Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2010 Sep 1.
Published in final edited form as: Trends Cogn Sci. 2009 Sep 1;13(9):368–369. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.07.003

Response to Koch: Elaborations on the SCP hypothesis

Biyu J He 1,*, Marcus E Raichle 1
PMCID: PMC2904980  NIHMSID: NIHMS141377  PMID: 20644654

We appreciate the excellent questions raised by Koch [1] in response to our article [2], and the opportunity to elaborate on our ideas further here.

Koch asked whether we propose that it is the existence of the SCP per se, or the activity of associated pyramidal cells, that is crucial for consciousness. We noted in the legend of Fig. 3a in the original paper: “We propose that long-lasting synaptic activities in superficial layers, manifesting as SCPs in surface recording or low-frequency current source density (CSD) activity in superficial layers, carry large-scale information integration in the brain and contribute directly to conscious awareness.” So the SCP is only our measurement of the responsible neuronal activities. If clever ways are found to eliminate the SCP while leaving all responsible neuronal communications intact, or even extract the responsible information transfer and integration relationships and implement those in artificial media [3], then the quality of consciousness would remain the same in our view. However, our interest here is in the physiological underpinnings of consciousness, starting with the human brain and the brain of those species that are most similar to ours. The SCP might be a marker of such physiological activities, as we tentatively propose.

Second, Koch suggested that the information content of the SCP, and field potentials in general, is too low to support conscious experiences. “Think of every frame in every movie… each one corresponds to a discrete visual experience.” We suppose that if that was true, there would never have been any movies, the production of which depends precisely on the visual system’s ability to fuse adjacent stimuli into a coherent image. Existing evidence suggests that the time scale at which conscious experience seems to flow is at tens to hundreds of milliseconds [3]. Successive presentations of word stimuli get fused into a single percept if they are separated by less than 80 ms [4]. In fact, the slowness of consciousness is supported by many standard psychological paradigms, including backward masking (~100 ms), attentional blink (~500 ms), psychological refractory period (~200 ms), and postdiction (~80 ms) [5,6]. Still, the frequency range of the SCP (< 4 Hz) might seem too slow for the 80-ms-rate at which visual perception is updated. This, however, is not a problem because negative SCP shifts in different neuronal groups can be integrated into conscious experience with temporal lags much shorter than a full SCP cycle, i.e., one neuronal group can become activated and contribute to conscious perception before the activity in the previous neuronal group drops and returns to baseline. Viewed in a different way, the amount of information the brain can process at any moment is huge, but most information processing is carried out unconsciously, and the amount of information in bits/sec (defined in the classical sense) accessible by consciousness is very small [7,8]. However, the information contributing to consciousness might be a privileged integrated kind that has had the chaff discarded [3,8].

Hence, the information contained in the SCP might not be less than that in the flow of consciousness. How can this view be reconciled with findings that individual neurons’ responses correlate with conscious perception? Crick wrote in 1984 [9]: “Since a neuron can usually be made to fire by several different combinations of its inputs, the significance of its firing is necessarily ambiguous. It is thus a reasonable deduction that this ambiguity can be removed, at least in part, by the firing pattern of an assembly of cells.” We add to this comment that concerted firing of hundreds or thousands of presynaptic neurons is the rule rather than exception [10], which would contribute to field potentials without significant information loss, and that the real computations in a neuron are carried out at the dendrites. Therefore, field potentials might indeed be a better marker for network computations than a single neuron’s firing.

Our proposal that the information carried by specific thalamocortical feedforward pathways has to be processed by superficial-layer neurons and integrated with other activities therein to contribute to conscious awareness is not dissimilar to previous ideas that the afferent pathways, though crucial for providing a basis for the content of conscious awareness, do not contribute directly to conscious experience [3,11,12]. The same would also apply to the efferent pathways from the cerebral cortex. As for the nonspecific thalamic pathways, and the cortico-cortical feedback connections that originate from layer V and terminate in superficial layers, those were included in our proposal (see Fig. 3a).

