Skip to main content
Journal of General Internal Medicine logoLink to Journal of General Internal Medicine
. 2008 Apr 18;23(6):867–870. doi: 10.1007/s11606-008-0616-y

The Ethics of Information: Absolute Risk Reduction and Patient Understanding of Screening

Peter H Schwartz 1,2,3,, Eric M Meslin 1,2,3
PMCID: PMC2517883  PMID: 18421509

Abstract

Some experts have argued that patients should routinely be told the specific magnitude and absolute probability of potential risks and benefits of screening tests. This position is motivated by the idea that framing risk information in ways that are less precise violates the ethical principle of respect for autonomy and its application in informed consent or shared decision-making. In this Perspective, we consider a number of problems with this view that have not been adequately addressed. The most important challenges stem from the danger that patients will misunderstand the information or have irrational responses to it. Any initiative in this area should take such factors into account and should consider carefully how to apply the ethical principles of respect for autonomy and beneficence.

KEY WORDS: risk and benefit data, informed consent, respect for autonomy

INTRODUCTION

When a patient is considering whether to undergo a preventive service such as a screening test, the relevant information to guide a decision includes the probability of risk and benefit.1,2 Some have argued that all patients considering preventive services should be given this information in the form of absolute probabilities, presented numerically or graphically.29 This claim is based on the worry that failing to give patients this type of risk information violates the ethical principle of respect for autonomy,10 since without this information patients are unable to make a fully informed decision.

In this Perspective, we point to a number of problems with this view that have not been adequately addressed. Most important is the danger that statements of absolute risk and benefit will confuse many patients, leading to negative effects on patient autonomy and health outcomes. Although various steps could be taken to offset these problems, we argue that there is a significant chance that such steps would be inadequate. There are also important questions about how to apply respect for autonomy and other ethical principles in this area.

Any initiative to provide absolute risk and benefit information to patients must take these issues into account. We limit our discussion to recommended screening tests such as mammograms, but similar issues arise when considering patient understanding of any preventive test or treatment.

PATIENT UNDERSTANDING AND FRAMING OF RISK/ BENEFIT DATA

Many patients currently are not given adequate information about recommended screening tests. Research shows that primary-care providers provide very limited information when ordering a test, often doing little more than describing its purpose.11,12 Similarly, health information about screening tests provided by brochures or on the Internet often gives incomplete information and varies widely in quality.13,14 Moreover, the risks of false positives, false negatives, and over-treatment are rarely described.13,14 In addition, research shows that individuals overestimate the benefits and underestimate the possible risks of screening.1517

All these observations suggest that in this area the medical establishment is failing to respect patient autonomy, one of the central principles of medical ethics.10 This principle requires, among other things, that patients guide their health care by providing informed consent to proposed interventions18 or by participating in shared decision-making.1921 While the ways that patients consent for invasive procedures, such as surgery, often are subjected to more intense scrutiny than for low-risk interventions, such as mammograms, the same principle applies.18,21 Unless the patient has an adequate understanding of the possible benefits, harms, and alternatives to the procedure, he or she cannot give adequate informed consent.18,20

But how much information is enough? Any quantitative data can be described in many ways, and research shows that such framing has significant effects on patient understanding.22,23 Consider the various ways to frame the risks and benefits of mammograms in women over 50 years old, a test that is recommended by the US Preventive Services Task Force.24 The most complete representation is in the form of natural frequencies, which present the expected probabilities of various outcomes in a population of 1,000 women undergoing screening compared to an equivalent population that is not being screened.4 According to one model, out of 1,000 women who are screened biannually for 10 years, 178 will be called back for repeat imaging, 64 will have a biopsy, and 33 will be diagnosed as having breast cancer.25 Over 20 years, there will be 14 deaths from breast cancer in the unscreened group, and just 9.1 in the group undergoing mammography.25

