Abstract
Following the publication of the Weatherall report on the use of non‐human primates in research, this paper reflects on how to provide appropriate and ethical models for research beneficial to humankind. Two of the main justifications for the use of non‐human primates in biomedical research are analysed. These are the “least‐harm/greatest‐good” argument and the “capacity” argument. This paper argues that these are equally applicable when considering whether humans are appropriate subjects of biomedical research.
Keywords: biomedical research, research subjects, primates
The recent publication of the Weatherall report on the use of non‐human primates in research1 offers an occasion to reflect on how to provide appropriate and ethical research models for research to benefit humankind. The central goal of the working group which produced this report was to consider the scientific case for the use of non‐human primates in medical research in the UK. The report concentrated its investigation on the major areas in which non‐human primate research is currently taking place: infectious diseases and neuroscience. (In studying infectious diseases it is the differences in the immune systems between the non‐human primates and other animals which render them better models, and in the neurosciences it is the similarity of their brain neural circuitry to that of humans.) It was noted that most research within these fields is carried out by the pharmaceutical industry for drug development and toxicology studies. Primates are preferred to other animal models for this type of research because of their “similarities with human physiological and behavioural characteristics” (p 60).1
Given that biomedical research as a whole, and research in communicable diseases and the neurosciences in particular, may reap vast benefits for humankind, saving lives and decreasing disease morbidity, it is imperative that it is carried out. The question, however, is who or what are the appropriate subjects of such research. The Weatherall report deals solely with biomedical research as applied to non‐human primates and, to that end, includes a commendable section on the ethics of the use of non‐human primates for this. The issues discussed included, but were not restricted to, the moral status of non‐human primates, cost–benefit analyses, personhood, sentience and intelligence, and reached the conclusion that
The justification for the continued use of non‐human primates in research is that their use is required lest greater harm occur (p 130).1
The construction of these arguments produced by the Weatherall committee appears to be both logically and ethically sound. However, it also appears that the key arguments used which indicate why this research should be carried out in non‐human primates could also indicate why such research ought to be carried out in human primates. If this is true, and I will argue in this paper that it is, then one comes to the inescapable conclusion that human rather than non‐human primates are the appropriate subjects of this type of biomedical research.
The least harm and the greatest good
This justification cited above is based upon “the fact that the numbers of non‐human primates used any medical experiment are very small and ... the number of humans whose suffering is ameliorated is often very large” (p130).1 This is essentially a utilitarian argument involving the balancing of cost versus benefit. On this type of analysis, having taken into account the relative suffering of non‐human primates versus that of human primates, and the relatively small numbers of non‐human primates used versus the potentially huge benefit for a large number of humans, it does seem ethically justifiable to use non‐human primates in medical research.
However, while these are robust arguments for the use of non‐human primates in medical research, they are also very good arguments for indicating why such research ought to be carried out in human primates. This type of utilitarian argumentation would endorse the use of a relatively small number of humans for use in medical research and would, in combination with scientific evidence, make the use of humans ethically preferable. Given that the scientific case for the use of non‐human primates rests on their similarity to humans, the only scientifically better model would be actual humans. It might be argued that it is often easier to control for experimental variables within animal populations than within human populations. However, aberrant outcomes are more likely when experiments are on non‐humans as opposed to humans. This is because no matter how much care is taken to control for external parameters, there may be biological differences which cannot be controlled for. Despite intrahuman variation, essentially the physiology remains within fixed bounds. In addition, it is clear that we cannot derive final and conclusive results from animal and non‐human primate experimentation; if we could, there would be no phase I, II or III clinical trials in humans. Therefore, we must seriously consider the case for using a very small number of humans for the large number whose suffering would be ameliorated. What exactly this might entail will be discussed later in the paper.
This might be a contentious claim, but if the use of humans in such research is not morally acceptable but the use of non‐human primates is, we are committed to giving a robust reason why. It is unjustifiable to decide that such a course of action is permissible by virtue of the non‐human status of some primates alone. To do this would be tantamount to what Singer calls speciesism2 and is void of decent moral justification in the same way that sexism and racism are. We must, therefore, ask ourselves what the morally relevant differences are (if any) between humans and non‐human primates (and indeed between the higher non‐human primates and the lower ones) that would justify our treating them differently.
