Abstract
A problem in understanding sympatric speciation is establishing how reproductive isolation can arise when there is disruptive selection on an ecological trait. One of the solutions that has been proposed is that a habitat preference evolves, and that mates are chosen within the preferred habitat. We present a model where the habitat preference can evolve either by means of a genetic mechanism or by means of learning. Employing an adaptive-dynamical analysis, we show that evolution proceeds either to a single population of specialists with a genetic preference for their optimal habitat, or to a population of generalists without a habitat preference. The generalist population subsequently experiences disruptive selection. Learning promotes speciation because it increases the intensity of disruptive selection. An individual-based version of the model shows that, when loci are completely unlinked and learning confers little cost, the presence of disruptive selection most probably leads to speciation via the simultaneous evolution of a learned habitat preference. For high costs of learning, speciation is most likely to occur via the evolution of a genetic habitat preference. However, the latter only happens when the effect of mutations is large, or when there is linkage between genes coding for the different traits.
Keywords: speciation, habitat preference, learning, disruptive selection, adaptive dynamics
1. Introduction
Unravelling the processes that underlie the evolution of new species is one of the major themes of evolutionary biology. Research has especially been focused on the role of geographical separation in speciation. However, despite decades of empirical and theoretical research, consensus on the likelihood of speciation in the face of geneflow has not been reached (Turelli et al. 2001; Via 2001; Kirkpatrick & Ravigné 2002; Coyne & Orr 2004; Gavrilets 2004). When a population experiences disruptive selection on an ecological trait, random mating will normally prevent the population from splitting into two species. Hence, a problem in understanding of sympatric speciation is establishing how assortative mating can evolve under such a regime of disruptive selection. One of the possible solutions that has been put forward is related to the availability of two different habitats or hosts. When disruptive selection favours ecological specialization on two different habitats, the evolution of habitat choice may aid sympatric speciation if prezygotic isolation is a by-product of divergent habitat selection. Several theoretical studies have demonstrated that this is a plausible speciation mechanism (Rice 1984; Diehl & Bush 1989; Johnson et al. 1996; Kawecki 1996, 1997; Fry 2003; Gavrilets 2004).
In these speciation models incorporating habitat choice, it is generally assumed that the preference for one of the habitats is a genetically determined trait. Typically, each preference allele shifts the preference in the direction of one of the habitats. We refer to this mechanism as a ‘genetic habitat preference’, although there are other ways to model a genetically based preference (e.g. Kawecki 1996, 1997). A possibility that has received less attention is that individuals may develop a preference for the habitat they have experienced at a young age. Such a learned preference for habitat or host features is known to occur in several groups of animal species, including birds, fishes and insects. Several examples are mentioned in West-Eberhard (2003) and Beltman et al. (2004), but the most extensive review to date is provided by Davis & Stamps (2004), who refer to this phenomenon as ‘natal habitat preference induction’. They suggest that it has been understudied, in part because scientists working with different taxa have used different terms to describe it (e.g. Hopkins' host selection principle, habitat imprinting or habitat conditioning). We will refer to it as a ‘learned habitat preference’, to highlight the resemblance to as well as the difference from a genetic habitat preference.
Several authors have discussed the possible importance of a learned habitat preference in speciation (e.g. Thorpe 1945; Maynard Smith 1966; Rice 1984; Kondrashov & Mina 1986; West-Eberhard 2003). Just as in the case of a genetic preference, the learned habitat preference may (i) cause assortative mating between individuals that prefer the same habitat, and (ii) cause individuals to produce their young in the habitat type they experienced themselves at a young age. As a result, a learned habitat preference may assist speciation because individuals exploiting a new, previously unused habitat may very quickly be reproductively isolated from the original population. However, it has also been stated that this effect is not large enough to play a significant role (Mayr 1947).
Recently, theoretical studies have shown that speciation through a learned habitat preference is extremely effective (Beltman et al. 2004; Beltman & Haccou 2005). In these previous theoretical analyses it was assumed that the learning of habitat features was already present from the onset of speciation. Thus, the question of whether the learning of habitat features can evolve from scratch as a consequence of disruptive selection on an ecological trait could not be answered. Still, this seems likely, because it was found that as soon as there is divergence in an ecological trait, there is selection on reinforcement of the effect that learning has on assortative mating and on the location where young are produced (Beltman & Haccou 2005). Hence, these effects of learning are expected to become stronger and stronger, which goes against the prediction of Mayr (1947) that a learned habitat preference is unimportant.
Speciation through the evolution of a learned habitat preference is an effective mechanism because it is a one-allele mechanism (Felsenstein 1981). That is, alleles that strengthen (the effects of) learning necessarily have the same effect in both habitats. In contrast, speciation through the evolution of a genetic habitat preference is a two-allele mechanism (at least, in our definition of a genetic preference). Hence, alleles that modify the genetic habitat preference always shift the preference in the same direction. Interestingly, the way we model the evolution of a learned habitat preference can alternatively be interpreted as a model of migration modification. It has been shown that modifiers of migration are expected to reduce migration between two populations to zero (Balkau & Feldman 1973; Karlin & McGregor 1974; Gillespie 1981; Wiener & Feldman 1991, 1993), which is in essence the same as the strengthening of a learned habitat preference. (Note, however, that this effect can be modified by kin competition and environmental stochasticity (Kisdi 2002; Leturque & Rousset 2002; Billiard & Lenormand 2005).)