Our comparison with previous work was not intended to suggest that there have been no physiologically-based theories of consciousness before our proposal. In fact, Edelman, Crick and Koch were first to advocate a neurobiological approach to consciousness. A number of physiologically-based accounts have been proposed, including but not limited to reentrant [13] or recurrent [14] processing, 40-Hz synchrony [15], global neuronal workspace (which included neuronal firing, gamma-frequency activity and the P300)[12]. Further, a formal mathematical framework has been put forward that contains significant heuristic value for empirical quests on consciousness [3]. We are very fortunate indeed to follow these pioneers’ footsteps. Our idea is different from, but not mutually exclusive with previous hypotheses. For example, as discussed in our original paper, neuronal firing and gamma-frequency activity, as well as P300 amplitude, tend to increase during the negativity of the SCP. Moreover, the P300 appears to be simply a disruption of the ongoing negative SCP [16,17]. Therefore changes in these signals might accompany the change in the SCP, but we propose that it is the neuronal activities directly underlying the SCP that are most fundamental in contributing to conscious awareness. We look forward to future studies that examine this hypothesis.

Lastly, we did not claim that insects do not have consciousness, but rather suggested that it might be very different. The reasoning goes as follows: If the SCP is the substrate for consciousness in vertebrates, and it does not have a homolog in most invertebrates, to the best of our knowledge (the SCP is not a regular oscillation), then a different physiological process must serve as the substrate for consciousness in invertebrates, if they are indeed conscious. If the substrates are different, then it is probable, but not necessary, that the information relationships carried by them, and therefore the quality of consciousness, would also be different. Nonetheless, as we commented previously, this is a non-testable conjecture at present.

Footnotes

Publisher's Disclaimer: This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final citable form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.

References

  • 1.Koch C. The SCP is not specific enough to represent conscious content. Trends Cog Sci. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.07.002. in press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.He BJ, Raichle ME. The fMRI signal, slow cortical potential and consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci. 2009;13:302–309. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2009.04.004. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Tononi G. Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto. Biol Bull. 2008;215:216–242. doi: 10.2307/25470707. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Forget J, Buiatti M, Dehaene S. Temporal integration in visual word recognition. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2009.21300. Epub Jul 7 2009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Eagleman DM, Sejnowski TJ. Motion integration and postdiction in visual awareness. Science. 2000;287:2036–2038. doi: 10.1126/science.287.5460.2036. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Marois R, Ivanoff J. Capacity limits of information processing in the brain. Trends Cogn Sci. 2005;9:296–305. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2005.04.010. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Anderson CH, Van Essen DC, Olshausen BA. Directed visual attention and the dynamic control of information. In: Itti L, Rees G, Tsotsos J, editors. Neurobiology of Attention. Elsevier; 2005. pp. 11–17. [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Norretranders T. The User Illusion: Cutting Consciousness Down to Size. New York: Penguin Books Ltd; 1999. [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Crick F. Function of the thalamic reticular complex: the searchlight hypothesis. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 1984;81:4586–4590. doi: 10.1073/pnas.81.14.4586. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.DeWeese MR, Zador AM. Non-Gaussian membrane potential dynamics imply sparse, synchronous activity in auditory cortex. J Neurosci. 2006;26:12206–12218. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2813-06.2006. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Bachmann T. Visibility of brief images: the dual-process approach. Conscious Cogn. 1997;6:491–518. doi: 10.1006/ccog.1997.0320. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Dehaene S, Sergent C, Changeux JP. A neuronal network model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data during conscious perception. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A. 2003;100:8520–8525. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1332574100. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Edelman GM. Neural Darwinism: selection and reentrant signaling in higher brain function. Neuron. 1993;10:115–125. doi: 10.1016/0896-6273(93)90304-a. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Lamme VA, Roelfsema PR. The distinct modes of vision offered by feedforward and recurrent processing. Trends Neurosci. 2000;23:571–579. doi: 10.1016/s0166-2236(00)01657-x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Singer W. Consciousness and the binding problem. Ann N Y Acad Sci. 2001;929:123–146. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2001.tb05712.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Birbaumer N, Elbert T. P3: Byproduct of a byproduct. Behav Brain Res. 1988;11:375–377. [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Deecke L, Lang W. P300 as the resolution of negative cortical DC shifts. Behav Brain Res. 1988;11:379–381. [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES