Abstract
Should face transplants be undertaken? This article examines the ethical problems involved from the perspective of the recipient, looking particularly at the question of identity, the donor and the donor's family, and the disfigured community and society more generally. Concern is expressed that full face transplants are going ahead.
So it has happened. According to the New Scientist,i the case was made out by a team in Louisville, Kentucky, USA, in 2004,1 and the first partial face transplant was performed in Lyon, France, in November 2005 on a woman whose face was mutilated by a dog.2ii Full face transplants are to go ahead at the Royal Free Hospital in Hampstead, North London, UK.3iii It has been called “the boldest cut”,4 and “a glorified sewing job”.4
The Royal College of Surgeons in the UK5,6 and the Comité Consultatif National d' Ethique Pour les Sciences de la Vie et de la Santé in France7 have cautioned against it. But even before the flurry of activity in late 2005, it was clear that this latest venture in transplantation technology would proceed: there were statements of intent—a prospectus almost—from clinicians and researchers, most notably from a University of Louisville team.1
It is sometimes suggested that face transplants are morally analogous to limb transplants.1,8 There have been hand transplants—some 20 transplants since the first was performed on Clint Hallam in 1998.9,10 Many of the problems are the same, but the ethical dilemmas that surround face transplants are, arguably, of a different dimension.11 And caution is rightly being argued in the case of hand transplants too.12,13 There must be concern that scientific advance is being urged before legal frameworks can be established, and before ethicists have debated the morality of the surgery.iv There may also be a danger that clinicians will seek to legitimate what they propose to do by finding justifications within ethicists on whom they can rely—even if no one else does.v
This paper considers the ethical issues of face transplants. Another paper will explore some of the legal questions. In considering the ethical issues, it is important to separate those which principally concern the recipient from those which affect the donor and the donor's family. But we must not ignore the interests of the disfigured community and those of society at large, and consideration will be given to those two interest groups as well.
The recipient
Transplants of organs are now not uncommon, and although some questions remain contentious (eg, whether they can be sold14), on the whole their therapeutic use is uncontroversial. The same applies to skin grafts and reconstructive surgery.15 Some parts of our body are more important than others. We cannot live without certain vital organs, such as the heart, but these are internal to us and are visible neither to ourselves nor to others. But even so, recipients of an organ may feel that their identity is being changed in some way. This was in part the reason why in 1999, a 15‐year‐old girl from Newcastle, UK, objected to having a heart transplant.vi And why many feel uncomfortable about xenotransplantation16: one person is quoted in a recent Swedish study as fearing he might start “grunting” if part of a pig was transplanted into him.17
These problems are, we believe, accentuated when a face is transplanted. As an expressive part of our body, it represents identity in a way no other part of the body does. It is the most intimate, the most individual characteristic of our body. It is what we recognise as ourselves and what others recognise as us. It is not surprising that we can talk of “losing face”. The 2004 Royal College of Surgeons report holds that:
The face is central to our understanding of our identity. Faces help us understand who we are and where we come from. (Morris et al,6 p 333)
And Margaret Lock18 has argued that
… donated organs very often represent much more than merely biological parts; the life with which they are animated is experienced by recipients as personified …
And, she notes, some recipients of organ transplants report “they experience embodiment in a radically different way after a transplant”.18 Embodiment may well be a key to our understanding of what makes face transplants different for potential recipients.
It is vital that central to the doctor–patient relationship is patient self‐determination or autonomy.19 But just as the importance of this can be exaggerated, with other considerations being neglected,20 so it is all too easy to concentrate on self‐determination and to neglect other aspects of personhood. As Dworkin20 has observed, not only do we “have bodies but … we are bodies”. The importance of this in the context of face transplants cannot be underestimated. There are implications for consent. It may even be an area where paternalism has a strong claim to our attention.21
Disfigured persons are, it may be assumed, a particularly vulnerable group. One of their main problems centres on social interaction. They are also subjected to unwanted intrusions, such as staring or unwelcome comments. Clarke quotes Macgregor that people who have experienced disfiguring burns
… in their attempts to go about their daily lives … are subjected to visual and verbal assaults, and a level of familiarity from strangers [including] naked stares, startled reactions, “double takes”, whispering, remarks, furtive looks, curiosity, personal questions, advice, manifestations of pity or aversion, laughter, ridicule and outright avoidance.22
Clarke22 (p 128) is of the view that the disfigured may have “very low self‐esteem and expectations about life chances”. They may even be seen as “freaks” or curiosities as the so‐called “elephant man” was in the late 19th century,23,24,25 and as conjoined twins and transsexuals are still today.26
This is likely to lead in many cases to a desperate, compulsive desire to alleviate their suffering. Recently published research4,27vii suggests that people are
… willing to trade more years for a hand, should they need one, than a foot, and more years for a larynx than a hand. But the body part for which people are willing to trade most years of life is by some margin a transplanted face. For a face they would take on even more risk than for a kidney.