In summary, when studied in separate models, both a genetic and a learned habitat preference have appeared quite likely to evolve. It is interesting to consider what would happen when both possibilities evolve at the same time. Clearly, the evolution of a learned habitat preference has the advantage of being a one-allele mechanism. Hence, during its evolution, recombination does not destroy associations between alleles that strengthen learning and ecological adaptation alleles, whereas this is a problem in the case of a genetic preference. However, the intensity of selection on the genetic habitat preference is expected to be stronger than selection on the learned habitat preference. This can be understood by considering offspring that are accidentally produced in the ‘wrong’ habitat. When their habitat preference is genetically determined, they are more likely to produce their own young in the ‘correct’ habitat, thus repairing their parents' mistakes, than when they learn their habitat preference.
In this paper, we construct a speciation model incorporating both a genetic and a learned habitat preference. Our aims are to investigate under which circumstances speciation occurs, and via which of the two preference mechanisms this is most likely. First, using adaptive dynamics (Dieckmann & Law 1996; Metz et al. 1996; Geritz et al. 1998; Leimar 2001, in press), we study the simultaneous evolution of an ecological trait, and of two traits determining, respectively, the genetic and learned habitat preference of individuals. For simplicity, we assume that habitat choice influences solely the location where young are produced, and do not take into account the effect on assortative mating. This allows us to study when evolution of the three traits leads to disruptive selection, which facilitates speciation (e.g. Kawecki 1996, 1997; Dieckmann & Doebeli 1999). Our results show that the presence of learning leads to a higher intensity of disruptive selection, thus promoting speciation. To examine whether speciation indeed follows the presence of disruptive selection, we extend the analysis employing an individual-based model, where in addition it is assumed that mate choice occurs in the preferred habitat. It appears that speciation more readily occurs through a learned than through a genetic habitat preference when there is free recombination and when the cost of learning is low. In that case, speciation through a genetic preference is only possible when the traits are coded by a few, and therefore major, loci. When there is linkage between genes that code for specialization and those that code for a genetic habitat preference, speciation through a genetic preference becomes more likely than for free recombination.
2. Model description
We consider a population of individuals that exploit two habitats, A and B. This could, for example, represent a population of phytophagous insects feeding on two different host plant species. Two variants of the model are examined: one uses the framework of adaptive dynamics (Dieckmann & Law 1996; Metz et al. 1996; Geritz et al. 1998; Leimar 2001, in press) to predict the course of evolution; the other is an individual-based model. In both cases individuals have three traits, two of which affect their habitat-selection behaviour (referred to as genetic habitat preference, and learning ability), and one that determines the viability of individuals when born in either of the two habitats (referred to as specialization coefficient).
(a) Habitat preference
The genetic habitat preference, g, is a baseline preference that individuals would express when experience does not affect habitat choice. Biologically relevant values of g can range from 0 (absolute preference for habitat A) through 0.5 (no preference) to 1 (absolute preference for habitat B). The habitat preference resulting from g can be modified by the learning of features of the habitat that is experienced early in life. The learning ability is the extent to which the genetic habitat preference is modified by experience. An individual with l=0 does not learn and hence its habitat preference exactly equals its genetic habitat preference. For 0<l≤1 the habitat preference shifts towards the habitat that was experienced early in life. For l=1 the genetic habitat preference is completely overruled by learning. Note that the extent of preference modification is genetically determined, but the direction of preference change depends on early experience and can thus be either in the same or in the opposite direction to the genetic preference.
We assume that the resulting habitat preference—an interplay between the genetic habitat preference and learning ability—determines the habitat that is chosen for reproduction. Specifically, an individual that is born in habitat x chooses habitat y for reproduction with probability fxy, where fxy is a function of g, l and the location of birth as in table 1.
Table 1.
The probability that a habitat is chosen for reproduction as a function of the genetic habitat preference (g), the learning ability (l) and the birthplace of an individual.
born in A | born in B | |
---|---|---|
reproduction in A | ||
reproduction in B | fAB=g(1−l) |
In our adaptive-dynamical analysis (see below), the habitat preference is assumed to influence the location where young are produced: females born in habitat x produce their young with probability fxy in habitat y. In the individual-based version of the model, habitat preference, in addition, affects mate choice in the sense that individuals with a preference for the same habitat are most likely to mate with each other because the probability that they encounter each other at the time of reproduction is large. Matings between individuals that prefer different habitats occur as long as the habitat preference of all individuals is not absolute.
