Abstract
In this paper, I present evidence for a robust and quite general force of selection on the human life cycle. The force of selection acts in remarkably invariant ways on human life histories, despite a great abundance of demographic diversity. Human life histories are highly structured, with mortality and fertility changing substantially through the life cycle. This structure necessitates the use of structured population models to understand human life history evolution. Using such structured models, I find that the vital rates to which fitness is most sensitive are pre-reproductive survival probabilities, particularly the survival of children ages 0–4. The fact that the preponderance of selection falls on transitions related to recruitment combined with the late age at first reproduction characteristic of the human life cycle, creates a fitness bottleneck out of recruitment. Because of this, antagonistic pleiotropy with any trait that detracts from the constituent transitions to recruitment is expected. I explore the predictors of variation in the force of selection on early survival. High fertility increases the selective premium placed on early survivorship, while high life expectancy at birth decreases it.
Keywords: demography, life history theory, natural selection, human evolution
1 Introduction
Understanding variation in the life cycle is a fundamental goal of modern evolutionary biology. Species differ in the schedules at which they develop, reproduce, and die, and the fact that these features of an organism’s life cycle are so proximate to fitness suggests functional value to the observed variation (Cole, 1954; Gadgil and Bossert, 1970). The human life cycle is characterized by a great deal of variation from one population to another. For example, populations have recorded total fertility rates (the number of offspring born to a woman who survives the entirety of her reproductive span) ranging from under two in the low fertility countries of contemporary Europe and Japan to more than 14 for historical agrarian populations (Wood, 1994; Livi-Bacci, 1997; Kohler et al., 2006). Similarly, life expectancy at birth ranges from little over 20 years to an excess of 80 years (Livi-Bacci, 1997; Keyfitz and Flieger, 1990). Even in hunter-gatherer populations, there is considerable variation in both life expectancy at birth and total fertility (Howell, 1979; Early and Peters, 1990; Hill and Hurtado, 1996; Gurven and Kaplan, 2007). This variation is presumably due to the varying historical, social, and technological circumstances of different populations.
In this paper, I attempt to answer the question of how such variation in the basic inputs to fitness affects the force of selection on the human life cycle. For example, does selection push in a fundamentally different direction in a population with an expectation of life at birth of 40 and a total fertility rate of 10 compared to a population with a life expectancy of 70 and a total fertility rate of 2? Any attempt to make general statements about the functional value of human behavior clearly depends on the answer to this question. This question is important also because of the existence of major demographic transitions in human history (e.g., Notestein, 1953; Caldwell, 1982; Coale and Watkins, 1986). Does the force of selection on the human life cycle fundamentally change following demographic transitions?
There is controversy in human behavioral biology regarding the relevance of either contemporary phenotypic variation or selective pressures for understanding how selection has shaped human behavior (Vining, 1986; Tooby and Cosmides, 1990; Perusse, 1993). However, two arguments suggest that understanding how selection changes with contemporary phenotypic variation is important. First, there is considerable variation in the demography of small-scale, face-to-face societies like those that characterized the entirety of human existence throughout the Pleistocene (e.g., Gurven and Kaplan, 2007). Second, the type of long-term evolutionary stasis argued for by Tooby and Cosmides (1990), for example, is itself dependent upon stabilizing selection. Thus to understand evolutionary constancy and universality, we still need measures of selection on the life cycle.
The human life cycle has a number of peculiarities that make it challenging to understand how it has been and continues to be shaped by selection. First, the human life cycle is highly structured. In a demographic sense, structure means that mortality and fertility rates vary with age, and do so in predictable ways across ensembles of people. This structure suggests that models that treat human populations as homogeneous – as does the Pearl-Verlhurst logistic model, for example – will fail to capture the essential features of selection on human life histories. Figure 1 depicts a schematic representation of the human life cycle divided into non-overlapping five-year age classes. This figure is known as the life cycle graph and provides a great deal of important information for understanding the dynamics of a structured life cycle (Caswell, 2001).
Figure 1.
(1) Life cycle graph for an age-structured human population. Circles represent non-overlapping five-year age classes and arrows connecting them the survival probabilities, Pi between stages. Loops back to the first class represent age-specific fertilities, Fi.
Second, as with many other vertebrates, generations overlap. In a natural fertility population it is quite possible that a woman’s grandchildren can be older than her youngest children. Cant and Johnstone (2008) have argued that human generations are more separated than expected compared to other primates. Demographically, this does not matter, as the pioneering work of Thompson (1931) showed. The key point is that generations are not completely discrete. While this observation seems, at first glance, obvious and perhaps trivial, its implications for the types of models used to represent the human life cycle are profound. In particular, because generations overlap, the timing of reproduction can matter critically for fitness, particularly if the population is not assumed, a priori, to be demographically stationary. In many evolutionary studies of human behavior, the fitness measure adopted is lifetime reproductive success (e.g., Turke and Betzig, 1985; Chagnon, 1988; Voland, 1990). However, this measure only applies to discrete-generation populations that are demographically stationary. In the more general case of non-stationarity and where generations overlap, the proper measure of fitness is the rate of increase given by the Euler-Lotka equation (Charlesworth, 1994), written here for a population with discrete, non-overlapping age classes,1
(1) |
Here, α is age at first reproduction, β is age at last reproduction, the Pj are the age-specific interval survival probabilities and Fi is the fertility rate at i. Equation 1 has a unique real root. Fitness is given by this root, the multiplicative intrinsic rate of increase λ, which is defined implicitly by equation 1. The intrinsic rate of increase r is the natural logarithm of λ, divided by the length of the projection interval (which is also the width of the age-classes).
