Skip to main content
Frontiers in Psychology logoLink to Frontiers in Psychology
. 2013 May 8;4:255. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00255

The Scope of Usage-Based Theory

Paul Ibbotson 1,*
PMCID: PMC3647106  PMID: 23658552

Abstract

Usage-based approaches typically draw on a relatively small set of cognitive processes, such as categorization, analogy, and chunking to explain language structure and function. The goal of this paper is to first review the extent to which the “cognitive commitment” of usage-based theory has had success in explaining empirical findings across domains, including language acquisition, processing, and typology. We then look at the overall strengths and weaknesses of usage-based theory and highlight where there are significant debates. Finally, we draw special attention to a set of culturally generated structural patterns that seem to lie beyond the explanation of core usage-based cognitive processes. In this context we draw a distinction between cognition permitting language structure vs. cognition entailing language structure. As well as addressing the need for greater clarity on the mechanisms of generalizations and the fundamental units of grammar, we suggest that integrating culturally generated structures within existing cognitive models of use will generate tighter predictions about how language works.

Keywords: usage-based, language processing, language-acquisition, typology, cultural learning


“Don’t ask for the meaning; ask for the use” – Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations

Linguistic theory has a lot to explain. First, the structure of language emerges over vastly different time scales: the split-second processes of producing and comprehending speech; the years an individual takes to construct their language; the centuries over which languages evolve. Second, there is the sheer diversity of forms languages take. Despite the rate at which languages are disappearing, a person would have to walk less than 50 miles on average to meet a new language if all they were equally distributed over the inhabitable world. Compare this with our closest living evolutionary cousins. The odd cultural variation in handshake in Chimpanzees is impressive but it does not really compete with over 6000 ways of saying “hello” (Foley and Lahr, 2011). Third, language is a complex adaptive system (Bybee, 2010). This means the language people know changes and reorganizes itself in response to multiple competing factors. The nested feedback loops this sets up defy any simple input-output analysis, ratcheting up the complexity further.

The structure of this paper is as follows. First, we give a brief outline of the core cognitive processes that underpin the usage-based approach. Second, we examine the extent to a usage-based cognitive framework predicts empirical findings in language acquisition, processing, and typology – domains that are not usually not brought together in this way. One criterion to judge the strength of usage-based theory is to examine whether it has made subtle predictions across a range of domains. Converging evidence from separate domains that employ a vast range of methodologies and occupy a wide range of positions on the theoretical spectrum would provide particularly strong support. Third, we briefly discuss the philosophical implications of adopting a usage-based approach before reflecting on what usage-based theory does well, what it does less well, and where there are significant points of disagreement pointing to new lines of research. Finally, we present findings from the linguistic anthropological literature, looking at ways in which culture may constrain linguistic structure. We suggest a challenging new line of research will be to ground culturally dependent structures within existing cognitive models of use.

The Usage-Based Approach

Despite the daunting scope of linguistic phenomena begging an explanation, usage-based theories of language representation have a simple overarching approach. Whether the focus is on language processing, acquisition, or change, knowledge of a language is based in knowledge of actual usage and generalizations made over usage events (Langacker, 1987, 1991; Croft, 1991; Givón, 1995; Tomasello, 2003; Goldberg, 2006; Bybee, 2010). For usage-based theories the complexity of language emerges not as a result of a language-specific instinct but through the interaction of cognition and use.

These broad assumptions are in contrast with those of the generativist and structural traditions who analyze language as a static or synchronic system, self-contained, and autonomous from the cognitive and social matrix of language use. The aim here is not to detail the case against generativist universal grammar (plenty of that criticism exists elsewhere, e.g., Tomasello, 2004; Christiansen and Chater, 2008; Evans and Levinson, 2009; see Ambridge and Lieven, 2011 for contrasting theoretical approaches to language acquisition). Here we devote more space to the strengths and weaknesses of usage-based theory and point to where there might be new theoretical ground to break. One thing is worth briefly stating here though. Much theoretical work in generativist linguistics followed from the assumption that it was impossible for a child to acquire the rules of their grammar with the tools of Behaviorism. Few developmental psychologists would disagree with this but equally, after 50 years of research into the social-cognitive abilities of children, few developmental psychologists would define the resources available to the child in merely Behaviorist terms. The section on language acquisition and cultural use outlines the nature of what some of these resources are – although it is a point of debate whether one is convinced that these resources provide a complete account of language acquisition.

The usage-based position is closely allied with that of Cognitive Linguistics and Construction Grammar where the fundamental linguistic unit is the construction: a meaningful symbolic assembly used for the purpose of signally relevant communicative intentions. Syntactic schemas, idioms, morphology, word classes, and lexical items are all treated as constructions that vary along a continuum of specificity (Langacker, 1987; Fillmore et al., 1988). If one accepts the premise that language is like this, the developmental implications are quite profound: if children can learn idiosyncratic yet productive constructions (e.g., Her go to the ballet! My mother-in-law ride a bike!), then why can they not learn the more canonical ones in the same way? In the cognitive linguistic/construction grammar approach, a grammar is more than a list of constructions however. The organization and productivity of language is understood as the result of analogies between the form and/or meaning in a structured inventory of constructions. For example, the phrases the taller they come the harder they fall, the more the merrier, the older they get the cuter they ain’t are all variations on an underlying theme or productive schema; the X-er the Y-er. Moreover, there are no core/periphery, competence/performance distinctions of generativist theory – it is constructions and use all the way down (and up). This very brief characterization of usage-based approaches gives a flavor of what usage-based theorists think language is. We now turn to the cognitive processes that are thought to generate linguistic structure.

Usage-Based Processes

Bybee (2010), a key architect of usage-based theory, identifies several cognitive processes that influence the use and development of linguistic structure (i) categorization; identifying tokens as an instances of a particular type (ii) chunking; the formation of sequential units through repetition or practice (iii) rich memory; the storage of detailed information from experience (iv) analogy; mapping of an existing structural pattern onto a novel instance, and (v) cross-modal association; the cognitive capacity to link form and meaning. Thus there is a strong “cognitive commitment” to explaining linguistic structure. As Taylor puts it, “the general thrust of the cognitive linguistics enterprise is to render accounts of syntax, morphology, phonology, and word meaning consonant with aspects of cognition which are well documented, or at least highly plausible, and which may manifest in non-linguistic (Taylor, 2002, p. 9).