(b) Habitat-dependent viability
Apart from the genetic habitat preference g and the learning ability l, there is a third trait, the specialization coefficient, a (from adaptedness), that determines the viability when born in different habitats (rendering a similar underlying ecological framework as in Geritz et al. 1998; Geritz & Kisdi 2000). Individuals with a=aA are most viable when born in habitat A (specialists on A), and those with a=aB are most viable when born in habitat B (specialists on B). Individuals with are equally well adapted to both habitats (generalists). The viability changes according to a Gaussian function with scale parameter σ2 when the specialization coefficient is away from the optimum. The parameter σ2 determines the trade-off between viabilities in habitat A and B. This is in part caused by how much the habitats differ from each other, and in part by the genetic architecture of the species. Specifically, the viability of an individual with specialization coefficient a who is born in habitat x equals
1 |
(c) Recurrence equations
To derive the recurrence equations, we need to keep track of two types of individuals, namely those born in habitat A and those born in habitat B. The density of these types is denoted by NA and NB, respectively. To derive equations for these densities at the next timestep (denoted by and ), we need to know the density of young produced in each habitat, and the fraction of these young that survive viability selection and competition for resources. Each individual produces on average E young. These young are produced partly in habitat A and partly in habitat B, depending on the individual's habitat preference (see table 1). A certain fraction of these young survive viability selection according to equation (2). Additionally, we assume that there is a cost of learning, c, for instance because brain nuclei involved in the learning process need to develop. Higher learning abilities, therefore, imply that that the viability is decreased by a factor (1−cl). The density of young after viability selection in habitat x, Yx, is then given by
2 |
Finally, after viability selection these individuals compete with others that are born in the same habitat. We model this process using Beverton–Holt type density dependence, where K is a parameter determining the population densities at equilibrium. Both habitats are assumed to be able to sustain an equal population density at equilibrium. These assumptions yield the following recurrence equations for the density of individuals in the next generation:
3 |
(d) Adaptive-dynamical analysis
For the first stage of the analysis we use the framework of adaptive dynamics (Dieckmann & Law 1996; Metz et al. 1996; Geritz et al. 1998; Leimar 2001, in press). In this framework, it is assumed that mutations occur rarely and that they lead to small changes in the phenotypic values of individuals. For simplicity, the initial population is assumed to be monomorphic (i.e. to consist of identical individuals). This allows one to predict the direction of evolution by calculating the intensity of selection on the evolving traits. As long as the intensity of selection on the traits is non-zero, this will result in directional evolution (Dieckmann & Law 1996). Such evolution comes to a halt in so-called evolutionarily singular points, in which the intensity of directional selection is zero. To calculate the selection gradient, which is a vector containing the intensities of selection on each of the evolving traits, mutants are assumed to appear after the residents have attained population dynamical equilibrium. The residents present at equilibrium and their densities influence the selection gradient, because the residents constitute the ecological environment of mutants. The detailed adaptive-dynamical analysis is given in the Electronic Appendix.
(e) Individual-based simulations
In our adaptive-dynamical analysis, the effect of habitat preference on mate choice is not taken into account. For directional evolution this does not influence the course of evolution when there is no heterozygote advantage (e.g. Kisdi & Geritz 1999; Geritz & Kisdi 2000; van Dooren in press; Metz in press). However, as soon as the population becomes polymorphic as a result of disruptive selection, mate choice should be taken into account to study further evolutionary changes. Therefore, we follow the evolutionary dynamics of g, l and a employing individual-based simulations (C program available on request). Speciation occurs when the population comes to consist of two types of specialists that have an ‘absolute’ preference (genetically determined or learned) for the habitat in which they are born.
The specialization coefficient, the genetic habitat preference and the learning ability are encoded by ka, kg and kl diploid loci, respectively. Alleles are either ⊕ or ⊖, and they act additively to determine the trait values of an individual. When an individual has i ⊕ alleles at the loci coding for that trait, it has a trait value of , where kt is the number of loci coding for the trait, and ϕ determines how large the effect of a mutation is. Hence, for individuals with only ⊖ alleles the trait value reaches its minimal value, and increasing the number of ⊕ alleles raises the trait value in a linear fashion to its maximum value. When the resulting trait value exceeds the range of biologically realistic values (as can be the case for g and l which can vary from 0 to 1), it is rounded off to its nearest extreme. Hence, although it is possible that individuals possess an excess habitat preference, this is not expressed.
In the simulations we assume that the viability optima in habitat A and B are 0 and 1, respectively (i.e. aA=0 and aB=1). The initial population consists of males and females with a=0, g=0.5 and l=0; that is, all individuals are specialized on habitat A but have no habitat preference. To avoid the artificial incorporation of unrealistic amounts of initial variation, at the start of the simulations all individuals are exact copies of one another. For example, half of the g loci are initially fixed for the ⊕ allele, and the other half for the ⊖ allele (note that we use an even number of loci to achieve this).
Only newborns that survive viability selection and density regulation have a chance to reproduce. To establish mate choice, all individuals are first distributed across the habitats according to their habitat preference. Subsequently, each female randomly chooses a mate from the population of males present in her habitat, and produces young in one of the habitats, again chosen according to her habitat preference.
At each locus, newborns inherit one allele from their mother, and one from their father. We use three different schemes for the physical linkage between loci. In the first scheme (‘no linkage’) we assume that there is free recombination. In the other two schemes some loci are physically linked, and we assume that this prevents recombination between them completely. Hence, the recombination rate between loci is assumed to be either 0 or 0.5: for simplicity we do not incorporate crossing over, and only take into account recombination that is due to the random distribution of male and female alleles that are on different chromosomes. To determine which loci are linked, individuals are assumed to contain kc chromosomes, and each locus is assigned one of the chromosomes. During one simulation the distribution of the loci over the chromosomes remains the same; in a subsequent simulation the distribution is chosen anew. In the second scheme the loci are evenly distributed over the chromosomes, which procedure is performed separately for each of the three traits (‘predetermined linkage’). In the third scheme (‘random linkage’), the distribution of all loci over the chromosomes is random. In both ‘predetermined linkage’ and ‘random linkage’ a value of kc=1 represents maximal linkage, because all loci are on the same chromosome. The degree of linkage decreases as kc becomes larger. At very large kc, all loci are on different chromosomes, which is represented by the ‘no linkage’ scheme. The three linkage schemes thus are a simple way to implement different degrees of linkage, ranging from maximal linkage to completely unlinked.