There are other ways to describe the risks and benefits of mammograms using absolute probabilities. For instance, the absolute risk reduction (ARR) is calculated by subtracting the mortality rate in the screened group from that of the unscreened group. Thus, the ARR of performing mammography regularly for 20 years is 4.9 per 1,000 (or 0.49%), i.e., 14 per 1,000 (1.4%) minus 9.1 per 1,000 (0.91%).25 Another absolute measure of benefit is the number needed to screen (NNS), which describes how many people have to be screened and provided follow-up testing and treatment to save one person (a slightly modified form of the number needed to treat (NNT) measure).26 According to the model above, roughly 204 women have to be screened for 20 years to save one from dying of breast cancer during that time period.25

However, patients are rarely given such absolute measures of possible benefit. In one study, just 22% of brochures concerning mammography quantified the benefit at all, and those that did only provided the relative risk reduction (RRR).13 RRR is calculated by dividing the decrease in morbidity or mortality by the baseline rate. Using the same model as above, mammograms performed over 20 years provide a RRR of 36%, i.e., 4.9 per 1,000 decrease in death from breast cancer divided by the baseline rate (in the unscreened group) of 14 per 1,000.25 In this case as in others, the RRR (36%) is a much larger number than the ARR (0.5%), and so it is not surprising that brochures that aim to encourage patients to get regular mammograms generally present RRR if numbers are given at all.13 Research confirms that patients are more likely to accept a preventive intervention when its benefit is described in terms of RRR than ARR and are least likely to accept when NNT is given.22

Other screening tests offer similar levels of risk reduction, so the same framing issues arise. For example, colon cancer screening with annual fecal occult blood testing over 18 years produces an ARR of dying of colon cancer over this period of just 4.6 per 1,000 (0.46%).27 In other words, 217 patients must undergo annual screening for 18 years to prevent one death from colon cancer. But the RRR is 31%, obtained by dividing the ARR by the baseline rate of death from colon cancer during this time period (roughly 15 per 1,000).

ARGUMENTS FOR PROVIDING ABSOLUTE RISK AND BENEFIT DATA

A number of experts argue that patients should always be given information about risks and benefits using absolute probabilities.29 Some favor natural frequencies,35 while others are comfortable with other absolute measures, such as ARR or NNS.2,6,7,9 As mentioned above, this position is motivated by the worry that giving less information violates the ethical principle of respect for autonomy, since such patients will not have enough information to make an adequately informed decision.18,21 For example, a patient who is told just the RRR of mammography may fail to understand the small number of patients who will benefit or the large number who must be screened to prevent one death from breast cancer. In addition, without information about absolute risk reduction, it is impossible to compare the value of different available preventive services or to fully weigh the chance of benefit against the risk of harm.2

Some argue that interactive computer programs—often called patient decision aids (PtDAs)—could do a good job of providing such complete information.2,6,8 There is a growing body of literature on introducing PtDAs into preventive medicine,6,28 and a recent set of guidelines states that they should provide data in terms of absolute probabilities.9 According to these guidelines and other discussions, providing just RRR or failing to give numbers at all is not an acceptable level of disclosure.3,4,6,29

PROBLEMS WITH PROVIDING ABSOLUTE RISK AND BENEFIT DATA

While this position is motivated by important ethical principles, we believe that there are significant difficulties that have not been adequately discussed. The biggest problems stem from the danger that patients will not understand the information provided or will use the information in irrational ways. Research shows that a large percentage of adults in the USA have difficulty understanding numerical concepts in general and that they have particular difficulty with probability statements.3034 And although these problems with numeracy impact the understanding of RRR numbers as well, research shows that patients have a better understanding of this measure than ARR, NNT, or a combination of different ones.32 Studies also have shown limitations in the ability of physicians to interpret statistics in this area.35

While some theorists advocate using graphs rather than numbers to convey absolute risk and benefit data,5,36 research shows that patients also have significant problems understanding charts, tables, and other illustrations.8,37 For example, a chart of 1,000 stick-figures printed in various colors to denote different outcomes, a popular way to graphically convey information about natural frequencies, can be difficult for patients to interpret and apply to a personal decision whether to be screened.8,37

