Abstract
Whether you take a fundamental or liberal view of scientific evidence will affect how you interpret it. But just as with religion, we need to admit there will be legitimate differences in our views
Conventional medicine can be seen as a belief system characterised by a profession of faith in evidence based medicine.1 Faith in evidence based medicine follows from the benefits it has delivered in the past and continues to deliver. It is the best method we have for navigating our way through potential new treatments.1
Evidence based medicine, analogous to many religious traditions, is a system for the interpretation of a canon of sacred texts (medical literature). Differences in interpretation can often be traced to different assumptions underlying our reading of the literature. Just as there are fundamentalist, conservative, and liberal views of religious texts there are similar views of evidence based medicine. An examination of these views and assumptions can tell us much about differences in medical opinion.
Religious fundamentalism
The Oxford dictionary defines fundamentalism as the strict maintenance of the ancient or fundamental doctrines of any religion or ideology.2 Fundamentalism sees truth as unified, revealed, absolute, and inerrant. Supporters have a black and white view, seeing themselves as the true keepers of the faith with good reason for an absolute belief that they are right. Critics see the world in shades of grey and view fundamentalism as self righteous and simplistic.
Fundamentalism is associated with literal readings of sacred texts. Texts can be interpreted in different ways. A liberal reading of biblical prohibitions of homosexuality, for example, might consider that they do not apply to contemporary committed same sex relationships. Thus people with the same basic belief system, reading the same text, can come to radically different conclusions. These differences derive from the varying assumptions they bring to reading and applying the literature.
Medical fundamentalism
Variation in interpretation of the medical literature shares many of the features of variations in interpretation of religious texts. Proponents of evidence based medicine emphasise important principles of a balanced view.3 This emphasises the limitations of evidence based medicine,4 the need for judgment in applying it to individual patients,5 and the validity of evidence other than randomised controlled trials.6 7 A liberal approach goes beyond this. It sees the literature as a guide, establishing principles that need to be applied to specific situations.
Fundamentalists, however, take a strict and literal view of the literature. They give little allowance for individualisation, show little scepticism about the limitations of the literature, and tend to undervalue non-randomised evidence.3 The fundamentalist approach sees the literature as law, a series of “sacred texts” that are treated with great respect and are to be applied literally. Any deviation from the text is seen as heresy. Just like religious fundamentalists, medical fundamentalists tend to be self righteous and denigrate other interpretations. Of course, the analogy between medicine and religion is not to be taken too far. Violence or fanaticism are not features of most medical decision making.
Examples of relevant questions
Deviation from good evidence based practice is an important reason for poor outcomes in many aspects of life. In the medical domain, issues of interpretation greatly affect the treatments that we recommend. There is often controversy, conflict, and heated discussion about medical decisions. Below I give some examples of controversies in oncology with a conservative and liberal view of the literature. Similar issues apply in other disciplines.
Can we extrapolate evidence from one drug to another?
This is a fundamental question in evidence based medicine.8 Trials provide evidence on specific drugs, yet we often deal with classes (or groups) of drugs with similar efficacy. Does the evidence apply only to the drug tested? Are trials recipes for treatment or proof of principle? For example, we know from a meta-analysis and a large randomised controlled trial that adjuvant chemotherapy for early non-small cell lung cancer offers a small survival advantage (4-5%). Does this provide proof that adjuvant chemotherapy works or that specific drugs work. It takes a long time to conduct such trials, and the drugs used have largely been replaced by combinations that have been shown to be more effective in advanced disease.9 It is tempting to substitute more contemporary regimens, and this has become standard practice in many countries. Is this liberal view an improvement in patient care, allowing use of less toxic or more efficacious regimens, or a deviation from the evidence to support chemotherapy in this setting?
Do we apply treatments exactly as they were prescribed in a clinical trial?