The human life cycle is characterized by an extremely late age at first reproduction (AFR). Given the potential importance of timing of reproduction for fitness, this observation is puzzling. The traditional explanation for this late age at first reproduction focuses on the development of competitive competence in populations that remain predictably in the vicinity of their carrying capacity (MacArthur and Wilson, 1967; Pianka, 1970). While this explanation certainly remains a viable contending hypothesis (e.g., Kaplan and Robson, 2002), other hypotheses may better explain this phenomenon. In addition to the late AFR, human reproductive patterns are characterized by a marked degree of iteroparity. That is, reproduction is spread out over a long reproductive span, lasting 25 years or more. Not only are the bouts of reproduction themselves drawn out over a parent’s lifetime, so is parental investment. Successful human reproduction, leading to the recruitment of offspring into the breeding pool, requires extensive, obligate parental investment (Hill et al., 2000; Lee and Kramer, 2002; Robinson et al., 2008). A notable feature of patterns of reproductive investment is that humans frequently invest heavily in two or more offspring simultaneously. A weaned child remains almost completely dependent upon his or her mother for years after weaning, while the weaned chimpanzee is economically independent of its mother (Hill et al., 2000; Goodall, 1986).
The facts that the human life history is so strongly structured and that it is characterized by overlapping generations have implications for the type of models that need to be employed in order to understand how selection acts to yield a late-breeding, highly iteroparous organism with high, obligate parental investment in multiple, simultaneously dependent offspring.
For this analysis, we would ideally like a probability sample of the human demographic experience. However, such a sample from the the diversity of human demographic experience is essentially impossible. The great majority of human history has been characterized by life in small, face-to-face societies, subject to natural fertility and relatively high mortality (particularly among infants and juveniles). Nonetheless, the great majority of reliable data on age-specific demographic schedules comes from contracepting nation-states which employ vital-event registration. The solution to this problem that I propose is to construct a space that defines the limits of human demographic variation and to explore the shape of selection around the limits of this space. This strategy of identifying points that define specific regions of a parameter space has been extremely effective in understanding past population dynamics from molecular phylogenies (Nee et al., 1995, 1996). Thus, the first goal of this paper is to define the demographic space which the human life cycle occupies. This is the launching point for more extensive analyses.
2 Human Demographic Space
Livi-Bacci (1997) suggests that the diversity of human demographic schedules can usefully be reduced to a low dimensional space defined by two summary measures: (1) life expectancy at birth e0, and (2) total fertility rate (TFR), the sum of a woman’s age-specific fertility rates across her reproductive lifespan.
I exploit the regularity of human mortality schedules to plot fitness isoclines for combinations of e0 and TFR. The definition of generation time, T, the time it takes a population growing at instantaneous rate r to increase by a factor of R0 is:
(2) |
R0 is the net reproduction ratio, the sum across the life cycle of the product of age-specific survival (Pi) and fertility (Fi),
(3) |
Here, I have written the probability of survival to age i as the product of all preceding age-specific survival probabilities (Pj) starting from the first age class. Livi-Bacci notes (1) that T is remarkably constant across human populations, and (2) R0 can be well approximated by the product of TFR and the fraction of women who survive to reproductive age, S(α). In figure 2, I plot fitness isoclines using relationships between e0 and S(α) from the Coale-Demeney West model life table family, and assuming T = 30. That is, for a given model table (which are indexed by e0), I look up the corresponding value of S(α), which I then use in the calculation.
Figure 2.
(2) Fitness isoclines for combinations of life expectancy at birth (e0) and total fertility rate (TFR). The four populations, indicated by triangles, mark the four quadrants of the space (conditional on r > 0) corresponding to high vs. low e0 and TFR. Included in the plot is Taiwan from 1906 (upward-pointing triangle), which Hamilton used in his classic (1966) perturbation analysis. See text for a discussion of the growth rates.
Figure 2 can be divided into four quadrants defined by high vs. low e0 and high vs. low TFR. I require that the populations must have a deterministic rate of annual increase r > 0. Any population with an expected growth rate less than zero is destined to extinction, so analyzing its asymptotic behavior is not rewarding. While no population can sustain 2% annual growth indefinitely either, stochastic variation in vital rates typically reduces the long-run rate of increase well below the growth rate of the average life history (Tuljapurkar, 1990).
Superimposed on the r isoclines are points for four populations which fall into each of these quadrants: !Kung (Howell, 1979), Ache (Hill and Hurtado, 1996), Venezuela in 1965 (Keyfitz and Flieger, 1990), and the contemporary United States (Martin et al., 2005; Wilmoth, 2007). 2 The first two populations are characterized by low life expectancy, while the !Kung have a low TFR and the Ache have a high TFR. The latter two populations have high life expectancy with Venezuela having high TFR and the United States having low TFR. Summary statistics of the four populations are provided in table 1.