Newborns can have mutations at the loci that code for g, l and a. Each allele has a mutation probability of 0.0001. A mutation means that the particular allele is modified from a ⊕ allele into a ⊖ allele, or vice versa.
3. Results
The main aim of our adaptive-dynamical analysis is to study at which points there is no longer directional evolution of g, l, and a. Such evolutionarily singular points have two properties that determine how evolution will proceed (Metz et al. 1996; Geritz et al. 1998). First, the convergence stability property determines whether the singular point will be approached or not (Eshel & Motro 1981; Eshel 1983; Christiansen 1991). Second, the evolutionary stability property determines whether nearby mutants can invade or not when the singular point has been attained (Maynard Smith 1982). In the following we summarize the results of our analysis (details are provided in the Electronic Appendix).
The following potentially attracting singular points were found: (i) points where the population consists of a single specialist species with a genetic preference for its optimal habitat (i.e. either a=aA, g=0 and l=0, or a=aB, g=1 and l=0), and (ii) the point where the population consists of generalists without habitat preference (i.e. , g=0.5 and l=0). The convergence stability of these points, and hence the evolutionary dynamics, depend in large part on σ2. For low σ2, evolution always proceeds to a single population of specialists with a genetic preference for their optimal habitat (figure 1a). For high σ2, directional evolution leads to a population of generalists without (genetic) habitat preference (figure 1c). When σ2 is intermediate, both types of singular points are convergence stable. Directional evolution then leads to one of them, but which one is attained depends on the initial trait values and the details of the mutation process (figure 1b).
Figure 1.
Examples of trajectories of evolution of the specialization coefficient a, the genetic habitat preference g and the learning ability l. Note that although the trait space is drawn as a cube, in reality the biologically meaningful trait space is only limited in the g and l directions, but not in the a direction. The outcome of directional evolution depends on σ2, which determines the trade-off between viabilities in the two habitats: (a) at low σ2, evolution leads to a population of specialists with a genetic preference for their optimal habitat; (b) at intermediate σ2, it depends on the initial conditions whether evolution proceeds to specialists with a genetic preference for their optimal habitat, or to generalists without habitat preference; (c) at high σ2, evolution ends with a population of generalists without habitat preference. Parameters: E=10, K=10 000, c=0.10, aA=0, aB=1. The elements on the main diagonal of the mutational matrix used for the calculation of the trajectories are 4x(1−x)—where x represents the traits a, g and l—while the off-diagonal elements are all zero.
There is one other possible end point of evolution, namely when the learning ability evolves to a value of one (trajectories leading to l=1 are omitted from figure 1). In that case, the population splits immediately into two separate subpopulations that no longer interact (each exploiting a different habitat), after which in each of the subpopulations evolution proceeds to local specialists. Hence, this is a third possible outcome of evolution. However, a closer look at the intensity of selection on the evolving traits reveals that the intensity of selection on l is much lower than on g and a, even when there is no cost of learning. This can be understood by considering, for instance, individuals that are better adapted to habitat A than to habitat B. Clearly, they will have most surviving offspring if they have a preference for habitat A. However, a proportion of the offspring will still end up in habitat B, to which they are poorly adapted. When these young survive despite their poor adaptedness, they would do best by producing their offspring in habitat A, the habitat they did not grow up in. This is achieved only when they have a genetic habitat preference; in case of a learned habitat preference, most young would be produced in the ‘wrong’ habitat. When only directional evolution is considered, a habitat preference is thus more likely to evolve through a genetic mechanism than through learning. This is confirmed by numerical calculations of trajectories that follow the selection gradient (not shown) and by the individual-based simulations (see below). Hence, unless (i) the learning ability is initially already high, (ii) mutations in l are much more likely than mutations in the other traits, or (iii) there exist strong genetic correlations between l and one of the other traits, it seems unlikely that directional evolution will lead to l=1.
We cannot exclude that, apart from the discussed evolutionarily singular points, there exist others that are, under some circumstances, attractors of directional evolution. However, numerical calculations of trajectories through trait space, and the individual-based simulations, did not reveal the existence of additional attracting singular points. Hence, we conclude that directional evolution will normally lead either to a population of specialists with a genetic preference for their optimal habitat, or to a population of generalists without habitat preference. Such attractors of directional evolution are not necessarily the final end points of evolution, because when a singular point is not evolutionarily stable, the population will experience disruptive selection. In that case, speciation may occur when additionally assortative mating evolves; this is one possible way to escape from the fitness minimum that keeps the population trapped at an evolutionarily unstable singular point. The singular point that represents a population of specialists is always evolutionarily stable. In contrast, the generalist population will under all circumstances experience disruptive selection. The intensity of this disruptive selection becomes higher as σ2 decreases, and as the learning ability increases. Hence, learning promotes speciation.
Whether selection that favours the evolution of two extreme types will indeed lead to speciation depends, on the one hand, on the intensity of the disruptive force, and on the other hand, on processes that oppose speciation such as random mate choice and recombination. Therefore, to study whether speciation can take place as soon as there is disruptive selection, mate choice should be taken into account. Our particular interest here is whether, given the availability of both options, this is more likely to occur via the evolution of a learned or genetic habitat preference. Using individual-based simulations, we examined the course of evolution of the specialization coefficient, genetic habitat preference and learning ability, starting from a population where all individuals specialize on habitat A (a=0) but have no preference for either of the habitats (g=0.5 and l=0). As predicted by the adaptive-dynamical analysis, evolution first proceeded to either a population of specialists with a genetic habitat preference for their optimal habitat (figure 2a), or a population of generalists without habitat preference (figure 2b–f). Both situations can be the end point of evolution (figure 2a,b), which means that in the latter case the forces that oppose speciation are stronger than the intensity of disruptive selection. Alternatively, disruptive selection experienced by the generalist population can lead to speciation (figure 2c–e). In that case, the population splits into two groups specialized on and preferring either habitat A or habitat B. This habitat preference can be genetically determined in both groups (figure 2c), learned in both groups (figure 2d), or genetically determined in one group and learned in the other group (figure 2e). Another possible simulation outcome is that a clear polymorphism in g and a evolves, but speciation is not completed or not ‘stable’ (e.g. figure 2f). (A similar result was found by Matessi et al. (2002) for a generic one-allele mechanism.) In the following we investigate the circumstances for which each of the evolutionary end results is most likely.