If this research is convincing—and we must express some scepticism as far too little information is vouchsafedviii—it suggests that the disfigured may well feel compelled to consent to a face transplant.
On any interpretation of informed consent (and this legal doctrine is not uniform across jurisdictions), a potential recipient would have to be alerted to substantial risks. Nor would there be any space for “therapeutic privilege” (particularly if the procedure is characterised as therapeutic research rather than treatment).
That there are risks is accepted even by advocates of face transplants (Wiggins et al,1 pp 3–5). There are risks of infections,28 of malignancies29 and of end‐organ toxicity.30 There is an increased chance of getting diabetes and kidney disease. And there are psychological risks as well:
… a desperation that creates unrealistic hopes, fears that [the] body will reject the transplant, guilt feelings about the death of the donor, difficulty conforming to the treatment regimen and its side–effects, and a sense of personal responsibility for the success of the procedure. (Wiggins et al,1 pp 4–5)
In addition, there is the possible trauma in adjusting to a new identity. No doubt, recipients can be taught to manage failure, but is any work being directed to such coping strategies or are the resources and the skills being devoted to the technology?31 Nor should it be forgotten that families may need psychological support as well.
Is consent then possible? Cunningham et al (the Louisville team) are in no doubt “ultimately, the decision to accept risk to receive the benefits of a given treatment belongs to the patient”.27 In standard cases, this must of course be so. But is this “treatment” or is it experimental research?ix And how is risk to be perceived? The assumption of advocates of face transplants, as represented in the article by Cunningham et al, is that this can be proved objectively. But is it rather the product of values, such as experience, trust, a sense of control, regret and fear?32
Risks are acknowledged, but also, we suspect, underestimated. For example, insufficient attention has been given to the problem likely to be caused by a paucity of donors. Publicity about transplants may well stimulate demand, and this will exceed supply. What will be the effect of being on a waiting list? What is the relationship, if any, between coping strategies before and after a transplant? Given the significance of the face, the recipient will have a different life after a transplant. It may be a better one, it may be worse. Adjustment is bound to be difficult. There may initially be psychological shock of a dimension equal to or exceeding that caused by the disfigurement. There may be a sense of violation. Margareta Sanner33 found that recipients of organ donations felt “their personality, behaviour or attitude have changed because they have received in their body an organ from another individual”.
Adjustment is bound to be difficult. Most of our communications are facial.34 Experiences after a transplant are bound to be different. The recipient may acquire different interests and even, it has been suggested, different eating habits.34
It is not clear whether potential recipients will be given any choice or any opportunity to view the prospective donor (alive or dead). Given the importance of the face, ought we to give the recipients a say, an opportunity to participate in the decision‐making process? And should this extend further to their family? And why not to the donor's family as well?
There will be matching for blood and tissue, but what about age? And sex? Could a man choose a woman's face, in which case the prospect looms of face transplantation as part of a sex reassignment operation? And what about race? And skin colour? And if a market were to develop,35 would value depend on attractiveness? Might it become possible to buy the face of a model or a football icon? Could face banks eventually emerge?
To whom will face transplants be offered? Butler et al36 (of the Royal Free Hospital) admit:
Selecting appropriate recipients will be difficult and will take a considerable time. This process [will] involve identifying those patients who would have functional benefit and who also had realistic expectations of the procedure. The patient would have to be determined and resolute in adhering to the prolonged rehabilitation and the need for chronic immunosuppression. The patient must be robust enough to cope with these challenges and the psychological effects involved.
So, appearance by itself is not enough to warrant surgery. Butler et al admit that:
… it may be that people who have well‐developed coping strategies and good social skills cope well with disfigurement, while those who find life generally more challenging, also cope poorly with disfigurement. The concern for us as clinicians … is that this group may also cope poorly with face transplantation; thus, the very group who might benefit most are those who are least likely to cope …, particularly if the results fall short of their expectations. (Butler et al,36 p 17)
Does this mean that those for whom a transplant is clinically indicated are also those least able to give genuine consent? And, concomitantly, that those robust enough to consent can cope adequately without and so do not need this surgical intervention?