Chemotherapy drugs often enter clinical practice with little information about optimal dosing. The doses deliverable in community practice are often less than those used in the registration trials. This experience is supported by respected guidelines, such as those of the British Columbia Cancer Agency, which recommend reduced dose intensities of topotecan, vinorelbine, and capecitabine.10 Such a practice is safe and rational but causes problems because the dose no longer corresponds to that in the efficacy trial. In some cases, low level evidence provides some support for the efficacy of lower doses,11 but is this enough?
The recommended dose for irinotecan for metatstatic colorectal cancer is 350 mg/m2, but in one trial 63% of patients developed grade 3/4 toxicity and 30% of patients were admitted to hospital for a median duration of nine days.12 The dose actually delivered is therefore much less than 350 mg/m2. Is it justifiable to prescribe a lower dose, and increase it in the absence of toxicity, in order to avoid a high level of initial toxicity? Prescribing unrealistic doses that require frequent omissions of doses or dose reductions is inefficient. It is disruptive to patients and staff. But should we take a conservative view and adhere to the treatment as delivered in the randomised trial?
How much evidence is enough?
Few advances in oncology offer cure of conditions that have previously had only palliative treatments. One such advance has been peritonectomy and hyperthermic intraperitoneal chemotherapy for peritoneal metastases from metastatic colorectal cancer.13 The well conducted randomised controlled trial was stopped early because the experimental treatment had a considerable advantage over conventional palliative treatment. The findings are supported by unrandomised data strongly suggesting that this treatment cures some patients.14 This trial has generated divergent responses. Because of the small size, the difference in survival relates to a small number of patients. Some will demand a confirmatory trial to prove the principle. An ethical trial requires equipoise, a difficult assumption with a trial that has strongly positive results. How much evidence is enough?
How do we apply data from trials to patients in the community?
Randomised controlled trials show a consistent improved survival (of three months) in patients with locally advanced non-small cell lung cancer who have concurrent rather than sequential chemo-irradiation. This has led to guidelines recommending concurrent treatment.15 16 The toxicity in these trials was substantial. The main difficulty in applying these data is the external validity. We know that most patients with this cancer have comorbidity, often chronic airflow limitation and vascular disease. We know that most patients are elderly and were not well represented in the clinical trials.17 How then should we treat patients with serious comorbidity and locally advanced non-small cell lung cancer who would not have been eligible for the reference trials? If we exclude these patients from combined treatment because of concerns about toxicity, what level of comorbidity do we use to make the decision?
Conclusions
Evidence based medicine and the scientific medical literature are the bedrock of modern medical practice. The above questions show that interpretation of the evidence is not clear cut. Just as in the religious literature, different world views result in varying interpretations. A person with a more fundamentalist orientation is much more likely to stay within the letter of the law. A more liberal perspective would result in important deviations from the evidence.
The advantage of the conservative position is that it is clear and well defined. If you allow a large degree of latitude to interpretation, where does it stop? The advantage of the liberal position is that it is flexible. The examples above suggest the possibility of delivering better outcomes in terms of reduced toxicity, increased efficacy, reduced cost, or improved convenience.
We all need to realise that differences in interpretation of the medical literature often relate to different assumptions about the way we view these texts. There is good interpretation and bad interpretation, but sometimes the reason for disagreement is that we bring equally valid but different views to the text. One of the difficulties of debate in both the religious and medical context is that attitudes tend to become polarised. We need to be aware of our differing assumptions, avoid self righteousness, and conduct these discussions in an atmosphere of tolerance.
Summary points
Belief systems in medicine are analogous to those of religious traditions
Attitudes to medical or religious literature can be characterised as fundamentalist, conservative, or liberal
Variations between these world views reflect different ways of reading evidence not a disparity in the value placed on the evidence
Debates on evidence need to acknowledge the validity of alternative world views
Contributors and sources: ML is a medical oncologist in clinical practice with an interest in lung cancer and intraperitoneal chemotherapy. This article has arisen out of discussions of evidence conducted with colleagues in a project to standardise chemotherapy protocols in New South Wales and controversy over the role of peritonectomy for metastatic colorectal cancer. He describes himself as having a liberal world view in relation to medical evidence and Christianity.