Figure 2.
Examples of the possible end results of the individual-based simulations of evolution of the specialization coefficient a, the genetic habitat preference g and the learning ability l. The darkness of the squares indicates the number of individuals with different values of a, g and l at a particular time (a white square means that no individuals of that type are present). (a) Evolution to specialists preferring habitat A (kc=10, σ2=0.20, c=0.04); (b) evolution to generalists without habitat preference (kc=10, σ2=0.25, c=0.08); (c) speciation through a genetic habitat preference (kc=5, σ2=0.18, c=0.05); (d) speciation through a learned habitat preference (kc=10, σ2=0.18, c=0); (e) speciation through a combination of genetic and learned habitat preference (kc=10, σ2=0.21, c=0.04); (f) polymorphism in a and g (kc=10, σ2=0.21, c=0.07). Other parameters: K=400, E=10, ϕ=1, ka=16, kg=16, kl=16. The linkage scheme used in these examples was ‘predetermined linkage’ (explanation in model description).
As predicted by the adaptive-dynamical analysis, when σ2 is low, evolution led to a population of specialists on habitat A that prefer that habitat (figure 3). For high values of σ2, evolution proceeded to a population of generalists (figure 3). At intermediate values of σ2, both the generalist and the specialist singular points are convergence stable. Hence, only in that case are the initial conditions expected to influence the results (e.g. starting closer to the generalist point will increase the likelihood of evolving to that point). We also know from the adaptive-dynamical analysis that the generalist population experiences disruptive selection, the intensity of which decreases as σ2 becomes higher. For free recombination and low costs of learning, disruptive selection indeed usually led to speciation. In that case, speciation always occurred through a learned habitat preference (figure 3a). For high costs of learning, the selective force acting against the evolution of learning is too strong; speciation then is possible only through a genetic habitat preference. This happened when few loci coded for each trait (figure 3a). Otherwise, speciation through a genetic habitat preference did not take place, but the end result was a generalist species. This is because recombination is constantly destroying associations between alleles for specialization on one of the habitats and alleles that confer a genetic preference for that same habitat. This can only be overcome when the number of loci coding for the different traits is small. Mutations are then of large effect, thus increasing the fitness of more extreme individuals in comparison with the case where many loci code for the traits.
Figure 3.
The outcome of individual-based simulations of evolution of the specialization coefficient a, the genetic habitat preference g and the learning ability l for free recombination (a), and when all loci are distributed over kc chromosomes (b). The evolutionary end result depends on σ2, which determines the trade-off between viabilities in the two habitats, and on c, the cost of learning. The evolutionary outcome for each parameter combination is based on a single run. Parameters: K=400, E=10, ϕ=1 and in (b) ka=16, kg=16, kl=16.
To see whether it was indeed recombination that obstructs speciation for intermediate values of σ2, we performed additional simulations using the linkage schemes in which some loci are physically linked. Because in these schemes loci are assumed to reside on a limited number of chromosomes (kc), recombination occurs less often. As expected, increasing the physical linkage between loci made it more likely that speciation occurred through a genetic habitat preference or through a combination of genetic and learned habitat preference instead of through a learned habitat preference (figure 3b).
The results shown in figure 3 are based on a single run per parameter combination. We preferred to take small steps in parameter space and perform single runs, rather than taking large steps, which would allow us to perform several runs per parameter combination. Our approach allows a good estimate of the resulting patterns, which are indeed very clear. In addition, we have investigated the robustness of the results by changing the values of E, the number of young produced per female, of K, which affects the size of the population at equilibrium, and of ϕ, which influences how large the effect of a mutation is, as well as the usage of ‘random linkage’ instead of ‘predetermined linkage’. All these modifications did not render qualitatively different results with respect to whether speciation was more likely to occur through a genetic or through a learned habitat preference. However, some of these changes affected the likelihood of speciation, e.g. at large E, speciation occurred more often than at low E. This can be explained with the aid of the adaptive-dynamical analysis: when E is high, the singular point consisting of generalists becomes attracting already at lower σ2 than when E is low (see the Electronic Appendix). Because at low σ2 the intensity of disruptive selection is higher than at high σ2, speciation is indeed expected more often at high E than at low E.
4. Discussion
We examined the process of speciation by means of specialization on two different habitats under the assumption that both mating and the production of young occur in the preferred habitat. Our analysis shows that the outcome of evolution depends for a large part on the parameter σ2, which determines the trade-off between viabilities in the two habitats. A variety of related models have predicted that weak trade-offs (high σ2) favour the evolution of generalists, while strong trade-offs (low σ2) lead more easily to the evolution of specialists (e.g. Egas et al. 2004a; Rueffler et al. 2004). Our results are in line with this: evolution proceeds either to a population where individuals specialize on one of the habitats and have a genetic preference for that habitat (for low σ2), or to a population of generalists that have no genetic habitat preference (for high σ2). The generalist population subsequently experiences disruptive selection, which can lead to speciation. We found that the intensity of disruptive selection is higher at high learning abilities than at low learning abilities, which means that learning promotes speciation.