As an example of this commitment, Ibbotson et al. (2012) looked at whether we can “import” what we know about categorization of non-linguistic stimuli to explain language use. In a classic study by Franks and Bransford (1971) they argued that a prototype comprises of a maximal number of features common to the category, often “averaged” across exemplars. They constructed stimuli by combining geometric forms such as circles, stars, and triangles into structured groups of various kinds. Some of these were then shown to participants who were then later asked whether they recognized these and other shapes they had not seen previously. Importantly, one of the exemplars shown at test contained all of the geometric forms together, an exemplar that had actually never been shown previously (but could be considered the prototype if all of the experienced exemplars were averaged). The participants not only thought that they had seen this prototype, but they were actually more confident that they had seen it than the other previously seen exemplars (or distracter items which they had not seen). Note that these effects were established for an ad hoc non-linguistic category. Ibbotson et al. found the same pattern of findings – misrecognition of prototypes – extends to the transitive argument-structure construction, a fundamental building block present in one form or another in all of the world’s languages (Hopper and Thompson, 1980; Næss, 2007). They argued that this shows abstract linguistic categories behave in similar ways to non-linguistic categories, for example, by showing graded membership of a category (see also Ibbotson and Tomasello, 2009 for a cross-linguistic, developmental perspective).

Focusing on analogy for the moment, in usage-based theory, constructions can be analogous in form and/or meaning (Figure 1), and there is good evidence that the alignment of relational structure and mapping between representations is a fundamental psychological process that underpins forming these abstract connections (Goldstone et al., 1991; Goldstone, 1994; Goldstone and Medin, 1994; Gentner and Markman, 1995).

Figure 1.

Figure 1

Constructions grouped together on the basis of similarity of form and/or function (adapted from Croft and Cruse, 2004).

There is quite a lot of evidence that people, including young children, focus on these kinds of relations in making analogies across linguistic constructions, with some of the most important being the meaning of the words involved, especially the verbs, and the spatial, temporal, and causal relations they encode (e.g., Gentner and Markman, 1997; Gentner and Medina, 1998; Tomasello, 2003). Bod (2009) showed how a computational learning algorithm was able use structural analogy, probabilistically, to mimic children’s language development from item-based constructions to abstract constructions, including simulation of some of the errors made by children in producing complex questions. In usage-based theory, analogy also operates in a more abstract sense, by extending the prototypical meaning of constructions. For example, the meaning of the ditransitive construction is closely associated with “transfer of possession” as in “John gave Mary a goat.” Metaphorical extensions of this pattern, such as “John gave the goat a kiss” or even “Cry me a river” are understood by analogy to the core meaning of the construction from which they were extended, which in the case of the ditransitive is something like “X causes Y to receive Z” (Goldberg, 2006).

The relative frequency of items in a corpus obviously plays a key role in many usage-based processes. Items that consistently co-occur together in the speech stream and are consistently used for the same function face a pressure to become automatized, in a manner that is similar to those which occur in a variety of non-linguistic sensory-motor skills. Thus, going to faces pressure to be compressed or chunked to gonna. The ultimate message compression strategy would be to say nothing at all, thus, at many different levels – grammatical, lexical, phonological – the linguistic system is trying to balance the trade-off between the amount of linguistic signal provided for a given message and the expectedness of that message (Jaeger and Tily, 2011). Irregular patterns can survive in the language because they are frequent enough to be learned and used on their own, whereas items and constructions that are less frequent tend to get regularized by pattern-seeking children or, in the extreme case, they drop out of use as children do not get enough exposure to them. The more a linguistic unit is established as a cognitive routine or “rehearsed” in the mind of the speaker, the more it is said to be entrenched (Langacker, 1987). Entrenchment is a matter of degree and essentially amounts to strengthening whatever response the system makes to the inputs that it receives (Hebb, 1949; Allport, 1985). The converse of this is that extended periods of disuse will weaken representations. For example, young infants are able to discriminate a wider range of sounds that are present in their native language (Aslin et al., 1981). Once this entrenchment is established as a routine it can be difficult to reverse. For example, Japanese speakers find it difficult to discriminate between /r/ and /l/ because it activates a single representation, whereas for English speakers the two representations remain separately entrenched (Munakata and McClelland, 2003).

We will now look at the extent to which core usage-based cognitive processes – like categorization, analogy, and chunking – can explain the empirical findings in language acquisition, processing, and change. Obviously these are all huge areas of research in their own right and there is no way to test usage-based theory against every finding. In the space we have, we try to focus on studies that make key points and are indicative of the wider literature.

Language Acquisition and Use

The good news for children is that they usually do not have to invent ways of communicating de novo. The language they are born into is very likely to be the result of a long history of cumulative cultural evolution and so provides them with off-the-peg solutions to communicative problems. The bad news is that they have to learn what these are.

Usage patterns

For a five-word string (e.g., I like your green cheese), with 20 words that can fill each slot, there are 3,200,000 possible five-word sentences (205). An important point for both processing and acquisition is that, in natural language the probability of encountering any given word or any combination of these words is not equal. Specifically, there are a few forms that are encountered relatively frequently whereas most are encountered rarely (Zipf, 1935/1965). As Shannon pointed out, this kind of redundancy allows recovery of meaning xvxn whxn thx sxgnxl xs nxxsy (Shannon, 1951). Interestingly, this is true not only for letter sequences and words (1 GRAM) but for sequences of words too (GRAM > 1), Figure 2.

Figure 2.

Figure 2

From Bannard and Lieven (2009). The figure plots the natural logarithm of the frequency of each string of words encountered against the natural logarithm of the position of each string in a ranked list of these substrings. Words are taken from the 89 million word written component of the British National Corpus (Burnard, 2000).

This formulaticity in language has consequences for learning. Item-based or exemplar-based approaches to learning recognize that a large part of a person’s language knowledge is constructed from rather specific pieces of language, grounded in the expressions people actually use during their everyday interactions. These items or exemplars are stored in a way that is not far removed (in terms of schematicity) from the way in which people encounter them in natural discourse. Focusing on Child Directed Speech, Cameron-Faulkner et al. (2003) found that a small number of semi-formulaic frames account for a large amount of the data. Frames like Where’s the X? I wanna X, More X, It’s a X, I’m X-ing it, Put X here, Mommy’s X-ing it, Let’s X it, Throw X, X gone, I X-ed it, Sit on the X, Open X, X here, There’s a X, X broken. Decades of research support the general idea that children used these islands of reliability when they are schematizing patterns in their language (e.g., Tomasello, 2003; Ambridge and Lieven, 2011).

Pronouns are a particularly important source of reliability in the input as children hear lots of these examples. Ibbotson et al. (2011) systematically varied constructional cues (NP is verbing NP vs. NP is getting verbed by NP) and case-marking cues on English pronouns (he/she vs. her/him vs. it). These can be configured as different “pronoun-frames,” for example (NPnominative – Verb – NPaccusative) vs. (NPneuter – Verb – NPaccusative). In a pointing comprehension test, both 2- and 3-year-olds used the case-marking on the pronoun frames to help them comprehend the sentences; this despite the fact that English has a relatively restricted case system compared to other languages like Finnish and Turkish. It shows even very young English children are sensitive to complex patterns of use – in this case comprehending the “value added” by case in marking the semantic roles of transitives over and above that of word order and other constructional cues. As Goldin-Meadow (2007) has pointed out pronoun frames may also have special status as they essentially act as deictic/pointing expressions. A child can than map the gestural productivity of a point – which can refer to anything in the world – onto the referential flexibility of lexical pronouns.

This item-based view does not necessarily entail that children do not, at some point, understand phrases like Susan tickles Mary or words like hands as exemplars of a more general pattern or schema, say X verbs Y or plural = noun + s. It is a claim about how children might get to this point of development and how information is stored in the mind of the speaker. Exemplar-based approaches are therefore as much about how language is represented as about the process of learning itself. In the usage-based view of language acquisition, children first acquire a number of lexical schemas or semi-formalic frames, e.g., X hits Y, X kisses Y, X pushes Y, X pulls Y, then by forming analogies between the roles that participants are playing in these events, these constructions eventually coalesce into a general abstract construction, e.g., X Verbtransitive Y (Tomasello, 2003; Bannard et al., 2009; Ibbotson, 2011).

Several researchers have attempted to simulate the process of moving from items to schemas in more mechanistic terms with computational models. For example, Bannard et al. (2009) built a model of acquisition that begins with children learning concrete words (exemplars) and phrases, with no categories or grammatical abstractions of any kind. That model was then compared to a model using grammatical categories and they found that the category-less model provided the best account of 2-year-old children’s early language. When categorical knowledge, comprising nouns and verbs, was entered into this item-based model, performance actually got worse. Importantly and in contrast, at 3 years of age adding grammatical categories such as nouns and verbs helped the performance, suggesting that these categories emerged around the third year of life. Another important finding was that at 2 years of age children’s item-based grammars were very different from one another, whereas by 3 years of age children’s more category-based grammars were more similar to one another, as the children all began converging on, in this case, English grammar (see also Bod, 2009 for a structural analogy model). Mechanisms of analogy and generalizations are a key area of research in usage-based theory and are discussed later in the sections on strengths, weaknesses, and challenges.

Having introduced moving from items to schemas, usage-based theory needs some proposal of how to constrain generalizations so that children arrive at the same conventions as adult do. The three main suggestions that would help children rule out some overgeneralizations are, in one way or another, all based on patterns of use (see Ambridge et al., 2013 for more detailed supporting evidence for each).

  1. Entrenchment (Braine and Brooks, 1995): the more often a child hears a verb in a particular syntactic context (e.g., I suggested the idea to him) the less likely they are to use it in a new context they haven’t heard it in (e.g., *I suggested him the idea; Ambridge et al., 2012a; see also Perfors et al., 2010 who use hierarchical Bayesian framework to model this kind of generalization).

  2. Pre-emption (Goldberg, 2006): if a child repeatedly hears a verb in a construction (e.g., I filled the cup with water) that serves the same communicative function as a possible unattested generalization (e.g., *I filled water into the cup), then the child infers that the generalization is not available (Ambridge et al., 2012b).

  3. Construction semantics (Pinker, 1989): constructions are associated with particular meanings (e.g., the transitive causative with direct external causation). As children refine this knowledge, they will cease to insert verbs that do not bear these meaning elements into the construction (e.g., *The joke giggled him; Ambridge et al., 2011).

What words refer to and usage patterns

Interestingly the issue of determining a word’s referent has often been presented as one shot learning problem (following Quine, 1960) – evidently not the same problem children actually face. By using invariant properties in the word-to-world mapping across multiple situations, it has been shown children reduce the degrees of freedom as to what nouns and verbs might mean, Figure 3 (Siskind, 1996; Smith and Yu, 2008; Scott and Fisher, 2012).

Figure 3.

Figure 3

An adult chooses a linguistic expression w1 associated with concept r1 that they want to communicate. At t1 the child doesn’t know whether the novel word w1 refers to r1 or r2 and for now the best she can do is remember the associations between the scene and the words. At t2 she hears w1 with one object r1 familiar from t1 and one new object r3. Cross-situational learning works by repeatedly recording the associations between language and the context in which it is used. Over time, the signal (an intentional word-referent pair) is more strongly represented than the noise (an unintentional word-referent pair). Items that appear in the hashed box are the raw data on which the child makes the cross-situational associations.

However powerful cross-situational learning is, it undoubtedly operates in combination with other cues to meaning. Yu and Ballard (2007) found that a computational model of word-learning performed better when it used social information (joint attention and prosody) in combination with statistical cues (cross-situational learning) than when it relied on purely statistical information alone (see also Frank et al., 2009 for the integration of pragmatic and statistical cues). Once the child has a foothold in the language, the context of the novel word gives a clue as to what kind of word it might be (Gleitman, 1990; Pinker, 1994). For example, the usage patterns in English hint at the following possibilities for pum (MacWhinney, 2005):

  • (1)

    Here is a pum (count noun).