It is generally accepted that an autonomous decision is generated by an individual who acts intentionally, with comprehension and without “controlling influences”.37 The disfiguring condition experienced by those for whom a face transplant is to be offered may well constitute just that controlling influence. And what comprehension can the potential recipient have when the surgeons themselves know so little about the benefits and the harms? The Louisville team contents itself with an acknowledgment that “… we have gained as much knowledge as we can though scientific studies; and therefore additional knowledge can be attained only by actually performing the experimental procedure and following the outcome” (Wiggins et al,1 p 8).
This is a candid admission that we are still in the realm of medical experimentation, which itself has implications for the question of consent.
Of course, voluntariness is a matter of degree. As Joel Feinberg38 has observed:
At one end of a spectrum are the acts and choices [which are] perfectly voluntary. Only the actions of normal adult human beings in full control of their deliberative faculties can qualify for that description. Such persons assume a risk in a perfectly voluntary way if they shoulder it when fully informed of all relevant facts and contingencies …, and in the absence of all coercive pressure. In the ideal case, there must be calmness and deliberateness …, no distracting or unsettling emotions, no neurotic compulsion, no misunderstanding. To whatever extent there is compulsion, misinformation, clouded judgment … or impaired reasoning … to that extent the choice falls short of perfect voluntariness.
Looked at in this way, it may be said that a face transplant falls so far short of the “ideal” as to raise doubts not just as to whether a potential recipient can consent, but also whether the offer is one that can ethically be made.
One answer to this may be to draw an analogy with the desperately ill, for example, those with AIDS, prepared to throw caution to the wind, willing to try anything, in the hope that they—or for the more altruistic those who come after them—may be cured.39 Should we refuse to sanction risk‐taking behaviour?40 Or should we rather be prepared to accept that individuals can consent to a procedure that may harm them but may also redound (ultimately) to the collective good? Our concern is that we are here focusing on a particularly vulnerable group of people. Nor is there any evidence, as there is, at least anecdotally, with those with AIDS that participation may be motivated by a desire to promote a more healthy population.
We know quite a lot about the physical risks involved.1,7 We know rather less about the psychological effects a face transplant may have. The recipients may be seeking normality, but may feel less normal than they did when possessed with their disfigured face. The recipients will look neither like themselves nor like the donor: instead they will have a composite identity.41 The effects of this on different people will be different.42,43 Indeed, the effects on men and women may be different, although no evidence exists that the gender question has been investigated.
The emphasis has been on whether face transplants can be accomplished, on the science and the technology. It is therefore not surprising that the body is seen here, as elsewhere, as a machine “operating according to material principles”.44 According to Leder,44 “We stretch toward the Cartesian dream of remaking the body at will” (p 239). Christian Byk45 has asked:
Hidden by the law under the concept of a person, but empirically revealed by our biomedical techniques, will the human body come to have the status of a thing to be utilized, to be dismembered for the benefit of the individual or the community, each claiming rights in it? Will the law … dig the grave of the living human body? Will it become a thing?
Commodification of the human body is not new, but facial transplantation may be the most striking example of the results of this reductionist view of the human body. It seeks to resolve the problems of disfigurement by disposing of the damaged face and replacing it with the face of another. But does it resolve anything? Our bodies and our persons are inextricably interconnected. Thus, “disease is not simply something that effects a biological body in the abstract”.x Rather, “illness is uniquely experienced by the particular person whose body it happens to be”.x Our relationship with our bodies is not like our relationship with things or even with other persons. As Sartre46 explained, “… the lived body is an embodied consciousness which engages and is engaged in the surrounding world … The parts of the body … form an intentional unity in the worldly engagement of the experiencing subject.”
The body is not an unconscious machine. Rather, “the self is an integrated whole whose subjectivity is embodied, and whose body is ‘mentalized' through and through” (Leder,44 p 254).