Table 1.
Summary statistics and data sources for the four human populations analyzed
Population | Year | e0 | TFR | r (%) | Citation |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
USA | 2002 | 77 | 2.05 | 0.8 | (Martin et al., 2005; Wilmoth, 2007) |
Venezuela | 1965 | 65 | 6.5 | 3.8 | (Keyfitz and Flieger, 1990) |
Ache | forest period | 37.5 | 8.0 | 2.7 | (Hill and Hurtado, 1996) |
!Kung | pre-1974 | 34 | 4.0 | 0.7 | (Howell, 1979) |
I will use these four populations to mark corners in Livi-Bacci’s human growth space. How does selection act upon populations in different quadrants in the space? As will become clear in later sections, the specific demographic details of the population matter remarkably little for understanding the overall patterns of selection on the human life history. In a subsequent section, I will simulate life histories using model schedules of age-specific vital events to explore more fully human demographic space and understand the way the force of selection on the human life cycle is shaped by demographic inputs.
3 Fitness Sensitivities: Measuring the Force of Selection
Increasing the probability of survival at any age before the age of last reproduction while holding everything else constant will increase fitness. Similarly, increasing fertility at any age, in the absence of trade-offs, will increase fitness. However, not all changes to age-specific schedules of survival and fertility will have equivalent impacts on fitness. The rate at which fitness changes with a small change to the demographic schedules that define fitness via equation 1 is a measure of the force of selection on this human life cycle. In this section, I ask the questions: how does the force of selection change across the human life cycle? and how does variation in demographic schedules affect the force of selection?
Caswell (2001) has demonstrated the power of matrix approaches to studying structured populations and I will use a number of his tools in subsequent sections. The second edition of his book (Caswell, 2001) provides a comprehensive overview of matrix methods for demography, evolutionary and otherwise. For all the analysis in this and subsequent sections, I use the demogR library for the R statistical programming language (R Development Core Team, 2008) which was designed specifically for the construction and analysis of age-structured population models (Jones, 2007).
Here I use age-structured demographic projection matrices to examine how we expect natural selection to act upon the human life history. Projection matrices carry with them a host of powerful tools for mathematical analysis. They also have the attractive feature of mapping directly onto the life cycle graph presented in figure 1. A Leslie matrix A is a sparse, square k × k matrix, where k represents the number of age-classes. The sub-diagonal of the matrix contains the probabilities of survival from one age-class to the next (Pi), while the first row contains age-specific fertility rates (Fi). All other matrix entries are zero. There are two other important features of projection matrices for age-structured human populations. First, the human life cycle is structured by age (and not by developmental stage, size, etc.). This insures that all paths through the life cycle must pass through the first age class (i.e., infancy). While this may seem obvious, it is not always the case in organisms with complex life cycles (e.g., those with both sexual and asexual reproduction). Two properties insure that the population will converge to a stable age distribution: irreducibility (or connectedness) and primitivity. If we consider only those age classes before the termination of reproduction (i < 50, say), this insures that the life cycle graph is strongly connected (all nodes can reach each other in the life cycle graph) and the resulting projection matrix is said to be irreducible. Second, as noted in the Introduction, the human life cycle is characterized by a strong degree of iteroparity. As long as the age classes are not too wide, the age-structured life cycle graph is bound to have two consecutive age classes with non-zero fertility. This condition is sufficient to insure that the resulting matrix is primitive and will converge to a stable age distribution. For a more complete (and technical) discussion of these issues, see Keyfitz (1977) or Caswell (2001).
For the age-structured population modeled as a Leslie matrix, fitness is given by the dominant eigenvalue λ of the matrix A. A matrix with k rows and columns will have k eigenvalues (indexed in decreasing absolute value from 1 to A;), and if the conditions of irreducibility and primitivity are met, each of these k will be distinct. The Perron-Frobenius theorem insures that one of these k eigenvalues will be positive, real, and strictly greater than all other eigenvalues. Whenever the meaning is unambiguous, I drop the subscript on the dominant eigenvalue λ1, denoting it simply as λ. This eigenvalue λ is the same as the real solution to equation 1. The dominant eigenvalue λ has associated right and left eigenvectors u and v respectively (again I drop the subscript for notational simplicity). The k × 1 right eigenvector of a Leslie matrix corresponds to the stable age distribution of the population, while the 1 × k: left eigenvector corresponds to the age-specific reproductive values. Using these quantities, Caswell (1978) derived a method to calculate the partial derivative of fitness with respect to a small perturbation in some life-cycle transition. The sensitivity of λ to a perturbation in the ijth element of A is given by:
(4) |
where vi is the ith element of v and uj is the jth element of u, and it is assumed that the vectors have been scaled so that 〈v, u〉 = 1. The sensitivity of fitness is thus the product of the reproductive value of the receiving stage and the stable proportion of the donor stage.
Fitness sensitivities tell us how small changes in age-specific survival and fertility will be translated into fitness. Improvements to life-cycle transitions with high sensitivities will change fitness more than improvements to less sensitive transitions.