Psychological research shows, further, that even well-educated, intelligent people do a poor job making decisions based on small probabilities. Irrational parts of human cognition—referred to as heuristics or biases by psychologists—may lead people to assign excessive importance to events that are quite unlikely (e.g., according to Prospect theory38), or to underestimate the importance of such events (e.g., because of the optimism bias3941 or the threshold bias42). In any particular case, the way that the information about absolute risks or benefits is presented may determine the patient’s perception as much as the data themselves, depending on which heuristics come into play.42 These aspects of human cognition have led some theorists to conclude that numbers do not play a key role in human decisions about how to act in the face of risk.43,44

All these observations raise important questions about the value of providing absolute risk and benefit data to patients considering recommended screening tests such as mammography. If a given type of data will not help patients do a better job of making decisions reflecting their values and desires, then it will not further their autonomy.45

DISCUSSION

Advocates of disclosure of absolute risks and benefits may respond to evidence about possible misunderstanding or misuse of the information by arguing that health-care providers simply need to do better a better job educating patients. Initiatives could aim at improving numeracy and counteracting irrational heuristics and could seek to present information that integrates risk and benefit data about multiple screening tests.

But this proposal must be evaluated in light of the challenges of educating patients sufficiently and the resources that would be required to do so. Doctor visits are already overcrowded with managing acute problems and chronic diseases and instituting an ever-growing list of preventive steps.46 While some of the education could be done by other health-care providers, such as nurses or other staff, limitations in availability and expertise would have to be addressed.47 Also, although PtDAs could play a key role in informing patients, there would most likely still need to be dedicated efforts by doctors or others to answer questions and provide follow up discussion.47 Finally, all these activities would incur expense for an uncompensated activity in a health-care system whose costs are already growing beyond all bounds.

Balancing these issues—the possible advantages of disclosing absolute risk and benefit against the resources required to do it right—requires careful examination of the relevant ethical principles. And while respect for autonomy is central to health-care ethics, it can be difficult to clarify what level of disclosure or understanding is necessary for a specific patient in a specific situation. Different patients, with varying interests, goals, and levels of education, may well need different levels of information to adequately consent to a medical intervention.18,45,48,49 This variability supports an approach where patients are given a standard body of information and are then given an opportunity to ask questions or request more information. Research confirms that people want varying amounts of information concerning their medical care.4951

Ethical principles provide little guidance on whether data about absolute risks and benefits should be part of the standard disclosure or should be seen as additional information that some may want. One precept requires that each patient be given any information that a reasonable person would want to know.18 And although absolute risk and benefit data are certainly relevant to a complete consideration, it seems possible that this sort of data—which is confusing to many and may not play a central role in human cognition—may be something that would be desired by some reasonable patients but not by others. In addition, some have argued that low-risk, well-supported interventions may require significantly less disclosure and discussion than other interventions.52,53

These issues emphasize the challenge of articulating the ideal of patient autonomy and balancing it against other medical goals, such as beneficence (doing what is best for the patient).10 While there has been a long tradition in western medical ethics of focusing on autonomy, that prioritization has now been critiqued.49,54 And there is clearly an issue of beneficence involved when health-care providers give information that may lead their patients to reject preventive services that have been proven to reduce morbidity or mortality. For many interventions, patient uptake drops when additional information concerning risk and benefit is provided, even when those data generally support the intervention.23,55,56 Admittedly, if a certain sort of information is central to decision-making, then its disclosure is mandatory despite any effect on well-being. For example, it would be unethical (and illegal) to withhold information about the risks of operative complications from heart surgery. But this is not the case for data about absolute probabilities of risk and benefit in screening tests. Benefit and harm of such tests must be discussed, for instance, but it is much less clear what level of precision is necessary.

Hearing this, some will sense paternalism and reject such considerations out of hand. And while this concern is important—nobody wants a return to doctor-knows-best—it should not lead us to disregard the concerns raised above. The simple fact is that medicine has multiple goals, not just providing any and all information that might be relevant.49,54 In almost all of our daily decisions, and even in most medical contexts, absolute risk and benefit data are not available or supplied.