Organ transplantation generally should force us to confront questions about the nature of the self and about identity. Where, as a result of a transplant, a change in physical appearance is the result, as with limb and face transplantation, these questions are all the more urgent and compelling. Kay Toombs has argued that medical treatments that alter the body's appearance “represent a threat to one's sense of personal identity [… because] changes in physical appearance cause one to experience the body as unfamiliar and unrecognisable—as no longer one's own” (Leder,44 p 89). It is to replace one disfigurement by another. We do not know how people will react to a conflation of self and “other”, to a kind of “third identity”. Does it not pose a threat to human dignity?41
Nor do we know how others will react to the recipient of a face transplant. The recipients' family, friends and acquaintances may not recognise in them the person they knew and loved before the transplant took place. Will they react and interact in the same way? And how will others react? Initially—indeed for a long time—it may be predicted that people, spurred on by the media, will be curious. And protecting the privacy of recipients will not be easy.47,48 They may be subjected to intrusions (staring, comments, etc) not altogether different from what occurred before the transplant. Some recipients may come to regret having had the transplant, as Clint Hallam, the recipient of the first hand transplant, did (Dickenson and Widdershoven,9 p 116). A transplanted hand can be amputated, as Hallam's was. But a face? It may be anticipated that those who are less than happy with their transplants will experience psychological disorders. There may even be suicides. Certainly, there will be some who will recognise in the drug regimen a medicine's attempt to impose on them a new persona, and who may thus cease to take them with all the consequences this will have.
Whatever the aesthetic result, we cannot escape the conclusion that the recipient will have neither a “normal” appearance nor a unique identity. We are far from grasping the implications of a face transplant.
But, defenders of the face transplant will respond that those with disfigured faces are entitled to exercise autonomy. We do not deny that it may theoretically be possible, even in the circumstances, to make an autonomous decision to receive a face transplant. The extent of the patient's vulnerability or ability to act without excessive compulsion is something that must be judged on an individual case‐by‐case basis. In addition, although there is an alarming lack of information about both the risks and benefits (even aesthetic or medical) of face transplants, we recognise the danger of subjecting individual decisions to external standards of rationality. It is arguable that as long as there exists “accurate knowledge, at a higher level, of the scope and limits [of this] first‐level knowledge” (Feinberg,38 p 160) it may be said that the patient's decision “was made in ignorance, as Aristotle would say, but ‘not by reason of ignorance'” (Feinberg,38 pp 150–61). However, the obligations of those who wish to transplant faces go beyond paying lip service to patient autonomy. Autonomy is emphasised because we believe in human dignity and respect for persons.49 But we cannot respect persons and their dignity merely by recognising that they have autonomy. Joffe et al50 argue that we should add “respect for the body, respect for the family, respect for community, respect for culture, respect for the moral value (dignity) of the individual, and respect for the personal narrative”.
And Rendtorff,51 writing of the basic ethical principles in European bioethics, has noted that theyxi find their “conceptual and empirical foundation in anthropology of the bodily‐incarnated human being”. There is, he continues, “an ongoing personalisation of the body”.50 The gap between this bioethical discourse and face transplant advocacy could not be greater. Face transplants may be regarded as the latest, perhaps even the final step, in medicine's depersonalisation of human beings.
The donors and their family
Much less attention has focused on the donor. Neither the Royal College of Surgeons in the UK5,6 nor the French Comité Consultatif7 considers the issue of the face transplants from the perspective of the donor.
To say that the donor will be dead—it is envisaged that it is from cadavers that faces will be removed—is far from an answer for two reasons. These reasons are related. First, there is the decision to donate. But this is not like the decision to donate other organs after death. And this is because, secondly, the donor will die and in a disembodied form live on. What was the stuff of drama to earlier generations (Hamlet's father's ghost reappearing or the Commendatore returning in Mozart's Don Giovanni) is set for contemporary realisation.
Should we therefore question a donor's motivation? Should it matter what this is? Should offers to donate be ruled out if the motivation is less altruistic than, literally, face saving? A form of “life after death”, a “second coming”, self‐aggrandisement? Perhaps even a desire to haunt family, friends and colleagues? We do not suggest that non‐altruistic donations will be common; they probably will be most uncommon. Nevertheless, it would be foolhardy not to alert ourselves to the contingency.
Does this mean that donations should be anonymous? The Louisville prospectus is clear that they should: “All reasonable efforts should be made to protect the donor's anonymity”.1,4 They acknowledge, however, that “the research team cannot prevent someone (e.g. a member or friend of the donor's family) who knows about the case from publicizing information on his or her own”.5,6 It is predictable that recipients will be curious as to the identity of the donor. This may be so in the case of other transplants too, but, given the significance of a face transplant for identity, it may be supposed that it will be greater and more common here. What has been conceptualised in another context (adoption) as “bewilderment”,52 and has led there to a search for origins, may have similar results here too. Anonymity may be best for donor's family, and it may encourage, or at least not discourage, donations. But it will deny the recipients their psychological need to know. Whether the interest in knowledge about facial origins is sufficiently strong to warrant designating it a “right to know” is debatable. A compromise solution would be to let the recipient know basic information (age, occupation, religion) without divulging identifying information. Some donors might see it as a way of living on after death. But it is in the interests of their families that identifying information is withheld, as it is in the interest of the recipient to have some basic information.