Figure 3c–d clearly reveals that the life-cycle transitions to which fitness is most sensitive are those of early survival, and the survival of 0–4 year-olds in particular. This, of course, is part of Hamilton’s classic result (Hamilton, 1966). However, while Hamilton’s analysis is frequently evoked to explain senescence, the fact that the force of selection is expected to be highest on infant survival (not that of higher reproductive value young adults) is rarely mentioned.
Figure 3.
(3) Demographic rates and fitness sensitivities of the four populations: (a) natural logarithms of the central death rates (nMx), (b) age-specific fertility rates, (c) sensitivities of λ to perturbations in age-specific survival, (d) sesitivities of λ to perturbations in age-specific fertility. In all plots: !Kung=solid line, Ache=long dashed line, USA=alternating long-short dahsed line, Venezuela=short dashed line.
3.1 Fitness Elasticities
A useful extension of the fitness sensitivity is the fitness elasticity. Elasticities are proportional sensitivities, measuring the corresponding increase in λ of a given increase in aij. For example, an elasticity measures by what percentage λ will change given a 1% change in the survival of 0–5 year-olds.
(5) |
Elasticities sum to unity and can be conceived – in a limited way – as representing the fraction of total selection accounted for by individual transitions. The degree to which elasticities measure the apportionment of selection to the elements of the life cycle is limited results from the fact that elasticities themselves are contingent. In particular, they measure the proportional change in fitness given a small change in a vital rate, while holding everything else constant. First, everything is very rarely held constant. Second, as selection acts on a life history, the vital rates – by definition – will change. As the vital rates change, so too will the elasticities. Nonetheless, elasticities provide a useful snapshot of the current force of selection on the life cycle conceived statically. The fitness elasticities of the four populations show a similar pattern to the sensitivities (figure 4). The highest elasticities are those of pre-reproductive survival. The elasticities of fertility – particularly early and late in the reproductive period when the absolute fertility is low – are relatively smaller than the corresponding fitness sensitivities.
Figure 4.
(4) Elasticities of fitness (λ) to perturbations in (a) age-specific survival and (b) age-specific fertility
A second structural property of fitness elasticities is that the sum of the elasticities of all outgoing transitions in a life cycle must equal the sum of the elasticities of all incoming transitions (van Groenendael et al., 1994). In terms of the matrix model, this means that the sum of elasticities for column i will be equal to the sum of elasticities for row i. In a life cycle that is structured by age, there will only be a single non-zero entry per column. In contrast there will be multiple non-zero entries along the first row of the Leslie matrix as long as the organism is iteroparous. This observation leads to the following conjecture: age-structured life cycles characterized by strong iteroparity will experience the strongest selection on survival in the first age-class.
Another way of approaching this observation is to note that the human life cycle – like the life cycle of any age-structured population – can be conceptually simplified to those events that transpire before the onset of reproduction and those that happen after its onset. The theorem of van Groenendael et al. (1994) then indicates that half of the total selection on the human life cycle falls before age at first reproduction (AFR). The summed transitions leading to AFR can be called “Recruitment.” Similarly, all life-cycle transitions occurring after AFR can be called “Reproduction.” Note that this includes the survival of reproductive-age adults. This is similar to Charnov’s decomposition of the mammalian life cycle into recruitment and adult reproductive value (Charnov, 1997). There are typically fewer transitions before AFR than there are after it in the human life cycle. Consequently, the total recruitment elasticity is more concentrated in those transitions. Furthermore, the reproduction elasticity is split between both fertility and adult survival. Survival to breeding age and subsequent recruitment into the reproductive population therefore represents the largest single contribution to human fitness. This, coupled with the extremely late AFR characteristic of the human life cycle, creates a major fitness bottleneck in juvenile recruitment.
This observation focuses attention on what selective regime favored such highly iteroparous reproduction in the human life cycle. Iteroparity is traditionally seen as a risk-spreading adaptation in variable environments (Murphy, 1968; Schaffer, 1974; Seger and Brockerman, 1987). However, the impact of environmental variability on the optimal life history in age-structured populations is more complex (Tuljapurkar, 1990; Jones, 2005). Tuljapurkar (1990) has shown that iteroparity is still the most likely outcome of selection in a variable environment for an age-structured population if the magnitude of variability is sufficiently high. At low and intermediate levels of environmental variability, more semelparous life histories can be favored.
As a strong degree of iteroparity is clearly fundamental to the human life cycle, this suggests that the selective regime which shaped the human life history was characterized by high levels of variability. This observation suggests that renewed effort should be placed into measuring the impact of environmental variability (both past and present) on human life history decisions and outcomes.