  • (2)

    Here is Pum (proper noun).

  • (3)

    I am pumming (intransitive verb).

  • (4)

    I pummed the duck [transitive (causative) verb].

  • (5)

    I need some pum (mass noun).

  • (6)

    This is the pum one (adjective).

Eight-month-old infants are sensitive to the statistical tendency that transitional probabilities are generally higher within words than across words, helping them to find “words in a sea of sounds” (Saffran et al., 1996; Saffran, 2001). Children are also able to discover syntactic regularities between categories of words as well as the statistical regularities in sound patterns (Marcus et al., 1999). By 12 months, infants can use their newly discovered word boundaries to discover regularities in the syntactic distributions of a novel word-string grammar (Saffran and Wilson, 2003). And by 15 months old, infants are able to combine multiple cues in order to learn morphophonological paradigmatic constraints (Gerken et al., 2005). Note the domain-generality of this statistical learning ability. 2-month-olds infants are sensitive to transitional probabilities between visual shape sequences (Kirkham et al., 2002) thus infants have already build up considerable expertize in statistical learning by the time these linguistic effects appear.

Adult’s use and children’s use

As usage-based theories would predict, errors in child speech, the age at which structures are acquired, and the sequence that language emerges can all be predicted on the basis of usage patterns in the input. For example,

  • The acquisition order of wh-questions (What, Where, When, Why, How) is predicted from the frequency with which particular wh-words and verbs occur in children’s input (Rowland and Pine, 2000; Rowland et al., 2003).

  • Children’s proportional use of me-for-I errors (e.g., when the child says “me do it”) correlates with their caregivers’ proportional use of me in certain contexts (e.g., “let me do it” (Kirjavainen et al., 2009).

  • The pattern of negator emergence (no → not → ’nt) follows the frequency of negators in the input; that is negators used frequently in the input are the first to emerge in the child’s speech (Cameron-Faulkner et al., 2007).

  • Children’s willingness to construct a productive schema reflects their experience with analogous lexical patterns in the input (Bannard and Matthews, 2010).

  • Children are less likely to make errors on sentences containing high-frequency verbs compared low frequency verbs (Brooks and Tomasello, 1999; Theakston, 2004; Ambridge et al., 2008).

Overall it seems there is good evidence to support the usage-based prediction that language structure emerges in ontogeny out of experience (viz. use) and when a child uses core usage-based cognitive processes – categorization, analogy, form-meaning mapping, chunking, exemplar/item-based representations – to find and use communicatively meaningful units.

Language Processing and Use

In this section we look at how the “cognitive commitment” of usage-based theory has been used to explain findings in language processing.

How words are stored and used

The approach from the generativist tradition has been to propose a fundamental division of labor between linguistic units and the rules that combine them into acceptable combinations, for example, singular muggle + plural marker s = plural muggles (e.g., Pinker, 1999). The usage-based view is that productivity is a result of knowledge generalized over usage events. Pluralizing a new word like muggle is by analogy to a relevant class of linguistic experience. Even regular forms, such as books, dogs, and cars, if encountered frequently enough are represented and stored as chunks. This process combines several of the core cognitive principles we are interested in here – categorization, analogy, chunking, and a rich memory for exemplars so plural formation is a good to test case for usage-based theory.

The well-established and unsurprising fact is that people are quicker to recognize high-frequency words; the more often a word is encountered the more entrenched that representation is and the more easily it is retrieved. The interesting question here is whether peoples’ response times are influenced by the frequency of the plural word form, e.g., books or by the combined frequency of the forms book + books. If plurals are stored separately, as predicted by usage-based approaches, we should expect that the frequency of the plural to be the crucial factor. Sereno and Jongman (1997) flashed words interspersed with non-words onto a monitor and asked participants whether the word was a word or not. They created two lists of nouns which were matched for their overall frequency in the language, but differed with respect to the ratio of singular to plural forms. List A contained words which predominantly occurred in the singular (island, river, kitchen, village) whereas list B contained forms that occurred equally often in singular and plural forms (statement, window, expense, error). In support of the usage-based hypothesis, singulars from List A were recognized more quickly than singulars from list B and plurals from group B were recognized more quickly than plurals from list A. Further research confirms their conclusions for plural formation (e.g., Baayen et al., 1997; Alegre and Gordon, 1999) and the same argument, namely, that high-frequency forms tend to be stored and processed as wholes, has also been extended to cover past tense formation in English (Bybee, 1999). The overall picture is one of a rich memory for exemplars, whereby sequences of units that frequently co-occur cohere to form more complex chunks (Reali and Christiansen, 2007; Ellis et al., 2008; Kapatsinski and Radicke, 2009).

This sensitivity to detailed distributional information exists not just at the levels of words but on many levels of linguistic analysis; from words to larger chunks to phrases (see Diessel, 2007 and Ellis, 2002 for reviews). For example, in a series of studies, Arnon and Neal (2010) showed that comprehenders are sensitive to the frequencies of compositional four-word phrases (e.g., don’t have to worry) such that more frequent phrases were processed faster (cf. Bannard and Matthews, 2010 for an interesting comparison with children). The effect was not reducible to the frequency of the individual words or substrings and was observed across the entire frequency range (for low-, mid-, and high-frequency phrases). They conclude that comprehenders seem to learn and store frequency information about multi-word phrases. These findings adds to the growing processing literature that broadly supports the usage-based position: processing models capture and predict multi-level frequency effects and support accounts where linguistic knowledge consists of patterns of varying sizes and levels of abstraction.