The deceased's family is likely to think of him or her in terms of his or her face. This may be especially so where the deceased is a child or a young person. In such cases there may even be a desire for a continuing a quasi‐relationship by means of contact. Has the effect of this continuing quasi‐relationship on the grieving process been thought through? Is it something that potential donors will grasp? It is most unlikely, indeed, undesirable, that any right to contact will develop. But denial could lead to frustration, anger and trauma, in extreme cases perhaps even to a macabre form of stalking. It is also possible that donation may deepen the family's sense of loss.
This leads on to a discussion of the consent process. It would be unthinkable to use the faces of dead persons without consent. It would also be in breach of the English law. We do not know how many people will leave their faces. Donor registration forms, which identify parts such as kidneys, heart, liver, cornea, lungs and pancreas, do not direct a potential donor's attention to face or limbs. Nor is it the least bit surprising, given both the novelty and ethical complexity of such transplants. Should we assume that those who request that “any part” of their body may be used would include within this their face? Caution at this stage, if nothing else, suggests that this would be an inappropriate interpretation. Nor is it likely that donors will specifically exclude faces or limbs from the remit of their donation: few will contemplate the possibility.
The Human Tissue Act 2004 unsurprisingly does not consider this issue.53 It states that the use of a body or the removal of organs of a deceased person for transplantation is lawful if done with “appropriate consent” (Section 1 (1) (b) and (c)). In the case of adults, this is their consent (this does not have to be in writing: Section 3 (6) (a)). If there is consent, in law, that is the end of the matter. But looked at ethically, concerns persist. Individuals who consent to their kidneys being used after their death can readily appreciate that their donation will save lives: its implications are only therapeutic. Can we be sure that those who consent to the use postmortem examination of their face are aware of the implications of what they are doing? The transplant is therapeutic, of course, but it is much else as well. It will have an effect on others, including the donor's family, in ways in which the donation of an internal organ is unlikely to have.
The Human Tissue Act 2004 also permits adults to nominate a person or persons to act in their interests after death (Section 4). This appointment can be made orally (if made before two witnesses together (Section 4 (4)). Consent may then be given or withheld by the person so nominated. We may assume that the likeliest nominee is a close family member, but it does not have to be and may well be someone else. If no one is nominated, authority is vested in a person who stood in a “qualifying relationship” to the deceased: these are statutorily ranked (see the ranking in Section 27 (4)). Consent by family or a nominated friend raises critical problems. We witnessed a similar quandary when, in a notorious case,xii sperm was removed from a dying man so that his partner could give birth to his posthumous child (she in fact had two sons as a result).
The case caused a furore, and comparisons were made, if overdramatically, with rape.54 There is some evidence that Stephen Blood would have wanted his widow to bear his child. But can a similar exercise of “substituted judgement” be made where a deceased person has expressed no opinion on what should happen to his face? The decision would have to be in the deceased's interests, but what these are will often be contentious. There is surely a distinction between living on through a son, as Stephen Blood might have been said to be doing, and living on because a stranger now has your face.
Too little attention has been given to these consent issues. Without a clear framework of rules it is difficult to see how transplants can be justified. The Louisville team does, we note, espouse the idea of a “subject advocate”.1,4 This may assist prospective recipients in making informed decisions, but donors and their families need support as well.
The disfigured community and society
The effect that face transplants could have on the disfigured community cannot be ignored. The Louisville team acknowledges this problem:
… A successful facial transplant might be interpreted as conveying the message that a good quality of life cannot be achieved by people with disfiguring conditions.1,4
But they do not appear to be unduly concerned by this. Even if we accept the premise that disfigured persons are unable to enjoy the good life, it is not their disfigurement that constitutes the barrier. Rather it is the reactions of others, of the society around them, which make them feel at least uncomfortable and often marginalised and stigmatised. The source of their pain on this interpretation is not their disfigured face, but societal intolerance. Of course, this problem is not unique to face transplants but generally applies to issues of disability.
If successful face transplants were to become routine, this is likely to increase. Those with disfigurement will be seen as even more deviant than before. Those who refuse a face transplant and those for whom one is not possible—perhaps, those who cannot bear the cost, a real consideration where there is no socialised medicine—may suffer more than they do now. They must come to terms with their face as those with other “deficits” must. It is more difficult to accept identity in a hostile environment. If society were more inviting, more tolerant, more accommodating, there might be less demand for face transplants. As was pointed out by Strauss55: “when something is correctable, our willingness to accept it as untouched is reduced”.