Competing interests: ML has accepted travel grants to attend conferences from AstraZeneca, Aventis, Eli-Lilly, Pierre Fabre, and Sanofi-Synthelabo. He has research funding and has worked as a consultant for Eli-Lilly. He is involved in a funding application for research on peritonectomy.
References
- 1.Group TE-BMW. Evidence-based medicine: a new approach to teaching the practice of medicine. JAMA 1992;268:2420-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Oxford University Press. AskOxford.com. (accessed 6 Aug 2006).
- 3.Loefler I. Evidence based medicine. BMJ 2004;328:842. [Google Scholar]
- 4.Julian DG. What is right and what is wrong about evidence-based medicine? J Cardiovasc Electrophysiol 2003;14(9 Suppl):S2-5. [DOI] [PubMed]
- 5.Schattner A, Fletcher RH. Research evidence and the individual patient. QJM 2003;96:1-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Green J, Britten N. Qualitative research and evidence based medicine. BMJ 1998;316:1230-2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Devereaux PJ, Yusuf S. The evolution of the randomized controlled trial and its role in evidence-based decision making. J Intern Med 2003;254(2):105-13. [DOI] [PubMed]
- 8.Antman EM, Ferguson JJ. Should evidence-based proof of efficacy as defined for a specific therapeutic agent be extrapolated to encompass a therapeutic class of agents?. Circulation 2003;108:2604-7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Socinski MA. Cytotoxic chemotherapy in advanced non-small cell lung cancer: a review of standard treatment paradigms. Clin Cancer Res 2004;10(12):4210-14s. [DOI] [PubMed]
- 10.British Columbia Cancer Agency. Chemotherapy protocols. www.bccancer.bc.ca/default.htm (accessed 6 Sep 2006).
- 11.Rose PG, Maxson JH, Fusco N, Mossbruger K, Rodriguez M. Liposomal doxorubicin in ovarian, peritoneal, and tubal carcinoma: a retrospective comparative study of single-agent dosages. Gynecol Oncol 2001;82:323-8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Fuchs CS, Moore MR, Harker G, Villa L, Rinaldi D, Hecht JR. Phase III comparison of two irinotecan dosing regimens in second-line therapy of metastatic colorectal cancer. J Clin Oncol 2003;21:807-14. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Verwaal VJ, van Ruth S, de Bree E, van Sloothen GW, van Tinteren H, Boot H, et al. Randomized trial of cytoreduction and hyperthermic intraperitoneal chemotherapy versus systemic chemotherapy and palliative surgery in patients with peritoneal carcinomatosis of colorectal cancer. J Clin Oncol 2003;21:3737-43. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Glehen O, Kwiatkowski F, Sugarbaker PH, Elias D, Levine EA, De Simone M, et al. Cytoreductive surgery combined with perioperative intraperitoneal chemotherapy for the management of peritoneal carcinomatosis from colorectal cancer: a multi-institutional study. J Clin Oncol 2004;22:3284-92. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Jett JR, Scott WJ, Rivera MP, Sause WT, American College of Chest Physicians. Guidelines on treatment of stage IIIB non-small cell lung cancer. Chest 2003;123(1 Suppl):221-5s. [DOI] [PubMed]
- 16.Australian Cancer Network Management of Lung Cancer Guidelines Working Party. Clinical practice guidelines for the prevention, diagnosis and management of lung cancer. Canberra: National Health and Medical Research Council of Australia, 2004.
- 17.Vardy JL, Boyer MJ, Beale P, Barnes D, Clarke SJ. Patients in advanced non small cell lung cancer (ANSCLC) chemotherapy trials are not representative of the general lung cancer population [abstract 2668]. Proc Am Soc Clin Oncol 2003;22:663. [Google Scholar]