Overall the psycholinguistic evidence supports the idea that representations are instantiated in a vast network of structured knowledge, which is encyclopedia-like in nature and in scope (see review by Elman, 2009). Knowledge of fairly specific (and sometimes idiosyncratic) aspects of verbal usage patterns is available and recruited early in sentence processing. For example:

  • Sentences of the type the boy heard the story was interesting have structural ambiguity. At the point of parsing the story, it could be the direct object (DO) of heard or it could be the subject noun of a sentential complement (SC), as it was in the above example. Hare et al. (2003, 2004) showed that it was possible to induce a DO or SC readings of the same verb on the basis of whether the preverbal context was associated with one reading or another (as determined from a corpus of natural speech). The message here is that people are sensitive to statistical patterns of usage that are associated with specific usages of an individual verb.

  • McRae et al. (1998) showed that The cop arrested promoted a main verb reading (the cop arrested X) over a reduced relative (the cop arrested by the X). Conversely, the criminal arrested promoted a reduced relative over a main verb reading. McRae concludes that the thematic role specifications for verbs must go beyond the traditional categories like agent, patient instrument, beneficiary to include very detailed information about the preferred fillers of the role and the prototypical events in which they take part (in the above example that criminals are more likely to be arrested than do the arresting and vice versa for cops).

  • Homonyms prime each other, for example bank (financial institution) momentarily activates the representation bank (land side of river), showing that linguistic knowledge is organized along phonological as well as the semantic dimensions (see Figure 1) (Swinney, 1979; Seidenberg et al., 1982).

All of this argues against a serial account of sentence processing where syntax proposes a structural interpretation for semantics to subsequently cash out (Frazier, 1987, 1989; Clifton and Frazier, 1989). Moreover, verbal knowledge is sensitive to contingencies (usage patterns) that hold across agents, aspect, instruments, event knowledge, and broader contextual discourse, so that altering any one may skew the construal of what is communicated. It seems unlikely then that syntactic knowledge is encapsulated from semantic, pragmatic, and world knowledge (e.g., Fodor, 1995). Rather, the evidence is converging on the idea of words as probabilistic cues that point to a conceptual space of possibilities, which is revised and honed as the discourse unfolds between speakers.

Language Diversity and Use

Like all scientific enterprises, linguistics is in the business of finding and explaining patterns. Why are languages the way they are, rather than some other way they could be? Again, we will examine the extent to which the cognitive commitment of usage-based linguistics has been able to account for findings at this level of description. Word order provides a good example. The world’s languages can be categorized on the basis of how they order the basic constituents of a sentence – subject, object, and verb – which function to coordinate “who did what to whom.” Of the six logically possible word orders this creates, some are much more prevalent than others. A survey of 402 languages reveals that the majority of languages favor either SOV (44.78%) or SVO (41.79%) with the other possibilities – VSO (9.20%), VOS (2.99%), OVS (1.24%), or OSV (0.00%) – significantly less popular (Tomlin, 1986).

There are several mechanisms that could be at work here to create this typological distribution. For example, we know there is a general preference to speak of given information before information that is new to the discourse (MacWhinney and Bates, 1978; Bock and Irwin, 1980; Prat-Sala and Branigan, 2000; Ferreira and Yoshita, 2003), a preference for shorter dependency length (Hawkins, 1994, 2007) and a preference for efficient information transfer (Maurits et al., 2010). Over historical time frames the serial position becomes grammaticalized into subject, verb, and object position, hence Givón’s (1979, p. 208–209) aphorism “today’s syntax is yesterday’s pragmatic discourse.” However, this doesn’t explain why any particular language looks the way it does; here we need a historical perspective. Dunn et al. (2011) used computational phylogenetics to show that typological variation in word order could be explained as a function of the iterated learning processes of cultural evolution. Croft et al. (2011) provide criticism of their methodology – the absence of any Type II error analysis to assess the rate of false negatives, the absence of contact effects and the nature of the phylogenies used – although they are in favor of the general approach. These criticisms do not undermine the wider point, namely, that popularity of word orders across languages can be explained in terms of general cognitive principles (e.g., pressure for iconicity of form and function, or concise representation of salient/frequent concepts; see section below). Why any particular language has come to the combination of solutions it has, needs reference to its historical antecedents/evolution (Bybee, 2010). To preface a distinction we return to in the final section, this can be thought of as the difference between cognition permitting a particular language vs. cognition entailing a particular language.

In the context of historical antecedents, an analogy with biological evolution may be informative. Evolution has to work with what it’s got, cumulatively tinkering with solutions to problems that have worked well enough for previous generations, but which might not be considered “ideal” if one could start afresh (e.g., the backward installed retina in humans). An evolutionary biologist could ask the question “Why do we only see the mammals we do given all the possible mammals that could exist but don’t?” For the biologist, different mammals could be thought of as a record of competing motivations, that have over time explored some of the space of what is physiological plausible for a mammal to be. For a particular feature of the animal’s development, for example the skeleton, a bat could be thought of as occupying one corner of this space while an elephant skeleton is in another – extreme variations on an underlying theme. Different languages are also a history of competing motivations that have explored some of the space of what is communicatively possible. Over time languages have radiated to different points in this space. For a particular feature of the language development, for example the sound system, in one corner there might be a three-vowel system (e.g., Greenlandic, an Eskimo-Aleut language) while in another corner is a language with 24 vowels (e.g., !Xu, a Khoisan language). Importantly, as language is a complex adaptive system, evolving toward an extreme in one direction will have functional consequences for the system as a whole. Just as a bat skeleton will place certain functional demands on the rest of its physiology, so it is with language. In languages with freer word order, the communicative work that is done by a fixed word order in other languages must be picked up by other aspects of the system, e.g., morphology and pragmatic inference. The analogy with biological evolution might be useful in another way. The eye has independently evolved in several different species, converging on a similar solution to a similar engineering problem. The major nuts and bolts of grammar (e.g., word-order, case-agreement, tense-aspect) that appear time after time in the world’s languages could be thought of as historically popular solutions to similar communicative and coordination problems, such as sharing, requesting, and informing. Having set out the general usage-based picture with respect to the role of history, we take a closer look at the cognitive constraints on cross-linguistic structure and assess whether this helps explain typological similarity and diversity.

Explaining similarity and diversity

The idea that languages are mostly alike has been undermined by the growing amount of evidence that languages are actually quite distinct (e.g., Bowerman and Choi, 2001; Evans and Levinson, 2009). The remaining similarities can typically be explained with respect to four domain-general classes of constraint which simultaneously act to shape language: perceptuo-motor factors, cognitive limitations on learning and processing, constraints from thought, and pragmatic constraints (e.g., Goldberg, 2006; Diessel, 2007, 2011; Ambridge and Goldberg, 2008; Christiansen and Chater, 2008).

Information-theoretic approaches to communicative efficiency have shown how human cognitive abilities directly or indirectly constrain the space of possible grammars (for a recent review of this, see Jaeger and Tily, 2011). Processing difficulty in comprehension and production can arise when the sentence overloads the memory systems or contains combinations of words which are infrequent, unexpected or for which there are competing cues. There are several ways in which on-line processing difficulty and a drive for communicative efficiency might constrain the typological distribution of grammars, for example, in acquisition, less complex forms might be learned preferentially due to higher frequency in the input. The processing approach to typology suggests that grammars preferentially conventionalize linguistic structures that are processed more efficiently (Hawkins, 1994, 2007). Evidence from English and German suggests that the average dependency length (known to correlate with processing difficulty; e.g., Gibson, 1998) in these languages is close to the theoretical minimum and far below what would be expected by chance (e.g., Gildea and Temperley, 2010). Moreover, work investigating learner’s preferences in the artificial language learning paradigm show that (a) learners of experimentally designed languages acquire typologically frequent patterns more easily than typologically infrequent patterns (Christiansen, 2000; Finley and Badecker, 2008; Hupp et al., 2009, St Clair et al., 2009); and, (b) learners restructure the input they receive shifting the acquired language toward typologically natural patterns (Fedzechkina et al., 2011; Culbertson et al., 2012).

The sheer diversity of forms that languages take presents all theories with a massive challenge. For example, as far as know, Pirahã is the only language in the world to use the sound of a voiced linguolabial lateral double-flap (Everett, 2012). As Everett points out, all theories of language would struggle to predict both its existence and rarity. In fact, it is much easier to identify common patterns of language change than it is to find cross-linguistic similarities (Bybee, 2010). Usage-based theories argue this is because there is a universal set of cognitive processes underlying cross-linguistic cycles (e.g., grammaticization, pidginization, and creolization) and the fact that all languages have to pass through the bottleneck of what is learnable (Bybee et al., 1994; Diessel, 2007, 2011; Heine and Kuteva, 2007; Christiansen and Chater, 2008).

Speaking the same language

It is uncontroversial that, as a function of linguistic experience, different speakers of the same language have different dialects, vocabularies, phrases, idioms, accents, and so on. For some reason, many linguists from all theoretical persuasions have resisted applying this logic to grammar. There is a wide spread assumption that adults are converging on the same grammar when they learn a particular language (Seidenberg, 1997, p. 9; Crain and Lillo-Martin, 1999, p. 1600; Nowak et al., 2001, p. 114). Dąbrowska (2012) challenges the prevailing wisdom by showing that different speakers have different grammars as a function of their individual usage histories. For example, the inflections on the polish dative are highly predictable and so in theory all adults should share the same intuitions: -owi for masculine nouns, -u for neuter nouns, and -e, -i/y for feminines. Dąbrowska (2008) asked adults to use nonce words, presented in the nominative, in contexts that required the dative. Individual scores on the inflection task ranged from 29 to 100% correct. The usage-based hypothesis would predict familiarity with noun exemplars (and thus familiarity with inflecting them) would correlate with the productivity of a particular morphological schema. This is what was found, with performance on the task positively correlated with vocabulary (r = 0.65, p < 0.001), which is itself correlated strongly in this experiment with years spent in formal education (r = 0.72, p < 0.001).

Analogous adult variation in comprehension has been demonstrated with the active-passive distinction (Dąbrowska and Street, 2006) and quantifiers in English (Brooks and Sekerina, 2006). The fact that both passive and quantifier performance could be improved with training (Street and Da?browska, 2010) underlies the role of use. Dąbrowska (2012) concludes that the results from English and Polish show that some speakers extract only fairly specific, local, and lexically based generalization whereas others are able to be more flexible and apply more abstract patterns. In general, this ability was tightly correlated with use, in a particular a more varied linguistic experience, which in this case was often education-related. It is worth noting that in the terminology of generativist grammar, we are talking about core competence here: passives, complex sentences, quantifiers, and morphological inflection. Different levels of grammatical attainment in healthy adults – even in “core competency” – are what one would expect if people build their grammar bottom-up as a function of their linguistic experience.

Philosophical Foundations and Use

Is there any broad philosophy that a usage-based approach to language follows? One candidate would be a non-essentialist view of describing the world (Janicki, 2006; Goldberg, 2009). Plato used the Greek word logos to mean the “ultimate essence”; the underlying reality or true nature of a thing that one cannot observe directly. So for instance, we understand circles as circles with respect to an abstract, unchanging ideal of what a circle is, laid out by well-defined criteria, such as “its area is equal to πr2.” With this mindset, one can then sensibly ask what is the essential quiddity or “whatness” for all sorts of things; “what is beauty,” “what is truth,” and so on. This kind of essentialist thinking was reincarnated in the philosophy of the Logical Positivists who sought to verify whether propositions were true or false with respect to the underlying logical structure of language. If we could only do this, as Leibniz had hoped, then “two philosophers who disagree about a point should, instead of arguing fruitlessly and endlessly, be able to take out their pencils, sit down amicably at their desks, and say ‘Let us calculate.”’

In one of the most famous (and honest) about-turns in intellectual history, Wittgenstein (1953/2001) completely abandoned his involvement in this approach, no longer so interested in the relationship between meaning and truth as that between meaning and use – hence the quote at the beginning of this article. The change in his thinking can be summarized in the change of his metaphors; from language as a picture (true propositions are those that picture the world as it is) to language as a tool. Tools are defined by what they do, how they are used. He realized that the labeling of a word presupposes understanding a deeper agreement between communicators about the way the word is being used. In relation to this he advocated the anti-essentialist notion of family-resemblance; the idea that categories are graded in nature, with better-or-worse exemplars. Against this backdrop of normative agreements, we can do things with language. Performatives such as I declare you man and wife, You are now under arrest, I condemn you to prison, I name this child, I promise to pay the bearer, impinge on the world because of the mutually held belief between members of a group that in certain contexts these words have force (Austin, 1962; Searle, 1969).

Despite the influence of Wittgenstein, essentialist thinking was still alive and well in much of twentieth century linguistics: the idea that there is an essence of a word that could neatly fit into a lexicon, rather than seeing words as instantiated in a vast network of encyclopedic knowledge (Elman, 2009); the idea that there is an essence of language that all speakers of the same language share, rather than an overlapping set of intuitions defined by the linguistic experience of the individuals (Dąbrowska, 2012); the idea that there is an universal essence to grammar (justifying a distinction between competence and performance), rather than acknowledging the diversity across languages (Bowerman and Choi, 2001; Evans and Levinson, 2009).

Following Popper (1957), evolutionary theorist Mayr (1942) suggested the antidote for essentialism is “population thinking” – a profile of characteristics across a group – just as Wittgenstein had discussed with the idea of family resemblance. It was this kind slipperiness in language that ultimately frustrated the Logical Positivists but which usage-based approaches have turned it into a productive research agenda: prototypes, conceptual metaphors, and probabilistic approaches to syntactic and lexical processing (Ellis, 2002; MacDonald and Christiansen, 2002; Jurafsky, 2003) and grammatical continua, for example, from more verb-like to less noun-like (Harris, 1981; Taylor, 2003).

Successes, Challenges, and Debates for the Usage-Based Approach

From the evidence reviewed here, the cognitive commitment of usage-based linguistics “to render accounts of syntax, morphology, phonology, and word meaning consonant with aspects of cognition” has accounted for a large range of empirical findings across the domains of language acquisition, processing, and typology. It is of course not without its weaknesses and is there is by no means a consensus as to what usage-based theory is or should be. Here we reflect on what some these debates are, which leads to the final section on where usage-based theory might go from here.

Perhaps unsurprisingly some of the strengths of usage-based theory are also related to its weaknesses; what it gains in breath of explanation it sometimes compromises in depth, for example being able to accommodate a large range of cross-linguistic findings means that stipulating in any detail, a priori, which processing constraints and input properties are most important, and when, is very difficult. The problem can be particularly acute in language-acquisition research. The hope is, that once enough of these types of experiments have been conducted, and the results synthesized, usage-based theory will evolve into something that generates tighter “riskier” predictions in the Popperian sense. This would also go a long way to engaging those from different theoretical approaches to language acquisition who are skeptical of the usage-based approach for this reason – “what pattern of results couldn’t a usage-based theory explain.” One kind of approach that seems particularly successful in generating this kind of rigor is combining corpus and experimental methods to answer a focused question about learning (e.g., Goldberg et al., 2004; Dąbrowska, 2008; Bannard and Matthews, 2010). In this approach one can use the distributions in the input as the starting point to generate predictions, and then through experimental manipulation, get closer to establishing some kind of cause-and-effect.

Those working in non-usage-based theory can become frustrated when usage-based theorists argue lexical specificity supports the theory, but then are also not worried by evidence of abstraction, since the child’s knowledge is predicted to become abstract at some point in development anyway. Clear developmental predictions about how the process of abstraction should develop, including which systems should become abstract first, are needed. This would also help counter claims that the theory is discontinuous (lexical specificity first, abstraction later). Clearly related to this issue is being able to model language acquisition as a complex dynamic system. For instance, say a child hears the utterance The dog tickles Mary. With no other analog in her experience she treats it as an instance of itself, perhaps even storing it as the chunk ThedogticklesMary. One might think of this as all constructions starting life toward the more idiomatic end of the constructional spectrum. However, the next time she hears The dog tickles Peter it “counts” as both an instance of The dog tickles Peter and an instance of The dog tickles X. The constriction has moved from being purely idiomatic to having a productive slot, X. The difference between this and kick the bucket is that the latter is much less productive; compare hit the bucket, kick the pail1. After many more examples, the child then hears The dog tickles Mary for the second time but now it might count as an instance of The dog tickles Mary, The dog tickles X, The Y tickles X, agent-action-patient, subject verb object, and so on. So, the same form is counted as different instances of different things at different times. The situation is analogous to believing a bat is an instance of a bird and then re-categorizing later it as a mammal, as one learns more about the world. The question is, which level of representation do developmental models count and when? Usage-based theories need more psychologically plausible models of what gets treated as a chunk when, and hence “counted” in any distributional analysis (Arnon, 2011). Dynamic systems theory and connectionist models try to address this issue by designing models that grow and internally reorganize themselves (e.g., Thelen and Smith, 1995) but it remains an outstanding challenge for a descriptively and predictively adequate usage-based theory.

A key part of responding to this challenge will be to specify in greater detail the mechanisms of generalization, specifically a mechanistic account of the dimensions over which children and adults make (and do not make) analogies. As usage-based approaches have argued, relational structure, and mapping between representations is a fundamental psychological process that underpins forming these abstract connections. In terms of linguistic form, we know variation sets are powerful cross-sentential cues to generalization – two or more sentences that share at least one lexical element, for example, look at the bunny, the bunny is brown, silly bunny, what a cute bunny, and so on (Küntay and Slobin, 1996; Waterfall, 2006; Waterfall and Edelman, 2009). Longitudinal studies show that infants are better at structurally appropriate use of nouns and verbs that had occurred in their caregivers’ speech within variation sets, compared to those that did not (Nelson, 1977; Hoff-Ginsberg, 1986, 1990; Waterfall, 2006). Moreover, the cue is relatively available: between 20 and 80% of utterances in a sample of English CDS occur within these variation sets – depending on the threshold of intervening sentences and therefore the definition of “set” (similar statistics apply to Turkish and Mandarin, Küntay and Slobin, 1996; Waterfall, 2006). Clearly generalizations are made not just over form but over meaning also (even if the forms share nothing in common) and here there is less consensus on what counts as a variation set of meaning or even how to formalize one. Usage-based approaches might respond by saying that the meaning is the sum total of how the form is used in a communicative context, however for those seeking more detail, usage-based theorists need to provide a more mechanistic accounts that integrates semantic and formal generalizations. One way to tackle this is to ask, where does the meaning of linguistic form x come from in the child’s environment? For example, in many of the world’s languages grammatical aspect is used to indicate how events unfold over time. In English, activities that are ongoing can be distinguished from those that are completed using the morphological marker -ing. Using naturalistic observations of children, Ibbotson et al. (2013b) quantified the availability and reliability of the imperfective form in the communicative context of the child performing actions. They found two features of the communicative context reliably mapped onto the functions of the imperfective, namely, that events are construed as ongoing and from within. In theory grammatical aspect is potentially an abstract notion, however, this shows how the pragmatic and referential context in which a child hears language may serve to limit the degrees of freedom on what linguistics constructions mean and therefore the directions in which analogies are made (see also Ibbotson, 2011).