Disfigurement is, of course, a social construct. As such it is shaped by cultural forces.14,41,56 The disfigured are only such in relation to those whose face comes closer to the norm. A face transplant “industry” could shift the benchmark, bringing more within the purview of disfigurements and increasing a potential clientele. We can learn lessons from the cosmetic surgery industry that promotes an ideal of beauty,57 and manufactures demand its services. Of particular relevance is the way cosmetic surgery has been used to “normalise” the faces of people with Down's syndrome.58,59 We have no doubt that this is intended to alleviate suffering, and may well do so. But has the effect been calculated on those with Down's syndrome who do not undergo the surgery, for whatever reason? Does the exercise of choice increase the options of others or foreclose them?
As far as society generally is concerned, there are other considerations that may be briefly addressed. What will be the effect on other organ and tissue donations? If face transplants attract adverse publicity in the media, there may be a knock‐on effect: a fall in the number of those willing to donate, a drop in those carrying donor cards and greater reluctance on the part of families to facilitate donations after death. The maintenance of altruism is heavily dependent on the preservation of a relationship of trust between the community dealing with transplants and the general public. We can afford nothing that will undermine this.
We cannot ignore the question of resource allocation, although there is a tendency to do so. It is not just the surgery that must be accounted for, or the counselling, but lifelong immunosuppressive drugs. It is not a factor that features in the Louisville manifesto: the assumption is that face transplants will be privately financed or paid for by medical insurance. Dickenson and Widdershoven,9 in discussing limb transplants, do consider this issue. It is at least of equal concern here. In the UK, the National Institute of Health and Clinical Excellence has had, inter alia, to resolve the question of β‐interferons for patients with multiple sclerosis,60 and infertility treatment for the infertile.61,62 The National Institute of Health and Clinical Excellence report was published in February 2004. Its decisions on both these issues were far from uncontroversial. Could it recommend face transplants on the National Health Service without courting major controversy? Or should face transplants only be available for those who can afford to meet the costs themselves, remembering of course that on any definition of cost, they would be meeting only a fraction of these?
And disfigurement is, we have already noted, a social construct. The need for a face transplant cannot be medically determined, as the need for a heart transplant or kidney transplant can. The desire for a face transplant is only in part a factor of disfigurement. The level of tolerance may vary with the degree of vanity and of course affluence. Could face transplants become the latest symbol of affluence, the “fashion label” of the early 21st century? Could we arrive at a time when only the poor need to be “ugly”?
Conclusion
We believe the case for face transplants has not yet been made. Others, writing before the first transplant was performed, have urged caution.5,6,7,41,63 It is our view that no further face transplants take place until a long‐term assessment—perhaps in 3 years—of this first such attempt is made. Our arguments against face transplants do not rely, as many would, on the “yuk” factor, although we would not discount its importance.64 The case against is pitched on three levels that examine the perspectives of the recipient, the donor and the donor's family, and the disfigured community and society more generally. The problems, particularly the psychological problems, for the recipient have been recognised, even by advocates of face transplants. Problems that may beset the donor and the donor's family and the disfigured community have, we believe, been underestimated.
Footnotes
iCover story of the New Scientist, 29 May 2004.
iiSee also The Guardian, 28 November 2005. The recipient gave an interview in the Daily Mail, 10 December 2005: 1, 20, 22. It had been reported that 12 people were queuing in Cleveland, Ohio, USA, to be chosen for the first transplants according to The Times, 19 September 2005: 13. See also The Guardian, 19 September 2005: 15.
iiiAlso reported in The Guardian, 16 December 2005:1.
ivA point made by Hedley J. In: W and BvH [2002] 1 FLR 1008, 1009. He refers to “an imbalance between our scientific and ethical capacities”.
vNote the Louisville team's reliance on Moore FD. We surely cannot be alone in having missed his 1988 and 1989 articles which feature prominently in reference 1.
viRe M [1999] 2 FLR 1097, 1100.
viiThis is based on a presentation at the Annual Meeting of the Association of Plastic Surgery in Seattle in 2002 by Banis et al.
viiiWe do not know what the respondents were told, and there is sparse information regarding their social profile.
ixAccording to the Royal College of Surgeons, “any surgeon contemplating performing facial transplantation should regard the procedure as experimental and subject it to the evaluation of an independent committee” (Royal College of Surgeons in England, p 17).
xA point made by Toombs K. What does it mean to be somebody? Phenomenological reflections and ethical quandaries. In Leder, p 73.
xiSee BIOMED II project “Basic Ethical Principles in European Bioethics and Biolaw” 1995–1998.
xiiR v Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority ex p. Blood [1999] Fam 151.
Competing interests: None.
The origins of this article are a Master's Dissertation submitted to the University of London, London, UK, in 2004 by PAJ and a paper presented to the International Association of Bioethics, 7th World Congress, Sydney, Australia, in November 2004, as well as to a staff research seminar in the Law Faculty of University College London, London, UK, in October 2004 by MF. Another paper on face transplants was presented to the Congress and is published as Huxtable R, Woodley J. Gaining face or losing face? Framing the debate on face transplants. Bioethics 2005;19:505–22. Neither was MF present at this presentation, nor, so far as is known, were the authors of the Bioethics article present at MF's presentation.
References
- 1.Wiggins O, Barker J, Martinez S.et al On the ethics of facial transplantation research. Am J Bioethics 200441–12. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Spurgeon B. Surgeons pleased with patient's progress after face transplant. BMJ 20053311359. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Butler P, Clarke A, Hettiaratchy S. Facial transplantation: a new option in reconstruction of severe facial injury. BMJ 20053311349–1350. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Concar D. The boldest cut. New Scientist 29 May 200432–37. [PubMed]
- 5.Royal College of Surgeons in England Facial transplantation: Working Party Report. London: Royal College of Surgeons, 2003 [DOI] [PubMed]
- 6.Morris P, Bradley J A, Doyal L.et al Facial transplantation: A Working Party Report from the Royal College of Surgeons in England. Transplantation 200477330–338. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Comité Consultatif National d'Ethique Pour Les Sciences de la Vie et de la Santé L'Allotransplantation de Tissu Composite (ATC) au Niveau de la Face (Greffe Totale ou Partielle d'un Visage). Opinion 82: 1–20, 2004. http://www.ccne‐ethique.fr (accessed 28 Nov 2006)
- 8.Siegler M. Ethical issues in innovative surgery: should we attempt a cadaveric hand transplantation in a human subject? Transplant Proc 1998302779–2782. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Dickenson D, Widdershoven G. Ethical issues in limb transplants. Bioethics 200115110–124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Goldenberg S. Medical miracles: five years on, the world's first hand transplant patient is thriving. The Guardian, 17 February 200410
- 11.Baylis F. A face is not just like a hand: pace Barker. Am J Bioethics 2004430–32. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Jones N. Concerns about human hand transplantation in the 21st century. J Hand Surg 200227A771–787. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Breidenbach W. A position statement in support of hand transplantation. J Hand Surg 200227A760–770. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Mahoney J. The market for human tissue. Va Law Rev 200086163–223. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Tardy M E. Ethics and integrity in facial plastic surgery: imperatives for the 21st century. Facial Plast Surg 199511111–115. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Cartwright W. The pig, the transplant surgeon, and the Nuffield Council. Med Law Rev 19964250–269. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Sanner M A. People's feelings and ideas about receiving transplants of different origins: questions of life and death, identity and nature's border. Clin Transplant 20011519–27. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Lock M. Human Body Parts as Therapeutic Tools: Contradictory Discourses and Transformed Subjectivities. Qualitative Health Research 2002121409. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Faden R, Beauchamp T L.A History and Theory of Informed Consent. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986
- 20.Dworkin G.The Theory and Practice of Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988113
- 21.Savulescu J. Rational non‐interventional paternalism: why doctors ought to make judgments of what is best for their patients. J Med Ethics 199521327–331. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Clarke A. psychosocial aspects of facial disfigurement. Psychol Health Med 19994127–142. [Google Scholar]
- 23.Bogdan R.Freak show: presenting human oddities for amusement and profit. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988
- 24.Fiedler L.Freaks: myths and images of the secret self. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1978
- 25.Bonderson J.Freaks: the pig‐faced lady of Manchester Square and other medical marvels. Stroud: Tempus, 2006
- 26.Dreger A D.Hermaphrodites and the medical invention of sex. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998