More alike than we think
One way of doing this might be to look at the characteristics possessed by each that might have a bearing on their moral status. This is important because in trying to decide whether it is justifiable to carry out biomedical research on non‐human primates rather than humans, we need to decide if the moral status of non‐human primates is equivalent to that of humans, or is less, or whether they are of no moral concern to us at all.
The relevant characteristics, and the crux of this moral difference, according to the report, seems to be “a difference in self‐awareness, cognitive awareness, cognitive capacities and sentience between most non‐human primates and most humans” (p 130).1 This is a differentiation based on capacity, and again it looks like a strong argument for the use of non‐human primates in biomedical research. As Rachels maintains:
[I]nsofar as a human and a member of another species are similar, they should be treated similarly, while to the extent that they are different, they should be treated differently. (p 109)3
This is a similar notion to what Singer means when he says that animals deserve an “equal consideration”.4 It represents the fact that if one makes a moral judgement with respect to specific criteria for a human, an animal that meets those criteria is entitled to an equivalent judgement.
In this respect, non‐human primates, while being our closest relatives on the evolutionary scale, do appear to have less self‐awareness, cognitive awareness and cognitive capacities than normal adult human primates (for further reading, see box). The problem, however, again becomes the fact that this type of reasoning is as applicable to inter‐human considerations as it is to those involving non‐human primate versus human primate. Not all humans have equal capacities, and if it is justifiable to use capacity to differentiate a non‐human primates and human primates, it is justifiable to use it to differentiate among humans themselves. Babies, young children, some severely disabled adults and persons in a permanent vegetative state display less capacity than fully competent human adults and also less than some non‐human primates.
Further reading
For further reading on the minds of animals, see:
Gallup GGJ. Chimpanzees: self‐recognition. Science 1970;167:86–7.
Gallup GGJ, Anderson JR, Shillito DJ. In: Beckoff M, Allen C, Burghardt GM, eds. The cognitive animal: empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002.
Hauser MD. Wild minds: what animals really think. New York: Owl Books, 2001.
Roth G, Dicke U. Evolution of the brain and intelligence. Trends Cogn Sci 2005;9:250–7.
For two guidelines on the use of human subjects, see:
Oviedo Convention of the Council of Europe (Convention for the protection of Human Rights and dignity of the human being with regards to the application of biology and medicine: Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine – ETS No.: 164)
Directive 2001/20.EC of the European Parliament and of the Council.
For further discussion of rights in general, see:
Jones P. Rights. Basingstoke: MacMillan, 1994
Raz J. On the Nature of Rights. Mind XCIII, 1984;
Sumner LW. The Moral Foundation of Rights. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987
In: Waldron J, Ed. Theories of Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984.
Of course, we could decide that these characteristics are not relevant. However, if we are to disregard and ignore the similarities and differences in capacity of non‐human primates that might attest to their moral status, then in the interests of consistency we ought to disregard those same characteristics in humans as well. And were we to do that, there could be no good reason not to experiment on those humans whose level of capacity is similar to that of most non‐human primates.
Humans, primates and international guidelines
Relatively few non‐human primates are used in biomedical research. (In the EU in 2002, 10 362 non‐human primates were used in experiments,5 and in the USA in the same year, 52 279.6) As pointed out above, it is this fact, coupled with the benefit to a large number of people, which forms part of the justification for using them in this type of research. I made the case that this argument, coupled with the scientific superiority of humans as the research model, means that we ought to seriously consider the case for replacing the very small number of non‐human primates with an equally small number of humans.