3.2 Life-Cycle Contributions to Infant Survival Sensitivities
The fitness sensitivities of infant early survivorship are always the highest for the age-structured human life cycle. There is nonetheless variation in the value of these early fitness sensitivities across different demographic schedules. To better understand this variation, I simulated a wide range of life histories using model schedules of age-specific mortality and fertility, calculated sensitivities, and evaluated the contribution of differences in indices of survival and fertility on the value of s21, the sensitivity of survival from age 0–5. I used the four regional families of Coale-Demeney model life tables (Coale et al., 1983) combined with a wide range of Coale-Trussell model fertility schedules (Coale and Trussell, 1974, 1978) to generate simulated life histories. Coale-Demeney regional model life tables come in 25 levels of overall mortality, indexed by life expectancy at age 10, in four distinct patterns – or shapes – of age-specific mortality. The Coale-Trussell model fertility schedules allow both the level and shape of age-specific fertility to be varied systematically. I simulated a total of 25,000 life histories and discarded those that yielded an annual rate of increase less than zero and greater than 5%, yielding a total of 12,198 simulated life histories.
I regressed the value of s21 on the logarithm of TFR and e0 (and their interaction). I log-transformed both TFR and e0 because of their skewed distributions. Table 2 summarizes the model. While s21 always has the greatest fitness sensitivity in the life cycle, its value varied from 0.173 to 0.363. Both TFR and e0 have modest but highly significant effects on the value of s21, with TFR increasing and e0 decreasing the value of s21. In addition, there was a strong interaction between e0 and TFR. This interaction can be seen in a plot of the s21 against both e0 and TFR (figure 5). Particular combinations of life expectancy and total fertility rate have very similar sensitivity values. Note that in these simulations, e0 varied in 2.5 year increments (Coale et al., 1983), while TFR effectively varied continuously. This is why the scatter plots exhibit the banding particularly visible in the s21/e0 subplots.
Table 2.
Summary of the regression model of S21 against the logarithms of life expectancy and total fertility rates, and their interaction
Estimate | Std. Error | t value | Pr(>|t|) | |
---|---|---|---|---|
(Intercept) | 0.2216 | 0.0056 | 39.56 | < 0.0001 |
log(tfr) | 0.0518 | 0.0035 | 14.70 | < 0.0001 |
log(e0) | −0.0094 | 0.0014 | −6.65 | < 0.0001 |
log(tfr):log(e0) | 0.0033 | 0.0009 | 3.56 | 0.0004 |
Figure 5.
(5) Scatterplot matrix showing the correlations between s21 TFR, and e0.
4 Discussion
Human populations are characterized by a tremendous degree of economic, social, and demographic diversity. Nonetheless, the results I have presented here indicate that the force of selection on the human life cycle is robust and remarkably consistent across the possible range of demographic variation. These observations make it clear that (1) the observed demographic diversity in humans is not itself likely to result from natural selection, and (2) that the force of selection points in largely the same direction on the adaptive landscape for all human populations.
In his classic paper, Hamilton (1966) first performed a perturbation analysis of the characteristic equation (equation 1), showing that the force of selection on age-specific survival declines monotonically with age. While his analysis was very similar to mine, there are two ways in which the present analysis extends Hamilton’s work. First, Hamilton (1966) used a single population to illustrate his calculations: Taiwan during the Japanese colonial period, a population characterized by both quite high fertility and mortality. I have expanded his analysis to consider a much broader range of the human demographic space (figure 2). Second, while Hamilton’s survival perturbation was essentially an elasticity, his fertility perturbation was ∂r/∂Fi, where r = log(λ). This is neither a sensitivity nor an elasticity according to the definitions I use, which follow Caswell (2001). Furthermore, it means that the fitness sensitivities with respect to survival and fertility have subtly different interpretations (Baudisch, 2005). Subsequent work in demography and life history theory uses either sensitivities or elasticities sensu Caswell (e.g., Lande, 1982; Tuljapurkar, 1990; Benton and Grant, 1996). I employ sensitivity and elasticity measures that are consistent with the demographic developments subsequent to Hamilton’s work, making them more comparable with common usage of perturbation analysis in evolutionary biology.
In this analysis, the preponderance of selection, as measured by fitness sensitivities and elasticities, falls upon the transitions leading to recruitment. A structural feature of elasticities is instructive in this respect. The summed elasticities of incoming and outgoing transitions in a life-cycle stage must be equal (van Groenendael et al., 1994). In an age-structured population, the more iteroparous the life cycle is, the more transitions will lead to the first life-cycle stage. The implication of this is that the force of selection will increase on survival from this stage. Humans are highly iteroparous and, consequently, a large fraction of the total fitness elasticity is accounted for by survival out of the first age class. It is interesting to note that as fertility becomes more concentrated with the aid of modern contraception, the relative elasticity of early survival is reduced. This can be seen in the differences between elasticities of the !Kung and Ache on the one hand and the USA on the other.
While the sensitivity of λ to first period survival (i.e., s21) is always the greatest in the age-structured human life cycle, its value varies considerably for different combinations of age-specific schedules of survivorship and fertility. I found that the value of s21 increases as TFR increases and declines as e0 increases (figure 5). Somewhat paradoxically, having more babies places a premium on their survival. The intuition behind this is that in high-fertility populations, the age-structure is more heavily weighted toward the youngest age classes. Since fitness sensitivities are the product of the receiving stage’s reproductive value and the sending stage’s stable age contribution, populations with higher fractions of 0–4 year-olds will have greater values of s21, certaris paribus. Understanding the dynamic interplay between the force of selection on early childhood survival, which increases with TFR, and fertility, which presumably trades-off against childhood survival, remains a major challenge in the formulation of an adequate theory of human life history evolution.
