72.Davidson ME, David K, Hsu N, et al. Consumer perspectives on genetic testing: Lessons learned. In: Khoury MJ, Burke W, Thomson E, eds. Genetics and Public Health in the 21st Century. New York, NY: Oxford; 2000:579–601.
  • 73.Lafayette D, Abuelo D, Passero M, Tantravahi U. Attitudes toward cystic fibrosis carrier and prenatal testing and utilization of carrier testing among relatives of individuals with cystic fibrosis. J Genet Couns. 1999;8:17–36. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 74.Jacobs H, Latza U, Vieregge A, Vieregge P. Attitudes of young patients with Parkinson’s disease towards possible presymptomatic and prenatal genetic testing. Genet Couns. 2001;12: 55–67. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 75.Markel DS, Young AB, Penny JB. At-risk persons’ attitudes toward presymptomatic and prenatal testing of Huntington disease in Michigan. Am J Med Genet. 1987;26:295–305. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 76.Benjamin CM, Colley A, Donnai D, Kington H, Harris R, Kerzin-Storrar L. Neurofibromatosis type 1 (NF1): knowledge, experience, and reproductive decisions of affected patients and families. J Med Genet. 1993;30:567–574. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 77.Stern SJ, Arnos KS, Murrelle L, Welch KO, Nance WE, Pandya A. Attitudes of deaf and hard of hearing subjects toward genetic testing and prenatal diagnosis of hearing loss. J Med Genet. 2002;39:449–453. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 78.Middleton A, Hewison J, Mueller RF. Attitudes of deaf adults toward genetic testing for hereditary deafness. Am J Hum Genet. 1998;63:1175–1180. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 79.Trippitelli CL, Jamison KR, Folstein MF, Bartko JJ, DePaula JR. Pilot study on patients’ and spouses’ attitudes toward potential genetic testing for bipolar disorder. Am J Psychiatry. 1998;155: 899–904. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 80.MacMillan JC, Harper PS. The Charcot-Marie-Tooth syndrome: perceptions of disability and projected use of DNA diagnostic tests. Clin Genet. 1992; 42:161–163. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 81.Furu T, Kaariainen H, Sankila EM, Norio R. Attitudes towards prenatal diagnosis and selective abortion among patients with retinitis pigmentosa or choroideremia as well as among their relatives. Clin Genet. 1993;43:160–165. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 82.Levy M, Pirson Y, Simon P, et al. Evaluation in patients with Alport syndrome of knowledge of the disease and attitudes toward prenatal diagnosis. Clin Nephrol. 1994;42:211–220. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 83.Nance MA, Sevenich EA, Schut LJ. Knowledge of genetics and attitudes toward genetic testing in two hereditary ataxia (SCA 1) kindreds. Am J Med Genet. 1994;54:242–248. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 84.Statement of the American Society of Human Genetics on genetic testing for breast and ovarian cancer predisposition. Am J Hum Genet. 1994;55:I–iv. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 85.Statement on use of apolipoprotein E testing for Alzheimer disease. JAMA. 1995;274:1627–1629. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 86.Grody WW, Cutting GR, Klinger KW, Richards CS, Watson MS, Desnick RJ. Laboratory standards and guidelines for population-based cystic fibrosis carrier screening. Genet Med. 2001;3:149–154. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 87.Castiglia PT. Achondroplasia. J Pediatr Health Care. 1996;10:180–182. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 88.Shiang R, Thompson LM, Zhu Y-Z, et al. Mutations in the transmembrane domain of FGFR3 cause the most common genetic form of dwarfism, achondroplasia. Cell. 1994;78:335–342. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 89.Gollust SE, Thompson RE, Gooding HC, Biesecker BB. Living with achondroplasia in an average-sized world: assessment of quality of life. Am J Med Genet. 2003;120A:447–458. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 90.Gooding HC, Boehm K, Thompson RE, Hadley D, Francomano CA, Biesecker BB. Issues surrounding prenatal genetic testing for achondroplasia. Prenat Diagn. 2002;22:933–940. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 91.Gollust SE, Thompson RE, Gooding HC, Biesecker BB. Living with achondroplasia: attitudes toward population screening and correlation with quality of life. Prenat Diagn. 2003;23: 1003–1008. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 92.Gooding HC, Wilfond BS, Boehm K, Biesecker BB. Unintended messages: the ethics of teaching genetic dilemmas. Hastings Cent Rep. 2002;32:37–39. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 93.Lippman A, Wilfond BS. Twice-told tales: stories about genetic disorders. Am J Hum Genet. 1992;51: 936–937. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 94.Marteau T, Dormandy E. Facilitating informed choice in prenatal testing: how well are we doing? Am J Med Genet. 2001;106:185–190. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 95.Michie S, Smith D, Marteau TM. Prenatal tests: how are women deciding? Prenat Diagn. 1999;19:743–748. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 96.Loeben GL, Marteau TM, Wilfond BS. Mixed messages: presentation of information in cystic fibrosis screening pamphlets. Am J Hum Genet. 1998;63: 1181–1189. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 97.A Lippman-Hand, Fraser FC. Genetic counseling—the postcounseling period: II. Making reproductive choices. Am J Med Genet. 1979;4:73–87. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 98.Gollust SE, Hull SC, Wilfond BS. Limitations of direct-to-consumer advertisements for clinical genetic testing. JAMA. 2002;288:1762–1767. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 99.A Lippman. Prenatal genetictesting and screening: constructing needs and reinforcing inequities. Am J Law Med. 1991;17:15–50. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from American Journal of Public Health are provided here courtesy of American Public Health Association

RESOURCES