Many more humans than non‐numan primates are involved as subjects in biomedical research. A quick look at just four clinical trials involving human participants verifies this: the four ISIS (International Study of Infarct Survival) trials investigating the treatment of patients with acute myocardial infarction involved 16 027,7 17 187,8 41 2999 and 58 05010 participants, or a total of 132 563. Most of this research on humans is on fully competent adults who have consented to participate, and most of this research could be quantified as mild to moderate as regards risk or invasiveness. This would be research which might involve observational studies, studies where biological samples such as blood were needed, studies involving minor surgery such as creating skin lesions, or toxicity studies for drugs. The inherent risks, however, are ones which the (presumably) rational and competent adults who do take part in medical research are willing to take.
Of those humans who do participate in biomedical research, there are also a few who lack capacity and who are, therefore, not legally competent to consent to their own involvement. We still permit their participation as research subjects, but they are heavily protected by national and international research guidelines (see box). These guidelines have been developed with the express purpose of protecting individuals whose lack of capacity makes them vulnerable. The International Ethical Guidelines for Biomedical Research produced by the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences (CIOMS) say that “special justification” is needed for the participation in research of vulnerable individuals,11 a category that includes those with “limited capacity”. It seems to me that most non‐human primates are of a level of capacity that, if they were human, would fall into this category of vulnerably persons and would therefore be protected. If, as argued previously, we cannot differentiate between non‐human primates and humans merely on the grounds of species membership, and if there is no difference in capacity between non‐human primates and some humans, then surely these guidelines ought to protect both.
If that is so, then such guidelines ought to be consistently applied. One particular provision of interest, which appears in slightly different formulations in the Declaration of Helsinki and the CIOMS guidelines, says essentially that medical research on vulnerable individuals must be of benefit either to that individual directly or to people of that individual's kind. The Declaration of Helsinki states:
These groups should not be included in research unless the research is necessary to promote the health of the population represented and this research cannot instead be performed on legally competent persons. (section B(24))12
Similarly, the CIOMS guidelines state:
[T]he research is intended to obtain knowledge that will lead to improved diagnosis, prevention or treatment of diseases or other health problems characteristic of, or unique to, the vulnerable class—either the actual subjects or other similarly situated members of the vulnerable class.11
At least research on vulnerable humans is of benefit to humankind. It is difficult to see how the medical research carried out on non‐human primates can ever be said to be of direct benefit to them or to their kind. If we want to concede that this research is of benefit to their kind, then we must be their kind. And if we accept this as true, we are another step closer to accepting that there does not appear to be a difference between human and non‐human primates that justifies medical research on them but not us.
Severely invasive research
The kind of research discussed above, in which humans, vulnerable or not, participate, involves procedures or studies deemed to be mild to moderately risky or invasive. The majority of research carried out on the non‐human primates also falls into this category.13 Fully competent adults already make decisions to participate in the majority research that carries this level of risk or invasiveness. For that reason, there is at least the presumption that we could get such people to participate in all research of this manner. Although the difference in capacities experienced by non‐human primates and adult humans probably means that the two groups' experience of suffering are qualitatively different, it is not clear that this difference directs us to using non‐human primates for such research. Although competent adult humans might experience some suffering, they can at least understand and rationalise it. These reasons, combined with the fact that humans are the scientifically preferable models for research to benefit humankind, mean that there can be no good moral reason why we ought to use primates for this type of research.
However, it is likely that we would be left with a small portion of biomedical research that no competent adult would consent to participate in. This is research of a highly invasive or risky nature—the type that the Weatherall report1 maintains would be “totally inappropriate” in humans (p 36). Examples of this might be research that involves being infected with viral agents such HIV (pp 43–57) or that requires the production of experimental brain lesions (p 67). What are we to do in this situation? Are we simply not to conduct this type of research?
It may be that to refrain from this type of research is the right course of action, but if, as intimated in the Weatherall report, the real dangers posed to individuals and to humankind by certain illnesses and diseases are so immense, we may be remiss in our moral duties if we do not carry out this research. If this is the case, such dangers, coupled with the potential benefits to humankind from this type of research, might constitute that special justification required by the CIOMS guidelines for the participation of those vulnerable individuals mentioned earlier. Of course, as also mentioned earlier, consistency would dictate that we include both vulnerable human and non‐human primates of limited capacity in this.