At the most general level, life history theory has as its constituent elements the traits that define the life-cycle (e.g., age-specific schedules of reproductive investments) and the trade-offs that bind them together (e.g., reproductive effort vs. future or current survival, number vs. quality of offspring). These trade-offs are driven by both the quantitative genetics underlying the traits, and the epigenetic processes which give rise to them. In this analysis, I have only analyzed the force of selection on demographic schedules and have not examined trade-offs explicitly. The results of this analysis are nonetheless informative regarding these trade-offs. In particular, we should expect any trait that is negatively correlated with juvenile recruitment to be opposed by selection.
The logic of this statement is made particularly lucid by considering Lande’s equation for the evolution of a quantitative multivariate trait z (Lande, 1982):
(6) |
where Δz̄ is a vector describing the change in the mean of the multivariate trait z – here taken to be the collection of life-cycle transitions, G is the additive genetic covariance matrix, and ∇λ is the fitness gradient – a column vector of all the projection matrix sensitivities.
For concreteness sake, consider a hypothetical trade-off between some adult fertility rate and infant survival. A negative covariance between these traits (i.e., a trade-off) will be multiplied by the largest sensitivity in the life cycle. Given the magnitude of the differences in sensitivities of early survival to the sensitivities of all the fertility rates, the absolute value of the sum of these scaled covariances is likely to be greater than the scaled additive genetic variance in fertility. Thus, even if selection favored increased fertility in the absence of trade-offs (as, of course, it does), fertility is expected to decrease. This whole discussion is predicated on the existence of additive genetic variation driving change in the trait, but illustrates the fundamental importance of such high fitness sensitivities for juvenile recruitment.
Elasticities are proportional sensitivities: For a per cent change in a vital rate, by what percentage will fitness change? Depending on the values of the vital rates, a per cent change may be easier for some transitions than for others. For example, survival is a probability. An increase of one per cent in the 0→5 survival for the USA in 2002 would be impossible since it would mean that more individuals would enter the five year-old age class than left the zero year-old one! In contrast, among the Ache the same proportional increase to the same transition probability would make infant survival go from 0.751 to 0.759 – not an unimaginable increase. Similarly, increasing contemporary American fertility by one per cent certainly seems within the realm of biological possibility while increasing the fertility of 35 year-old Ache women (with their TFRs of 8) seems less biologically plausible.
I have not dealt explicitly with the problem of post-reproductive survival. However, the analysis is nonetheless potentially instructive about its evolution. It is not difficult to imagine that post-reproductive survival could be favored if it increased the survivorship of juveniles. Given the high fitness elasticities of juvenile survivorship (together with the seeming feasibility of making improvements under hunter-gatherer demographic schedules) and the relatively low elasticities of fertility – even at the peak of a woman’s reproductive career – it seems more plausible that investments in post-reproductive lifespan would have been favored more for its value in increasing grandchildren’s survival rather than daughters’ fertility, a point supported empirically by Sear and Mace (2008).
The model for the evolution of human life histories that has probably received the most attention of late is due to Charnov (1991). The fact that the fitness elasticities for pre-reproductive survival are the highest in the human life cycle – and are likely to be the highest among any iteroparous age-structured life cycle – calls into question the one fundamental assumption of Charnov’s life history model. Charnov (1991) presented a model for mammalian life history evolution in which the causal pathway flows from adult mortality rates to age at first reproduction, by way of a growth law. Size at maturity determines adult fertility. Perfect population stationarity is assumed and the mechanism by which such homeostasis is achieved is through juvenile mortality. Under this formulation, juvenile mortality is not free to vary independently (in con trast to Charnov’s earlier work: (Charnov and Schaffer, 1973)), but instead is adjusted to insure population stationarity. In other words, juvenile mortality takes on the role of book-keeping in this influential model, which has been used extensively in evolutionary anthropology in recent years (Hill, 1993; Hawkes et al., 1998; Kaplan et al., 2000). The results presented here suggest that juvenile mortality should be expected to exert a strong selective force in itself. It remains an open research question whether a model that can account for the joint effects of juvenile and adult mortality while retaining the appealing reproductive power allometry of Charnov’s model can be formulated.
In this paper, I have shown that there is a universal pattern to the way selection acts on the age-specific patterns of survival and fertility in the human life cycle. Such universality suggests we should look for specific species-typical adaptations to parenting and the promotion of child survival. The existence of extensive intergenerational transfers with net downward flow (e.g., Lee, 2003) is clearly one avenue for the promotion of child survival and recruitment. The results that I have presented in this paper also suggest that behavioral plasticity allowing parents to capitalize on favorable environmental circumstances for the promotion of child survival on the one hand and to buffer child survival against deleterious environmental circumstances on the other, should be a hallmark of human parental care behavior. A recent empirical example of this type of phenomenon comes from Marlowe’s study of male parental investment among the Hadza of Tanzania. Marlowe (2003) shows that while women typically subsidize men’s hunting through their more reliable foraging among the Hadza (Hawkes et al., 2001), men increase their provisioning when their wives are energetically stressed due to the presence of young nurslings. Note that while the population models I have analyzed are one-sex, the same logic applies to two-sex models, a topic I take up in a related paper. The survival of men’s offspring will have the highest impact on their fitness, with the provision that men’s paternal uncertainty will discount this benefit somewhat.
