To evaluate the safety and efficacy of medical interventions for children, investigators often must conduct research with children, including research that does not offer them a compensating potential for clinical benefit.1, 2 To evaluate lopinavir/ritonavir in children with HIV, investigators first gave single doses to a few children to determine what dose levels they could tolerate.3 These tests, necessary preludes to future efficacy studies, posed some risks to the participating children, but did not offer them any potential for clinical benefit.
‘Non-beneficial’ pediatric research had been the subject of ethical debate for over 25 years.4, 5, 6, 7 Most notably, McCormick argued that children, if they were capable, would consent to non-beneficial pediatric research when it poses no “discernible risk.”8, 9 Paul Ramsey responded that McCormick’s argument relies on unwarranted assumptions regarding children’s hypothetical choices, ignores the fact that children are neither mature nor autonomous, and disregards adults’ obligations to protect children.10, 11
Although the theoretical debate continues, current guidelines allow children to be enrolled in non-beneficial research when it poses acceptably low risks, and is likely to yield information important for improving children’s health and well-being. Unfortunately, current standards for defining what constitutes an acceptable level of risk suffer serious shortcomings. The present paper evaluates a possible alternative, the ‘charitable participation’ standard, which assesses the risks of pediatric research based on the level of risks to which children may be exposed in appropriate charitable activities.
THE NO SERIOUS HARM THRESHOLD
Guidelines might allow non-beneficial pediatric research provided it poses no risk of serious harm. The Council of Europe and the U.K. Medical Research Council appear to endorse this approach, stipulating that research is acceptable when “it is to be expected that [the research] will result, at the most, in a very slight and temporary negative impact on the health of the person concerned.”12, 13 Because this approach blocks research that poses any chance, no matter how low, of serious injury, it has the potential to block a good deal of pediatric research. Even a single blood draw poses some, extremely low risk of serious harm.
Other guidelines, including those from Kenya and the Indian Council on Medical Research, leave the decision of when pediatric risks are acceptably low to the judgement of reviewing ethics committees.14, 15 Yet, psychological research demonstrates that individuals often make systematic errors when they rely on their own perceptions to assess risks,16, 17, 18 suggesting more guidance is needed to protect pediatric research participants.
THE ROUTINE EXAMINATIONS STANDARD
The Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS) allows non-beneficial pediatric research when the risks “do not exceed those associated with routine medical and psychological examination of such persons.”19 As stated, this standard appears to allow those who require risky examinations as part of their routine medical care to be exposed to greater research risks than healthy children. To avoid taking advantage of sick children in this way, several authors define acceptable risks based on the level of risk posed by routine examinations for healthy children.20, 21
The Bright Futures guidelines, endorsed by the American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP), recommend that healthy children be assessed for height, weight, head circumference, vision and hearing.22 The only invasive examination recommended for healthy children is a single heel stick at birth to screen for metabolic disorders. In practice, then, the healthy child standard seems to preclude research that poses risks any greater than the level of risk posed by a single heel stick. Moreover, children in some countries do not undergo routine medical examinations, leaving it unclear how this standard applies in those countries.
RISKS OF DAILY LIFE STANDARD
Many guidelines define acceptably low risks based on the level of risks children face in daily life. Australia’s guidelines allow research interventions when “the probability and magnitude of harm or discomfort anticipated in the research are not greater in and of themselves than those ordinarily encountered in daily life.”23 Guidelines from Nepal and the U.S. combine this definition with the routine examinations standard, defining ‘minimal’ risks as “not greater in and of themselves than those ordinarily encountered in daily life or during the performance of routine physical or psychological examinations or tests.”24, 25, 26
Despite widespread endorsement, the ‘risks of daily life’ standard suffers significant shortcomings.27 Most importantly, many of the activities of daily life offer children the potential for personal benefit. Parents do not allow their children to play basketball because they find the risks inherently acceptable/ parents accept these risks because they assume their children will benefit. It follows that the level of risk considered acceptable in daily life may not be appropriate for evaluating research that does not offer a compensating potential for clinical benefit.
CHARITABLE ACTIVITIES IN DAILY LIFE
Every year, millions of children participate in charitable programs around the world. These programs, designed to benefit others, pose some risks to the participating children. Youth Service America “partners with thousands of organizations committed to increasing the quality and quantity of volunteer opportunities for young people, ages 5–25.”28 During Global Youth Service Day, millions of children in over 120 countries carry out local community improvement projects.29 They plant crops, visit the sick, dig wells, and collect donations. Many respected international charitable organizations have programs designed for children. UNICEF encourages children to collect money for the poor,30 Habit for Humanity “focuses on engaging youth ages 5 to 25 in the mission and work of Habitat for Humanity.”31
When children participate in charitable activities, special safeguards are needed, and some charitable activities are not appropriate for children at all. Habit for Humanity, for example, does not allow children under age 16 to enter construction sites. Yet, with appropriate safeguards in place, it is recognized around the world that it can be appropriate for children to participate in charitable activities to help others, even when doing so poses some risk to them.
PRO: ARGUMENTS FOR THE CHARITABLE PARTICIPATION STANDARD
Charitable activities are similar to non-beneficial research in a number of ethically salient respects. First, charitable activities and non-beneficial pediatric research typically are designed to help individuals unrelated to the participants. Second, many charitable activities, like most non-beneficial research studies, help unidentified individuals. Third, non-beneficial pediatric research and charitable programs offer only a chance that others will be helped. The anticipated benefits of a charitable car wash, like those of a clinical trial, may fail to materialize. The fact that children may participate in charitable activities suggests that it may be acceptable for them to participate in non-beneficial research, even though such involvement offers only a chance of helping unidentified and unrelated individuals.
One possible difference between research and charitable activities is that children actively participate in charitable activities: they collect donations, wash cars, build homes. Research participation, in contrast, seems to be inherently passive: children are subjected to research interventions. In fact, research participation typically requires some active participation. Children must come to the clinic, answer questions, remember their schedule, monitor and report side effects. Even interventions that seem to involve purely passive participation—such as holding still for an MRI scan—can require more effort than many charitable activities.
A different, and perhaps more relevant, sense of ‘passive’ participation involves the relationship between individuals’ participation and their understanding and will. Adults and older children can render their involvement in a given project active by understanding and voluntarily agreeing to it. The collection of blood involves essentially no physical movement on the part of donors. Yet, as long as the donor understands and agrees, blood donation is described in active terms, as the “giving” or “donating” of blood. In contrast, researchers “take” blood from infants who cannot understand and agree.
The claim that such passive exposure to risks for the benefit of others is unethical seems to gain support from the fact that charitable activities typically do not involve infants or toddlers. Alternatively, infants and toddlers may not be involved in charitable activities for the simple reason that they are unable to contribute to most charitable activities. Choosing between these two options requires analysis of the moral significance of individuals’ understanding and endorsing the charitable activities in which they are involved.
There are at least two ways to understand the importance of obtaining individuals’ informed and voluntary agreement.32 One view holds that it is ethically unacceptable to expose an individual to risk for the benefit of others without that individual’s agreement. This view implies that charitable activities with infants and toddlers are unethical because they cannot understand and agree. A second view holds that it is unacceptable to expose an individual to risks for the benefit of others in a way that is inconsistent with that individual’s will. On this view, informed agreement is not an ethical requirement for those, including infants and toddlers, who lack the capacity to provide it. In these cases, research enrollment cannot be inconsistent with the individual’s will, hence, may be acceptable provided alternative safeguards are in place.
Although complete analysis is beyond the scope of the present paper, one way to assess these two views is to consider their implications in concrete cases. Imagine that taking a few extra drops of blood from a group of newborns during a clinically indicated heel stick could yield information needed to develop a new treatment for a childhood illness. The view that individuals should never be exposed to risks for the benefit of others unless they understand and accept them implies that this intervention is necessarily unethical, no matter how low the risks and no matter how important the information to be gained.
The alternative view holds that agreement is not required for individuals who lack the capacity to provide it. This view implies that obtaining a few extra drops of blood from infants may be acceptable provided appropriate safeguards are in place, including low risks, the information to be gained is important, there is no other reasonable way to obtain the information, the child’s parents give permission, and an independent review committee certifies that these safeguards have been satisfied. This approach raises the question of whether the level of risk acceptable for charitable activities with 5 year olds provides an appropriate threshold for research risks with infants and toddlers. The fact that infants and toddlers cannot provide even rudimentary informed agreement may imply that the level of risks to which they may be exposed for the benefit of others is lower. If so, a supplementary standard to the charitable participation standard may be needed to evaluate the risks of non-beneficial research with infants and toddlers.
CON: ARGUMENTS AGAINST CHARITABLE PARTICIPATION STANDARD
Most research guidelines allow children to be exposed to risks for the benefit of others, provided the risks are not too great and the information to be gained is important enough to justify the risks. The U.S federal regulations, for example, permit such research if the risk of harm is minimal or a minor increase over minimal and “the intervention or procedure is likely to yield generalizable knowledge about the subjects' disorder or condition which is of vital importance for the understanding or amelioration of the subjects' disorder or condition” (45 CFR 46.406 c).
Although this approach strikes a utilitarian balance, it does not answer the fundamental ethical question of why this utilitarian approach should override other ethical concerns. The most serious ethical problem such research represents is that of the obligation of loyalty of powerful persons to less powerful persons. It is not that all powerful persons must be loyal to all less powerful persons. But there are some relationships that require such loyalty. Parents in particular are supposed to act in ways that further the interests of their children. Physicians also are supposed to act in ways that further the interests of their patients and do not unnecessarily place patients at risk.
When a researcher asks a person to be a research subject, the researcher is asking for a gift. Gifts are made knowingly and voluntarily by one person to another. If the transaction is not knowing and voluntary, it is not a gift. In general, gifts may not be made by surrogates. Faced with the possibility of removing a kidney from an incompetent person to “donate” it to a family member, the court ruled that since guardians cannot make gifts of money or property, they certainly could not make gifts of an organ.33
It has been argued that parents should be able to volunteer their children for research that holds out no prospect of clinical benefit for the children, and poses some risk of harm. This argument is based largely on the notion that societal values both endorse and recognize parents’ authority to expose children to risks for the benefit of unrelated others when the risks are acceptably low. However the charitable examples cited in the previous section do not support research on very young children. These examples reflect a societal notion that children partaking in activities with their parents is a good thing. In addition, these examples involve normal childhood activities, in which children readily and happily engage. These examples do not seem analogous to a child undergoing a lumbar puncture, or having an indwelling catheter inserted in a vein requiring the child to be still for eight hours.
The major difference, in my opinion, is that, in medical research, something is being done to the child, not with or by the child. If charity has been done, it has not been done by the child, but rather by the parent who has volunteered the child. It is certainly the case that some research requires a child’s true participation as in filling out questionnaires or entering information in a computer. I am not sure anyone would object to this type of research since the child is active and doing child-like things. Further, the children can always stop doing these activities if they get bored or tired unlike a child who is exposed to a drug. However it seems fanciful to argue that children are active participants in biomedical research. They do not “come to the clinic,” they are brought to the clinic. Indeed the claim of “passive participation” would seem to be a contradiction in terms. It is difficult to see how the toxicity study of lopinar/ritonavir required the “participation” of children. The use of children in that study might have been necessary to answer the research question, and the end sought may have been important, but the children were a means to that end, not active “participants”.
It is the class of research that involves children’s bodies being invaded with drugs or devices that is the true cause of concern. It is hard to imagine on what ethical basis a parent can permit a researcher to put a needle in a four-year-old’s spine purely for research purposes. This conclusion seems supported by the fact that charitable organizations often exclude young children. The American Red Cross requires blood donors to be at least 16 years of age.34 One must be 16 to participate in Habitat for Humanity’s building programs. Indeed, its programs for 5–8 year olds contain no element of charity, but rather involve activities that may sensitize children to the need for future charity. These differences suggest the level of risk of charitable activities does not offer an appropriate standard for assessing the risks of non-beneficial research with children who are unable to give their own informed consent.
CONCLUSION
Many research regulations assess the risks of non-beneficial pediatric research by comparing them to the level of risks children face in daily life. However, some risks of daily life are justified by a potential direct benefit to the child, even though others are considered inappropriate. These concerns raise the need to consider other standards for assessing the risks of non-beneficial pediatric research.
It can be argued that non-beneficial pediatric research involves a kind of charitable activity. If one accepts this argument, the level of risk posed by appropriate charitable activities might offer a standard for assessing the risks of non-beneficial pediatric research. In its favor, this ‘charitable participation’ standard would allow children to be enrolled in non-beneficial research only when the risks are within societally accepted limits, and the children’s parents give their permission. The charitable participation standard also may help researchers, review committees, parents and society come to view non-beneficial pediatric research in the same favorable light we now regard charitable activities in daily life. Implementation of the charitable participation standard, like other empirical standards, will require research to collect empirical data on the level of risks allowed in charitable activities appropriate for children.
On the other hand, there are arguably important differences between medical research and charitable activities which raise concern about this approach. In particular, children are active participants in most charitable activities, whereas most medical research is done to the child’s body. This difference raises concern that the risks of charitable activities may not offer an appropriate standard for assessing the risks of most clinical research. Similarly, infants and toddlers never engage in charitable activities so the analogy would appear not to apply to this class of children. Furthermore, many children’s charitable activities are done alongside or with parents or other adults whereas research with children is done exclusively to them.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks to Christine Grady, Laura Tiehen, Franklin Miller, Benjamin Wilfond, Gopal Sreenivasan, Stephen Spielberg, and Seema Shah for their helpful comments on previous versions of the manuscript.