In the end, numerous considerations should come into play when deciding whether absolute risk and benefit data will be presented to patients, and in what form, when discussing recommended screening tests. Similar issues will come up in other settings of preventive care, such as when patients are considering long-term preventive treatments such as taking medication for high blood pressure or choosing to have less well-supported tests. In all these areas, decisions about how much information should be disclosed to all patients must be made in light of careful consideration of patient understanding and possible impacts on uptake and well-being, using all applicable ethical principles.

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Thomas Imperiale, MD, and Greg Sachs, MD, for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. We would also like to thank audiences who participated in discussion of earlier versions of this work at the Seminars in Medical Humanities and Bioethics, Medical Humanities Program, Indiana University School of Medicine, Indianapolis, IN, USA and at the Poynter Health Care Ethics Seminar, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN, USA.

The authors were supported in part by grants from the Indiana Genomics Initiative, which is funded by the Lilly Endowment (PHS, EMM), and from the Richard M. Fairbanks Foundation to the Indiana University Center for Bioethics (PHS, EMM).

Conflict of Interest Dr. Meslin serves as a consultant to Eli Lilly and Company, Indianapolis.

References

  • 1.General Medical Council. Seeking patients’ consent: the ethical considerations. [Internet]. London; c1998-2006. Accessed 7 March 2008. Available from: http://www.gmc-uk.org/guidance/current/library/consent.asp#33.
  • 2.Thornton H, Edwards A, Baum M. Women need better information about routine mammography. BMJ. 2003;327(7406):101–103. doi: 10.1136/bmj.327.7406.101. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Gigerenzer G. Why does framing influence judgment? J Gen Intern Med. 2003;18(11):960–961. doi: 10.1046/j.1525-1497.2003.30901.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Gigerenzer G, Edwards A. Simple tools for understanding risks: from innumeracy to insight. BMJ. 2003;327(7417):741–744. doi: 10.1136/bmj.327.7417.741. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Paling J. Strategies to help patients understand risks. BMJ. 2003;327(7417):745–748. doi: 10.1136/bmj.327.7417.745. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Barratt A, Trevena L, Davey HM, McCaffery K. Use of decision aids to support informed choices about screening. BMJ. 2004;329(7464):507–510. doi: 10.1136/bmj.329.7464.507. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Thomson R, Edwards A, Grey J. Risk communication in the clinical consultation. Clin Med. 2005;5(5):465–469. doi: 10.7861/clinmedicine.5-5-465. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Trevena LJ, Davey HM, Barratt A, Butow P, Caldwell P. A systematic review on communicating with patients about evidence. J Eval Clin Pract. 2006;12(1):13–23. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2753.2005.00596.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Elwyn G, O’Connor A, Stacey D, Volk R, Edwards A, Coulter A, et al. Developing a quality criteria framework for patient decision aids: online international Delphi consensus process. BMJ. 2006;333(7565):417. doi: 10.1136/bmj.38926.629329.AE. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Beauchamp T, Childress J. Principles of biomedical ethics. 5. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2001. p. 472. [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Braddock CH, Fihn SD, Levinson W, Jonsen AR, Pearlman RA. How doctors and patients discuss routine clinical decisions informed decision making in the outpatient setting. J Gen Intern Med. 1997;12(6):339–345. doi: 10.1046/j.1525-1497.1997.00057.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Braddock CH, III, Edwards KA, Hasenberg NM, Laidley TL, Levinson W. Informed decision making in outpatient practice: time to get back to basics. JAMA. 1999;282(24):2313–2320. doi: 10.1001/jama.282.24.2313. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Slaytor EK, Ward JE. How risks of breast cancer and benefits of screening are communicated to women: analysis of 58 pamphlets. BMJ. 1998;317(7153):263–264. doi: 10.1136/bmj.317.7153.263. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Jorgensen KJ, Gotzsche PC. Presentation on websites of possible benefits and harms from screening for breast cancer: cross sectional study. BMJ. 2004;328(7432):148. doi: 10.1136/bmj.328.7432.148. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Chamot E, Perneger TV. Misconceptions about efficacy of mammography screening: a public health dilemma. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2001;55(11):799–803. doi: 10.1136/jech.55.11.799. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Domenighetti G, D’Avanzo B, Egger M, Berrino F, Perneger T, Mosconi P, et al. Women’s perception of the benefits of mammography screening: population-based survey in four countries [see comment] Int J Epidemiol. 2003;32(5):816–821. doi: 10.1093/ije/dyg257. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Schwartz LM, Woloshin S, Fowler FJ, Jr, Welch HG. Enthusiasm for cancer screening in the United States. JAMA. 2004;291(1):71–78. doi: 10.1001/jama.291.1.71. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Faden RR, Beauchamp TL. A history and theory of informed consent. New York: Oxford University Press; 1986. p. 408. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Frosch DL, Kaplan RM. Shared decision making in clinical medicine: past research and future directions. Am J Prev Med. 1999;17(4):285–294. doi: 10.1016/S0749-3797(99)00097-5. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Sieber WJ, Kaplan RM. Informed adherence: the need for shared medical decision making. Control Clin Trials. 2000;21(5 Suppl):233S–240S. doi: 10.1016/S0197-2456(00)00084-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Sheridan SL, Harris RP, Woolf SH. Shared decision making about screening and chemoprevention. A suggested approach from the U.S. Preventive Services Task Force. Am J Prev Med. 2004;26(1):56–66. doi: 10.1016/j.amepre.2003.09.011. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Misselbrook D, Armstrong D. Patients’ responses to risk information about the benefits of treating hypertension [see comment] Br J Gen Pract. 2001;51(465):276–279. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Edwards A, Elwyn G, Covey J, Matthews E, Pill R. Presenting risk information—a review of the effects of “framing” and other manipulations on patient outcomes. J Health Commun. 2001;6(1):61–82. doi: 10.1080/10810730150501413. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Agency for Healthcare Research and Quality (AHRQ). U.S. Preventive Services Task Force (USPSTF). [Internet] Rockville, MD; 2008 [updated 2008; cited 2008 March 7]; Available from: http://www.ahrq.gov/clinic/uspstfix.htm
  • 25.Barratt A, Howard K, Irwig L, Salkeld G, Houssami N. Model of outcomes of screening mammography: information to support informed choices. BMJ. 2005;330(7497):936. doi: 10.1136/bmj.38398.469479.8F. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26.Rembold CM. Number needed to screen: development of a statistic for disease screening. BMJ. 1998;317(7154):307–312. doi: 10.1136/bmj.317.7154.307. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Mandel JS, Church TR, Ederer F, Bond JH. Colorectal cancer mortality: effectiveness of biennial screening for fecal occult blood. J Natl Cancer Inst. 1999;91(5):434–437. doi: 10.1093/jnci/91.5.434. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28.O’Connor AM, Rostom A, Fiset V, Tetroe J, Entwistle V, Llewellyn-Thomas H, et al. Decision aids for patients facing health treatment or screening decisions: systematic review. BMJ. 1999;319(7212):731–734. doi: 10.1136/bmj.319.7212.731. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Skolbekken JA. Communicating the risk reduction achieved by cholesterol reducing drugs [see comment] BMJ. 1998;316(7149):1956–1958. doi: 10.1136/bmj.316.7149.1956. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Schwartz LM, Woloshin S, Black WC, Welch HG. The role of numeracy in understanding the benefit of screening mammography. Ann Intern Med. 1997;127(11):966–972. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-127-11-199712010-00003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Vahabi M. The impact of health communication on health-related decision making: A review of evidence. Health Educ. 2007;107(1):27–41. doi: 10.1108/09654280710716860. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Sheridan SL, Pignone MP, Lewis CL. A randomized comparison of patients’ understanding of number needed to treat and other common risk reduction formats. J Gen Intern Med. 2003;18(11):884–892. doi: 10.1046/j.1525-1497.2003.21102.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Lipkus IM, Samsa G, Rimer BK. General performance on a numeracy scale among highly educated samples. Med Decis Mak. 2001;21(1):37–44. doi: 10.1177/0272989X0102100105. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Woloshin S, Schwartz LM, Welch HG. The effectiveness of a primer to help people understand risk: two randomized trials in distinct populations. Ann Intern Med. 2007;146(4):256–265. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-146-4-200702200-00004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Hoffrage U, Gigerenzer G. Using natural frequencies to improve diagnostic inferences. Acad Med. 1998;73(5):538–540. doi: 10.1097/00001888-199805000-00024. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Edwards A, Elwyn G, Mulley A. Explaining risks: turning numerical data into meaningful pictures. BMJ. 2002;324(7341):827–830. doi: 10.1136/bmj.324.7341.827. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Hoffman JR, Wilkes MS, Day FC, Bell DS, Higa JK. The roulette wheel: an aid to informed decision making. PLoS Medicine. 2006;3(6), June 1. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  • 38.Kahneman D, Tversky A. Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica: J Econom Soc. 1979;47(2):263–292. [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Bowling A, Ebrahim S. Measuring patients’ preferences for treatment and perceptions of risk. Qual Health Care. 2001;10(Suppl 1):i2–i8. doi: 10.1136/qhc.0100002... [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40.Weinstein ND. Unrealistic optimism about future life events. J Pers Soc Psychol. 1980;39:806–820. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.39.5.806. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 41.McKenna FP. It won’t happen to me: unrealistic optimism or illusion of control? Br J Psychol. 1993;84(1):39–50. [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Baron J. Thinking and deciding. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2000. p. 570. [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Reyna VF. How people make decisions that involve risk. A dual-processes approach. Curr Dir Psychol Sci. 2004;13(2):60–66. doi: 10.1111/j.0963-7214.2004.00275.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.Lloyd AJ. The extent of patients’ understanding of the risk of treatments. Qual Saf Health Care. 2001;10:14i-8. doi: 10.1136/qhc.0100014... [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45.O’Neill O. Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2002. p. 228. [Google Scholar]
  • 46.Yarnall KSH, Pollak KI, Ostbye T, Krause KM, Michener JL. Primary care: is there enough time for prevention? Am J Public Health. 2003;93(4):635–641. doi: 10.2105/ajph.93.4.635. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Woolf SH, Chan EC, Harris R, Sheridan SL, Braddock CH, 3rd, Kaplan RM, et al. Promoting informed choice: transforming health care to dispense knowledge for decision making. Ann Intern Med. 2005;143(4):293–300. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-143-4-200508160-00010. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Manson NC, O’Neill O. Rethinking informed consent in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2007. p. 226. [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Schneider CE. The practice of autonomy: patients, doctors, and medical decisions. New York: Oxford University Press; 1998. [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Say R, Murtagh M, Thomson R. Patients’ preference for involvement in medical decision making: a narrative review. Patient Educ Couns. 2006;60(2):102–114. doi: 10.1016/j.pec.2005.02.003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Ende J, Kazis L, Ash A, Moskowitz MA. Measuring patients’ desire for autonomy: decision making and information-seeking preferences among medical patients. J Gen Intern Med. 1989;4(1):23–30. doi: 10.1007/BF02596485. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Whitney SN. A new model of medical decisions: exploring the limits of shared decision making. Med Decis Mak. 2003;23(4):275–280. doi: 10.1177/0272989X03256006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53.Whitney SN, McGuire AL, McCullough LB. A typology of shared decision making, informed consent, and simple consent. Ann Intern Med. 2004;140(1):54–59. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-140-1-200401060-00012. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54.Tauber AI. Patient autonomy and the ethics of responsibility. Cambridge: MIT Press; 2005. [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Adab P, Marshall T, Rouse A, Randhawa B, Sangha H, Bhangoo N. Randomised controlled trial of the effect of evidence based information on women’s willingness to participate in cervical cancer screening. J Epidemiol Community Health. 2003;57(8):589–593. doi: 10.1136/jech.57.8.589. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Wolf AMD, Schorling JB. Does informed consent alter elderly patients’ preferences for colorectal cancer screening? Results of a randomized trial. J Gen Intern Med. 2000;15(1):24–30. doi: 10.1046/j.1525-1497.2000.01079.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Journal of General Internal Medicine are provided here courtesy of Society of General Internal Medicine

RESOURCES