Footnotes
I have written the Euler-Lotka equation in a manner consistent with the matrix model I use in subsequent sections. The form typically seen in textbooks is written in continuous time as , where α is age at first reproduction, β is age at last reproduction, r is the rate of increase, x is age, l(x) is the probability of surviving to exact age x and m(x) is the fertility rate (in daughters) of women age x. Note that . That is the cumulative probability of survival is the product of all previous interval probabilities.
Note that the growth rates calculated in figure 2 differ slightly from both the observed growth rates and those calculated later in the paper. This difference arises because of the simplifying assumptions of equation 2, where we use the approximation R0 ≈ S(α)· TFR.
Publisher's Disclaimer: This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final citable form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
References
- Baudisch A. Hamilton’s indicators of the force of selection. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA. 2005;102(23):8263–8268. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0502155102. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Benton TG, Grant A. How to keep fit in the real world: Elasticity analyses and selection pressures on life histories in a variable environment. American Naturalist. 1996;147(1):115–139. [Google Scholar]
- Caldwell J. Theory of fertility decline. New York: Academic Press; 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Cant MA, Johnstone RA. Reproductive conflict and the separation of reproductive generations in humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2008;105(14):5332–5336. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0711911105. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Caswell H. A general formula for the sensitivity of population growth rate to changes in life history parameters. Theoretical Population Biology. 1978;14:215–230. doi: 10.1016/0040-5809(78)90025-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Caswell H. Matrix Population Models: Construction, Analysis and Interpretation. 2. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer; 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Chagnon N. Life histories, blood revenge, and warfare in a tribal population. Science. 1988;239:985–992. doi: 10.1126/science.239.4843.985. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Charlesworth B. Evolution in age-structured populations. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1994. [Google Scholar]
- Charnov EL. Evolution of life history variation among female mammals. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA. 1991;88:1134–1137. doi: 10.1073/pnas.88.4.1134. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Charnov EL. Trade-off invariant rules for evolutionary stable life histories. Nature. 1997;387:393–394. doi: 10.1038/387393a0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Charnov EL, Schaffer WM. Life history consequences of natural selection: Cole’s result revisited. American Naturalist. 1973;107:791–793. [Google Scholar]
- Coale A, Demeny P, Vaughn B. Regional model life tables and stable populations. 2. New York: Academic Press; 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Coale A, Trussell J. Model fertility schedules: Variations in the age-structure of childbrearing. Population Index. 1974;40(2):185–258. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Coale A, Trussell J. Technical note: Finding two parameters that specify a model schedule of marital fertility. Population Index. 1978;44(2):202–213. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Coale AJ, Watkins SC, editors. The decline of fertility in Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Cole LC. The population consequences of life history phenomena. Quarterly Review of Biology. 1954;29(2):103–137. doi: 10.1086/400074. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Early JD, Peters JF. The population dynamics of the Mucajai Yanomama. San Diego: Academic Press; 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Gadgil M, Bossert WH. Life historical consequences of natural selection. American Naturalist. 1970;104:1–24. [Google Scholar]
- Goodall J. The chimpanzees of Gombe: Patterns of behavior. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Gurven M, Kaplan H. Longevity among hunter-gatherer: A cross-cultural examination. Population and Development Review. 2007;33(2):321–365. [Google Scholar]
- Hamilton WD. The moulding of senescence by natural selection. Journal of Theoretical Biology. 1966;12:12–45. doi: 10.1016/0022-5193(66)90184-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hawkes K, O’Connell JF, Jones NGB, Alvarez H, Charnov EL. Grandmothering, menopause, and the evolution of human life histories. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA. 1998;95(3):1336. doi: 10.1073/pnas.95.3.1336. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hawkes K, O’Connell JF, Jones NGB. Hunting and nuclear families: Some lessons from the Hadza about men’s work. Current Anthropology. 2001;42(5):681–709. [Google Scholar]
- Hill K. Life history theory and evolutionary anthropology. Evolutionary Anthropology. 1993;2(3):78–88. [Google Scholar]
- Hill K, Hurtado AM. Ache life history. New York: Aldine de Gruyter; 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Hill K, Kaplan H, Lancaster J, Hurtado AM. A theory of human life history evolution: Diet, intelligence, and longevity. Evolutionary Anthropology. 2000;9(4):156–185. [Google Scholar]
- Howell N. The demography of the Dobe !Kung. New York: Academic Press; 1979. [Google Scholar]
- Jones JH. Fetal programming: Adaptive life-history tactic or making the best of a bad start? American Journal of Human Biology. 2005;17:22–33. doi: 10.1002/ajhb.20099. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jones JH. demogR: A package for evolutionary demographic analysis in R. Journal of Statistical Software. 2007;22(10):1–28. [Google Scholar]