Footnotes
Publisher's Disclaimer: This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final citable form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
REFERENCES
- 1.Institute of Medicine. Ethical conduct of clinical research involving children. Washington, DC: National Academies Press; 2004. chapter 2. Available from: www.nap.edu. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Nicholson RH. Medical research with children: ethics, law, and practice. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1986. pp. 40–60. [Google Scholar]
- 3.FDA. The Pediatric exclusivity provision. Status Report to Congress. 2001 January; Available from: http://www.fda.gov/cder/pediatric.
- 4.Kopelman L. In: Children and health care: moral and social issues. Kopelman LM, Moskop JC, editors. Boston: Kluwer; 1989. pp. 89–99. [Google Scholar]
- 5.Koocker GP, Keith-Spiegel P. In: Children as research subjects: Science, Ethics and Law. Grodin MA, Glantz LH, editors. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 1994. [Google Scholar]
- 6.Brock DW. Glantz LH. Ethical issues in exposing children to risks in research. In: Grodin MA, editor; Children as research subjects: Science, Ethics and Law. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 1994. pp. 81–101. [Google Scholar]
- 7.Ackerman TF. Nontherapeutic research procedures involving children with cancer. J Ped Oncology. 1994;11:134–136. doi: 10.1177/104345429401100310. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.McCormick RA. Proxy consent in the experimental situation. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine. 1974;18:2–20. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.McCormick RA. Experimentation in children: sharing in sociality. Hastings Center Report. 1976;6:41–46. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Ramsey P. The enforcement of morals: nontherapeutic research on children: a reply to Richard McCormick. Hastings Center Report. 1976;6:21–30. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Ramsey P. Children as research subjects: a reply. Hastings Center Report. 1977;7:40–42. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Council of Europe. Available from: http://conventions.coe.int/treaty/en/Treaties/Html/195.htm.
- 13.Medical Research Council of the U.K. Available from: http://www.mrc.ac.uk/pdf-ethics_guide_children.pdf#xml=http://www.mrc.ac.uk/scripts/texis.exe/webinator/search/xml.txt?query=risks+in+children&pr=mrcall&order=r&cq=&id=44b886ec2.
- 14.National Council for Science and Technology. Nairobi, Kenya: Guidelines for the Ethical Conduct of Biomedical Research Involving Human Subjects in Kenya. 2004
- 15.Indian Council on Medical Research. Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research on Human Subjects. 2000 Available from: http://icmr.nic.in/ethical.pdf.
- 16.Slovic P. Perception of risk. Science. 1987;236:280–285. doi: 10.1126/science.3563507. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Tversky A, Kahneman D. Judgments under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science. 1974;185:1124–1131. doi: 10.1126/science.185.4157.1124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Weinstein N. Optimistic biases about personal risks. Science. 1989;246:1232–1233. doi: 10.1126/science.2686031. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.CIOMS. Geneva: CIOMS; International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research. 2002 commentary on guideline 13.
- 20.Kopelman LM. Minimal risk as an international ethical standard in research. J Med Phil. 2004;29:351–378. doi: 10.1080/03605310490500545. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Resnik DB. Eliminating the daily risks standard from the definition of minimal risk. J Med Ethics. 2005;31:35–38. doi: 10.1136/jme.2004.010470. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22. Available from: http://brightfutures.aap.org/web/healthCareProfessionalstoolsAndResources.asp.
- 23.National Health and Medical Research Council. National Statement on ethical conduct in research involving humans. available at http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/international/HSPCompilation.pdf.
- 24.Nepal Health Research Council. Kathmandu, Nepal: Guidelines for Institutional Review Committees for health research in Nepal. 2005
- 25.Department of Health and Human Services. Code of Federal Regulations. 45 CFR 46.116.
- 26.Food And Drug Administration. Code of Federal Regulations. Title 21, 50.25. Volume 1 Revised April 1, 2005.
- 27.Wendler D, Belsky L, Thompson KM, Emanuel EJ. Quantifying the federal minimal risk standard: implications for pediatric research without a prospect of direct benefit. JAMA. 2005;294:826–832. doi: 10.1001/jama.294.7.826. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28. Available from: http://www.ysa.org/program/program.cfm.
- 29. Available from: http://www.gysd.net/home/index.html.
- 30. Available from: http://www.unicefusa.org/site/pp.asp?c=hkIXLdMRJtE&b=1706865.
- 31. Available from: http://www.habitat.org/youthprograms/suppdocs/2005_summary_report_pdf.pdf.
- 32.Fried C. Children as Subjects for Medical Experimentation. In: van Eys J, editor. Research on Children. Baltimore: University Park Press; 1978. pp. 107–114. [Google Scholar]
- 33. In re Richardson, 284 So. 2d 185 (La. App. 1973). [Google Scholar]
- 34. Available from: http://www.redcross.org/services/biomed/0,1082,0_557_,00.html.