Employing an individual-based version of the model, it was shown that, when loci are completely unlinked and learning confers only little cost, the presence of disruptive selection often leads to speciation through a learned habitat preference. As expected, high costs of learning prevent the evolution of a learned habitat preference. Instead, speciation then occurs through a genetic habitat preference, but only when the number of loci coding for the traits is small. In that case mutations are of large effect. As a result, recombination between loci coding for adaptation to the habitats and loci coding for a genetic habitat preference, which counteracts speciation, can be overcome. For large numbers of loci this is not true: a generalist is then the end result of evolution because the force of recombination is too strong for speciation to take place. This is confirmed by simulations in which we incorporated physical linkage between loci, thus decreasing the amount of recombination counteracting speciation. In that case, speciation through a genetic habitat preference occurs more readily than in the case of completely unlinked loci.
Speciation through a learned habitat preference is not hindered by recombination, because it represents a one-allele mechanism in the sense of Felsenstein (1981). Our results demonstrate that this advantage of a learned habitat preference is decisive when it competes with a genetic habitat preference, even though the intensity of selection on the learning ability is lower than that on the genetic habitat preference (figure 1). One can imagine other mechanisms of genetically determined habitat preference that represent a one-allele mechanism (e.g. Kawecki 1996, 1997). An example of this is alleles that reduce migration between two populations (as in Balkau & Feldman 1973; Karlin & McGregor 1974). In fact, the way we modelled the learning ability can alternatively be interpreted as such a model of migration modification. The two particular mechanisms of development of habitat preference in this paper were chosen because they had already been studied in separation, but had not been incorporated in a single model. It would be interesting to extend the analysis by looking at refinements, and possible alternative implementations of these habitat-choice mechanisms.
Similar models studying the possibility of speciation through the evolution of a genetic habitat preference have concluded that such speciation occurred easily (e.g. Rice 1984; Diehl & Bush 1989; Johnson et al. 1996; Kawecki 1996, 1997; Fry 2003; Gavrilets 2004). This was found even when multiple, completely unlinked, loci code for the evolving traits. How do these results relate to our finding that recombination is a large obstacle to speciation, apparently preventing speciation more often than in the other models? Probably the most important reason for this is that the other studies went for very strong diversifying selection. For instance, one of these models was used to specifically search the intensity of diversifying selection on the ecological trait needed to overcome the recombination barrier (Fry 2003). In our model, the intensity of disruptive selection is higher when σ2 is small than when σ2 is large. However, small σ2 also favours the evolution of a single specialist on one of the habitats. This happens because in our model the disruptive selection emerges at the level of the total population as a result of a heterogeneity in the selection in different subpopulations. In contrast, in other models that incorporate habitat preference the diversifying selection pressure is assumed a priori. Therefore, the option of evolving a single specialist is excluded by these models, which probably explains the difference in results.
We assumed that the learning of habitat features is costly, for example, because brain structures that enable learning need to develop, giving those individuals with a high learning ability a competitive disadvantage in comparison with individuals with a low learning ability (e.g. see Johnston 1982; Dukas 1999). To estimate such a cost of learning is a difficult task (for an attempt see Mery & Kawecki 2003). By incorporating learning costs we studied a kind of worst-case scenario for the evolution of a learned habitat preference. First, it could be argued just as well that exhibiting a genetic habitat preference is costly. Second, apart from being costly, learning could also confer an additional selective advantage. Here, we assumed that the only advantage of habitat choice is that it may give a large survival probability to the offspring of an individual with high learning ability. However, adaptive learning of habitat choice is often also advantageous in an individual's own lifetime (Johnston 1982; Papaj & Prokopy 1989; Bernays 1998; Egas & Sabelis 2001). Such learning is thought to evolve most easily in environments that are unpredictable in space and time (Stephens 1991, 1993). It might then be employed in the manner envisaged in our model, thus increasing the survival probability not only of the individual itself, but also of its offspring.
Our results suggest that when speciation occurs via the simultaneous evolution of a habitat preference, it is likely that this happens either through a learned habitat preference, or that genes coding for ecological adaptation and those coding for genetic habitat preference are tightly linked. Interestingly, in a case where early experience is known not to influence habitat preference (Via 1991), genes for habitat choice and ecological adaptation indeed appeared to reside close together on the same chromosome (Hawthorne & Via 2001), or possibly are one and the same gene (Coyne & Orr 2004). This calls for more studies examining, on the one hand, the presence of such physical linkage, and on the other hand, in what manner experience influences habitat choice.
Several researchers have mentioned the possible importance of a learned habitat preference in speciation (e.g. Thorpe 1945; Maynard Smith 1966; Rice 1984; Kondrashov & Mina 1986; West-Eberhard 2003). In contrast, Mayr (1947) stated that it would not be strong enough to play a significant role. However, our analysis shows that a learned habitat preference is likely to evolve when there is disruptive selection (even when a genetic preference could evolve as an alternative). In addition, we found that such learning promotes speciation because it increases the intensity of disruptive selection (see also Egas et al. 2004b). Taken together, this could result in a cascade of speciation events: once the learning of habitat features starts to evolve, this not only represents progress towards speciation, but it also promotes additional speciation events by new habitat shifts. It is thus expected that in clades where the learning of habitat features occurs, the learning is not restricted to one particular species, but is widespread among closely related species. Whether habitats are evenly distributed over space, or are more or less separated areas, does not matter for this expectation, because our model for learning ability can also be interpreted as a model for migration modification. In conclusion, the learning of habitat preferences is likely to play a crucial role in the evolution of new species more often than realized so far.