- Kaplan H, Hill K, Lancaster J, Hurtado AM. A theory of human life history evolution: Diet, intelligence, and longevity. Evolutionary Anthropology. 2000;9(4):156–185. [Google Scholar]
- Kaplan HS, Robson AJ. The emergence of humans: The coevolution of intelligence and longevity with intergenerational transfers. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 2002;99(15):10221–10226. doi: 10.1073/pnas.152502899. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Keyfitz N. Introduction to the mathematics of populations. Menlo Park: Addison-Wesley; 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Keyfitz N, Flieger W. World population growth and aging: Demographic trends in the late twentieth century. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Kohler HP, Billari FC, Ortega J. Low fertility in Europe: Causes, implications and policy options. In: Harris F, editor. The Baby Bust: Who will do the Work? Who Will Pay the Taxes? Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlield; 2006. pp. 48–109. [Google Scholar]
- Lande RA. A quantitative genetic theory of life history evolution. Ecology. 1982;63:607–615. [Google Scholar]
- Lee RD. Rethinking the evolutionary theory of aging: Transfers, not births, shape social species. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 2003;100(16):9637–9642. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1530303100. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lee RD, Kramer KL. Children’s economic roles in the Maya family life cycle: Cain, Caldwell, and Chayanov revisited. Population and Development Review. 2002;28(3):475–499. [Google Scholar]
- Livi-Bacci M. A concise history of world population. 2. Blackwell; 1997. [Google Scholar]
- MacArthur RH, Wilson EO. The theory of island biogeography. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 1967. [Google Scholar]
- Marlowe F. A critical period for provisioning by Hadza men: Implications for pair bonding. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2003;24:217–229. [Google Scholar]
- Martin JA, Hamilton BE, Sutton PD, Ventura SJ, Menacker F, Munson ML. Technical Report. 2. Vol. 54. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention; 2005. Births: Final data for 2003. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Murphy GI. Pattern of life history and the environment. American Naturalist. 1968;102:390–404. [Google Scholar]
- Nee S, Holmes EC, Rambaut A, Harvey PH. Inferring population history from molecular phylogenies. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, B Biological Sciences. 1995;349(1327):25–31. doi: 10.1098/rstb.1995.0087. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nee S, Holmes EC, Rambaut A, Harvey PH. Inferring population history from molecular phylogenies. In: Harvey PH, Leigh Brown A, Maynard Smith J, Nee S, editors. New Uses for New Phylogenies. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1996. pp. 66–80. [Google Scholar]
- Notestein F. Economic problems of population change. Proceedings of the Eighth International Conference of Agricultural Economists; London: Oxford University Press; 1953. pp. 13–31. [Google Scholar]
- Perusse D. Cultural and reproductive success in industrial societies: Testing relationship at the proximate and ultimate levels. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1993;16:267–322. [Google Scholar]
- Pianka ER. On r and K selection. American Naturalist. 1970;104:592–597. [Google Scholar]
- R Development Core Team. R: A language and environment for statistical computing. Vienna, Austria: R Foundation for Statistical Computing; 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Robinson RS, Lee RD, Kramer KL. Counting women’s labour: A reanalysis of children’s net production using Cain’s data from a Bangladeshi village. Population Studies. 2008;62(1):25–38. doi: 10.1080/00324720701788590. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Schaffer W. Optimal reproductive effort in fluctuating environments. American Naturalist. 1974;108:783–790. [Google Scholar]
- Sear R, Mace R. Who keeps children alive? a review of the effects of kin on child survival. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2008;29(1):1–18. [Google Scholar]
- Seger J, Brockerman HJ. What is bet-hedging? In: Harvey P, Partridge L, editors. Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology. Vol. 4. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1987. pp. 182–211. [Google Scholar]
- Thompson W. On the reproduction of organisms with overlapping generations. Bulletin of Entomological Research. 1931:22. [Google Scholar]
- Tooby J, Cosmides L. The past explains the present - emotional adaptations and the structure of ancestral environments. Ethology and Sociobiology. 1990;11(4–5):375–424. [Google Scholar]
- Tuljapurkar S. Lecture notes in biomathematics. Vol. 85. Berlin: Springer-Veralg; 1990. Population dynamics in variable environments. [Google Scholar]
- Turke P, Betzig LL. Those who can do: Wealth, status, and reproductive success on Ifaluk. Etholology & Sociobiology. 1985;6:79–87. [Google Scholar]
- van Groenendael J, De Kroon H, Kalisz S, Tuljapurkar S. Loop analysis: Evaluating life history pathways in population projection matrices. Ecology. 1994;75:2410–2415. [Google Scholar]
- Vining D. Social versus reproductive success: The central theoretical problem of human sociobiology. Behavior and Brain Sciences. 1986;9:167–260. [Google Scholar]
- Voland E. Differential reproductive success within the Krummhorn population (Germany, 18th & 19th centuries) Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology. 1990;26:65–72. [Google Scholar]
- Wilmoth J. Human mortality database. 2007 ( http://www.mortality.org)
- Wood JW. Dynamics of human reproduction: Biology, biometry, demography. New York: Aldine de Gruyter; 1994. [Google Scholar]