- 27.Cunningham M, Majzoub R, Brouha P.et al Risk acceptance in composite tissue allotransplantation reconstructive procedures—instrument design and validation. Eur J Trauma 20043012–16. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Daoud A J, Schroeder T J, Shah M.et al A study of the safety and efficacy of mycophenolate mofetil, prednisome and cyclosporine and mycophenolate mofetil, and prednisone and tacrolimus. Transplant Proc 1998304079–4081. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Matthew T H. A blinded, long‐term, randomized multicenter study of mycophenolate mofetil in cadareric renal transplantation: results at three years. Transplantation 1998651450–1454. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Johnson C, Ahsan N, Gonwa W.et al Randomised trial of tacrolimus in combination with azathioprine or mychophenolate mofetil versus cyclosporine (neoral) with mycophenolate mofetil after cadaveric kidney transplantation. Transplantation 200069834–841. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Christensen A J. Effect of family environment and donor source on patient quality of life following renal transplantation. Health Psychol 200221468. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Smith R D. is regret theory an alternative basis for estimating the value of healthcare interventions? Health Policy 199637105–115. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Sanner M A. transplant recipients' conceptions of three key phenomena in transplantation: the organ donation, the organ donor, and the organ transplant. Clin Transplant 200317391–400. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Sharp L A. Organ transplantation as a transformative experience: anthropological insights into the restructuring of the self. Med Anthropol Q 19959357–389. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Cohen L R. Increasing the supply of transplant organs: the virtues of a futures market. George Washington Law Rev 1990581–62. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Butler P, Clarke A, Ashcroft R E. Face transplantation: when and for whom? Am J Bioethics 2004416–17. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Beauchamp T, Childress J.Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 200159
- 38.Feinberg J.Harm To self. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986104
- 39.Schűklenk U, Hogan C. Patient access to experimental drugs and aids clinical trial designs: ethical issues. Camb Q Healthcare Ethics 19965400–409. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Sunstein C R. Social norms and social roles. Columbia Law Rev 199696903–968. [Google Scholar]
- 41.Hartman R G. Face value: challenges of transplant technology. Am J Law Med 2005317–46. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Kafka F.Metamorphosis (originally published in German in 1915). London: Penguin, 2000
- 43.Turney J.Frankenstein's footsteps. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998
- 44.Leder D. Whose body? What body? In: Cherry MJ, ed, Persons and their bodies: rights, responsibilities, relationships. Dordrecht: Kluwer 1999236
- 45.Byk C. The impact of biomedical developments on the legal theory of the mind‐body relationship. Philosophy and Medicine. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999269
- 46.Sartre J ‐ P.Being and nothingness (First published as L'Etre et le Néant. Paris: Gallimard, 1943), London: Routledge 195885
- 47.Morreim E H. High profile research and the media: the case of the Abiocor artificial heart. Hastings Cent Rep 20043411–24. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Morreim E H. About face: down playing the role of the press in facial transplantation research. Am J Bioethics 2004427–29. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.O'Neill O.Autonomy and trust in bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002
- 50.Joffe S, Mannochia M, Weeks J C.et al What do patients value in their hospital care? An empirical perspective on autonomy centred bioethics. J Med Ethics 200329103–108. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Rendtorff J. Basic ethical principles in european bioethics: autonomy, dignity, integrity and vulnerability. Med Health Care Philos 20025235–244. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Sants H. Genealogical bewilderment in children with substitute parents. Br J Med Psychol 19654732–42. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Mason J K, Laurie G T.Law and medical ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006493
- 54.Morgan D, Lee R. In the name of the father? Ex parte Blood: dealing with novelty and anomaly, Mod Law Rev 199760840–856. [Google Scholar]
- 55.Strauss R P. Ethical and social concerns in facial surgical decision making. Plast Reconstruct Surg 198372727. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Hacking I.The social construction of what?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999
- 57.Haiken E.Venus envy: a history of cosmetic surgery. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997
- 58.Katz S, Kravetz S. Facial plastic surgery for persons with Down syndrome: research findings and their professional and social implications. Am J Mental Retard 198994101–110. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Frank A W. Emily's scars: surgical shapings, technoluze, and bioethics. Hastings Cent Rep 20043418–29. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Filippini G, Munari L, Incorvaia B. Interferons in relapsing‐remitting multiple sclerosis: a systematic review. Lancet 2003361545–552. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Uniacke S. IVF and the right to reproduce. Bioethics 19871241–254. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Ryan M. Should government fund assisted reproduction techniques? A study using willingness to pay. Appl Econ 199729841–849. [Google Scholar]
- 63.Huxtable R, Woodley J. Gaining face or losing face? The debate on face transplants. Bioethics 200519505–522. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 64.Midgley M. Biotechnology and monstrosity—why we should pay attention to the “yuk factor”. Hastings Cent Rep 2000307–15. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]