Acknowledgments
We thank Michel Durinx for helping out with the multidimensional adaptive-dynamical analysis, Pim Edelaar, Rob Lachlan and Machteld Verzijden for discussions, and Carel ten Cate, Sergey Gavrilets, Patsy Haccou, Kevin Laland, Olof Leimar and an anonymous reviewer for comments on previous versions of this manuscript. This study was supported by the Research Council for Earth and Life sciences (ALW), which is subsidized by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO).
Supplementary Material
References
- Balkau B.J, Feldman M.W. Selection for migration modification. Genetics. 1973;74:171–174. doi: 10.1093/genetics/74.1.171. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Beltman J.B, Haccou P. Speciation through a learned habitat preference. Theor. Popul. Biol. 2005;67:189–202. doi: 10.1016/j.tpb.2005.01.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Beltman J.B, Haccou P, ten Cate C. Learning and colonization of new niches: a first step toward speciation. Evolution. 2004;58:35–46. doi: 10.1111/j.0014-3820.2004.tb01571.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bernays E.A. The value of being a resource specialist: behavioral support for a neural hypothesis. Am. Nat. 1998;151:451–464. doi: 10.1086/286132. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Billiard S, Lenormand T. Evolution of migration under kin selection and local adaptation. Evolution. 2005;59:13–23. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Christiansen F.B. On conditions for evolutionary stability for a continuously varying character. Am. Nat. 1991;138:37–50. [Google Scholar]
- Coyne J.A, Orr H.A.Speciation2004Sinauer Associates; Sunderland, MA [Google Scholar]
- Davis J.M, Stamps J.A. The effect of natal experience on habitat preferences. Trends Ecol. Evol. 2004;19:411–416. doi: 10.1016/j.tree.2004.04.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dieckmann U, Doebeli M. On the origin of species by sympatric speciation. Nature. 1999;400:354–357. doi: 10.1038/22521. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dieckmann U, Law R. The dynamical theory of coevolution: a derivation from stochastic ecological processes. J. Math. Biol. 1996;34:579–612. doi: 10.1007/BF02409751. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Diehl S.R, Bush G.L. The role of habitat preference in adaptation and speciation. In: Otte D, editor. Speciation and its consequences. Sinauer Associates; Sunderland, MA: 1989. pp. 345–365. [Google Scholar]
- Dukas R. Costs of memory: ideas and predictions. J. Theor. Biol. 1999;197:41–50. doi: 10.1006/jtbi.1998.0856. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Egas M, Sabelis M.W. Adaptive learning of host preference in a herbivorous arthropod. Ecol. Lett. 2001;4:190–195. [Google Scholar]
- Egas M, Dieckmann U, Sabelis M.W. Evolution restricts the coexistence of specialists and generalists—the role of trade-off structure. Am. Nat. 2004a;163:518–531. doi: 10.1086/382599. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Egas, M., Sabelis, M. W., Vala, F. & Lesna, I. 2004b Adaptive speciation in agricultural pests. In Adaptive speciation (ed. J. A. J. Metz & U. Dieckmann), pp. 249–263. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Eshel I. Evolutionary and continuous stability. J. Theor. Biol. 1983;103:99–111. doi: 10.1006/jtbi.1996.0312. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Eshel I, Motro U. Kin selection and strong evolutionary stability of mutual help. Theor. Popul. Biol. 1981;19:420–433. doi: 10.1016/0040-5809(81)90029-0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Felsenstein J. Skepticism towards Santa Rosalia, or why are there so few kinds of animals? Evolution. 1981;35:124–138. doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1981.tb04864.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Fry J.D. Multilocus models of sympatric speciation: Bush versus Rice versus Felsenstein. Evolution. 2003;57:1735–1746. doi: 10.1111/j.0014-3820.2003.tb00582.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gavrilets S.Fitness landscapes and the origin of speciesMonographs in Population Biology 37 2004Princeton University Press; Princeton [Google Scholar]
- Geritz S.A.H, Kisdi É. Adaptive dynamics in diploid, sexual populations and the evolution of reproductive isolation. Proc. R. Soc. B. 2000;267:1671–1678. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2000.1194. 10.1098/rspb.2000.1194 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Geritz S.A.H, Kisdi É, Meszéna G, Metz J.A.J. Evolutionarily singular strategies and the adaptive growth and branching of the evolutionary tree. Evol. Ecol. 1998;12:35–57. [Google Scholar]
- Gillespie J.H. The role of migration in the genetic structure of populations in temporally and spatially varying environments. iii. Migration modification. Am. Nat. 1981;117:223–234. [Google Scholar]
- Hawthorne D.J, Via S. Genetic linkage of ecological specialization and reproductive isolation in pea aphids. Nature. 2001;412:904–907. doi: 10.1038/35091062. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Johnson P.A, Hoppensteadt F.C, Smith J.J, Bush G. Conditions for sympatric speciation: a diploid model incorporating habitat fidelity and non-habitat assortative mating. Evol. Ecol. 1996;10:187–205. [Google Scholar]
- Johnston T.D. Selective costs and benefits in the evolution of learning. Adv. Study Behav. 1982;12:65–106. [Google Scholar]