This is not to say that I am putting forward a case for ascribing rights to non‐human primates, or indeed to animals in general. I am not. But then neither am I advocating the ascription of rights to humans of a similar level of capacity. If one thinks, as I do, that the normative function of rights is the protection of autonomy, then individuals that do not have the requisite capacity for autonomy cannot be rights‐holders (see box). That said, the moral supportability of our treatment of any being does not reside in rights. That a being is not deemed to be a rights‐holder is not to say that either the vulnerable human or non‐human primate is outwith our sphere of moral concern.
Conclusion
It seems that the benchmark of whether it is morally justifiable to conduct certain types of medical research on non‐human primates is whether we would carry out that research on humans of a similar level of capacity. If we decide that research on these types of human is acceptable, then it is celebration time for the non‐human primates, as they are no longer needed because the scientific evidence tells us that research on humans is better. If, on the other hand, we decide that research on this category of human is not ethically acceptable, then I can see no good reason why it ought to be conducted on non‐human primates. Either way, it seems that the non‐human primates win.
Acknowledgements
I would to thank the reviewers for their helpful comments.
Footnotes
There are many stages and facets of biomedical research, and not all involve non‐human primates or even humans. Stages of research include basic and applied research, in vitro research on cell and tissue cultures and in vivo research in the form of preclinical animal trials and clinical trials in humans.
There may be a capacity‐based argument that would point to research on vulnerable humans being less desirable than that on non‐human primates. This argument appeals not to the capacities of the vulnerable humans themselves but rather those of their nearest and dearest. It is likely that the use of these humans would generate suffering for those people who care for them. This might perhaps give us a reason not to use them in this manner.
Competing interests: None
References
- 1.Report of Sir David Weatherall's working group The use of non‐human primates in research
- 2.Singer P. Animal liberation: a new ethics for our treatment of animals. New York: New York Review/Random House, 1975
- 3.Rachels J. Darwin, species and morality. Monist 19877098–113. [Google Scholar]
- 4.Singer P. All animals are equal. In: Regan T, Singer P, eds. Animal rights and human obligations. New Jersey: Prentice‐Hall, 1976154
- 5.Commission of the European Communities Fourth report on the statistics on the number of animals used for experimental and other scientific purposes in the member states of the European Union. 2005.
- 6.USDA Annual report of enforcement for the fiscal year 2002. Riverdale MD: USDA, 2003
- 7. ISIS‐1 First International Study of Infarct Survival Collaborative Group. Randomised trial of intravenous atenolol among 16 027 cases of suspected acute myocardial infarction—ISIS‐1. Lancet 1986257–66. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. ISIS‐2 (Second International Study of Infarct Survival) Collaborative Group. Randomised trial of intravenous streptokinase, oral aspirin, both, or neither among 17 187 cases of suspected acute myocardial infarction—ISIS‐2. Lancet 19882349–360. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9. ISIS‐3 (Third International Study of Infarct Survival) Collaborative Group. ISIS‐3: a randomised comparison of streptokinase vs tissue plasminogen activator vs anistreplase and of aspirin plus heparin vs aspirin alone among 41 299 cases of suspected acute myocardial infarction. Lancet 1992339753–770. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10. ISIS‐4 (Fourth International Study of Infarct Survival) Collaborative Group. ISIS‐4: a randomised factorial trial assessing early oral captopril, oral mononitrate, and intravenous magnesium sulphate in 58 050 patients with suspected myocardial infarction. Lancet 1995345669–684. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.The Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences(CIOMS) International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects. Guideline 13. Geneva: CIOMS, 2002. http://www.cioms.ch/frame_guidelines_nov_2002.htm (accessed 13 July 2007) [PubMed]
- 12.World Medical Association World Medical Association Declaration of Helsinki: ethical principles for medical research involving human subjects. WMA: Ferney‐Voltaire (France), 2004, http://www.wma.net/e/policy/b3.htm (accessed 13 July 2007)
- 13.Home Office Statistics of scientific procedures on living animals: Great Britain 2004. London: Stationery Office, 2006. http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/pdfs06/spanimals05.pdf [DOI] [PubMed]