- Karlin S, McGregor J. Towards a theory of the evolution of modifier genes. Theor. Popul. Biol. 1974;5:59–103. doi: 10.1016/0040-5809(74)90052-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kawecki T.J. Sympatric speciation driven by beneficial mutations. Proc. R. Soc. B. 1996;263:1515–1520. [Google Scholar]
- Kawecki T.J. Sympatric speciation via habitat specialization driven by deleterious mutations. Evolution. 1997;51:1751–1763. doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1997.tb05099.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kirkpatrick M, Ravigné V. Speciation by natural and sexual selection: models and experiments. Am. Nat. 2002;159:S22–S35. doi: 10.1086/338370. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kisdi E. Dispersal: risk spreading versus local adaptation. Am. Nat. 2002;159:579–596. doi: 10.1086/339989. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kisdi É, Geritz S.A.H. Adaptive dynamics in allele space: evolution of genetic polymorphism by small mutations in a heterogeneous environment. Evolution. 1999;53:993–1008. doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1999.tb04515.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kondrashov A.S, Mina M.V. Sympatric speciation: when is it possible? Biol. J. Linn. Soc. 1986;27:201–223. [Google Scholar]
- Leimar O. Evolutionary change and darwinian demons. Selection. 2001;2:65–72. [Google Scholar]
- Leimar, O. In press. Multidimensional convergence stability and the canonical adaptive dynamics. In Elements of adaptive dynamics (ed. J. A. J. Metz & U. Dieckmann). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Leturque H, Rousset F. Dispersal, kin competition and the ideal free distribution in a spatially heterogeneous population. Theor. Popul. Biol. 2002;62:169–180. doi: 10.1006/tpbi.2002.1600. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Matessi C, Gimelfarb A, Gavrilets S. Long-term buildup of reproductive isolation promoted by disruptive selection: how far does it go? Selection. 2002;2:41–64. [Google Scholar]
- Maynard Smith J. Sympatric speciation. Am. Nat. 1966;100:637–650. [Google Scholar]
- Maynard Smith J.Evolution and the theory of games1982Cambridge University Press; Cambridge [Google Scholar]
- Mayr E. Ecological factors in speciation. Evolution. 1947;1:263–288. [Google Scholar]
- Mery F, Kawecki T.J. A fitness cost of learning ability in Drosophila melanogaster. Proc. R. Soc. B. 2003;270:2465–2469. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2003.2548. 10.1098/rspb.2003.2548 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Metz, J. A. J. In press. Invasion fitness, canonical equations, and global invasibility criteria for Mendelian populations. In Elements of adaptive dynamics (ed. J. A. J. Metz & U. Dieckmann). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Metz J.A.J, Geritz S.A.H, Meszéna G, Jacobs F.J.A, van Heerwaarden J.S. Adaptive dynamics, a geometrical study of the consequences of nearly faithful reproduction. In: van Strien D.H, Verduyn S.M, editors. Stochastic and spatial structures of dynamical systems. North Holland; Amsterdam: 1996. pp. 147–194. [Google Scholar]
- Papaj D.R, Prokopy R.J. Ecological and evolutionary aspects of learning in phytophagous insects. A. Rev. Entomol. 1989;34:315–350. [Google Scholar]
- Rice W.R. Disruptive selection on habitat preference and the evolution of reproductive isolation: a simulation study. Evolution. 1984;38:1251–1260. doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1984.tb05647.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rueffler C, van Dooren T.J.M, Metz J.A.J. Adaptive walks on changing landscapes: Levins' approach extended. Theor. Popul. Biol. 2004;65:165–178. doi: 10.1016/j.tpb.2003.10.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stephens D. Change, regularity, and value in the evolution of animal learning. Behav. Ecol. 1991;2:77–89. [Google Scholar]
- Stephens D.W. Learning and behavioral ecology: incomplete information and environmental predictability. In: Papaj D.R, Lewis A.C, editors. Insect learning: ecological and evolutionary perspectives. Chapman & Hall; New York: 1993. pp. 245–264. [Google Scholar]
- Thorpe W.H. The evolutionary significance of habitat selection. Anim. Ecol. 1945;14:67–70. [Google Scholar]
- Turelli M, Barton N.H, Coyne J.A. Theory and speciation. Trends Ecol. Evol. 2001;16:330–343. doi: 10.1016/s0169-5347(01)02177-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- van Dooren, T. J. M. In press. Adaptive dynamics for Mendelian genetics. In Elements of adaptive dynamics (ed. J. A. J. Metz & U. Dieckmann). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Via S. Specialized host plant performance of pea aphid clones is not altered by experience. Ecology. 1991;72:1420–1427. [Google Scholar]
- Via S. Sympatric speciation in animals: the ugly duckling grows up. Trends Ecol. Evol. 2001;16:381–390. doi: 10.1016/s0169-5347(01)02188-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- West-Eberhard M.J.Developmental plasticity and evolution2003Oxford University Press; New York [Google Scholar]
- Wiener P, Feldman M.W. The evolution of dispersal in a model of mixed selfing and random mating. Evolution. 1991;45:1717–1726. doi: 10.1111/j.1558-5646.1991.tb02679.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Wiener P, Feldman M.W. The effects of the mating system on the evolution of migration in a spatially heterogeneous population. Evol. Ecol. 1993;7:251–269. [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.