The usage-based” approach is of course something of a generalization in itself; there are almost as many usage-based theories as there are theorists. A major contention in the field, which points to future research, is over what level of representation best characterizes usage patterns. For example, although Ninio (2011) and Goldberg (2006) agree on many of the cognitive principles that underpin usage-based approaches, they radically disagree about the role of semantic similarity in generalization and what are the fundamental units of grammar. Namely, whether they are best characterized as merge-dependency couplets or constructions. Schematic constructions like X verbs Y are by no means deemed necessary for all usage-based accounts either. For example, Daelemans and van den Bosch’s (2005) radically exemplar-based computational model, which is still very much rooted in the cognitive linguistic, usage-based approach, questions the necessity of schematic knowledge. The implication is that a large amount of linguistic knowledge may consist of rather specific, low-level knowledge, ultimately instantiated in the memory traces of specific instances. Alternatively, some cognitive grammars posit a degree of schematicity, but only to the extent that they are schematic for actually occurring structures and actually occurring instances. Croft (2001) argues that such things as subjects and DO only exist in constructions (not as schemas that exists as themselves) and are different entities when they appear in different constructions, for example a transitive-subject, a passive-subject, and there-subject. In general though, what unifies usage-based models is a general skepticism about underlying structures that diverge from surface structure with respect to the ordering and content of constituent parts (Langacker, 1987).

Another potential area of development relates to the interface between social-cognitive representations and grammatical representations. There is a lot of work that has emerged in recent years on infants’ development of social cognition and pragmatic reasoning, but it has yet to be worked through in any detail how that understanding interacts with and/or constrains syntactic representations and generalizations. It seems important then that usage-based approaches start integrating the wealth of experimental data on social cognition with the statistical syntactic learning literature. One area that seems particularly relevant here is the grammar-attention interface. For example, Ibbotson et al. (2013a) investigated whether children (3- and 4-year-olds) and adults can use the active/passive alternation – essentially a choice of subject – in a way that is consistent with the eye-gaze of the speaker. Previous work suggests the function of the subject position can be grounded in attentional mechanisms (Tomlin, 1995, 1997). Eye-gaze is one powerful source of directing attention that we know adults and young children are sensitive to; furthermore, we know adults are more likely to look at the subject of their sentence than any other character (Griffin and Bock, 2000; Gleitman et al., 2007). They demonstrated that older children and adults are able to use speaker-gaze to choose a felicitous subject when describing a scene with both agent-focused and patient focused cues.

Taking the “developmental cognitive linguistics” enterprise to its logical conclusion, one of the big questions is whether there are any purely linguistic representations or can all linguistic categories be traced back or decomposed into the functional or communicative roles they play. In the next section we outline why there might be fundamental limits of what we can explain with a purely cognitive conception of usage-based processes.

Culture and Use

Overall it might be argued that, while significant challenges remain, the usage-based commitment to domain-general cognitive processes has been able to account for a large range of empirical findings across the domains of language acquisition, processing, and typology. Below we briefly sketch out some examples that do not seem to fit easily into this category and present a challenge for a cognitive process level of explanation.

Several authors have argued that we need to acknowledge language as part of a broader species-specific adaptation for cultural life in general, with linguistic norms as specific coordination solutions to the general problem of coordination (Clark, 1996; Tomasello, 1999, 2008; Everett, 2012). It is important to outline what one thinks is special about humans as many of the usage-based claims about core cognitive processes in language – categorization, chunking, rich item-based memory – are likely to be true of other species (and computers). However once our view of language, and more generally of communication, is one of a social act in the context of normative agreements and cooperative reasoning, it is possible to say why domain-general cognitive processes and even species-general processes might be necessary but not sufficient for language.

Groupishness and normativity

People see themselves as belonging to families, cliques, nations, clans, religions – and of course languages. Being part of a group comes with expectations about how one ought to act and think – norms. For example, I tacitly expect other English speakers to put adjectives before the noun they modify. And if they don’t I might tell them that they should.

Cross-culturally, people seem particularly adept at reasoning about normative matters compared to non-normative matters (Cosmides and Tooby, 2008). By 3-years-of-age children are better at reasoning about violations in deontic conditionals, e.g., if x then y must/should do z, than they are with indicative conditions, e.g., if x then y does z (Cummins, 1996a,b; Harris and Núñez, 1996). We also know young children from diverse cultural backgrounds “overimitate” adults’ behavior, for instance copying non-functional means to a goal-directed action (Lyons et al., 2007; Nielsen and Tomaselli, 2010). By comparison, Chimpanzees in same situation drop the unnecessary steps and focus on the goal (Tennie et al., 2009; Whiten et al., 2009). This is important as the ability to produce high fidelity copies of cultural tools is a necessary precursor for cumulative cultural evolution to work: if you can’t copy a wheel then you will have to wait for someone to reinvent it. Moreover, the advantage of a general adaptation to imitate is that it doesn’t need to specify “copy what works” because the fact that enough adults are doing it shows at the very least it works well enough for them to still be alive (on average). Chimpanzees seem to exhibit some evolutionary precursors of normative cognition (tolerant societies, well-developed social-cognitive skills, empathetic competence) but appear to lack the shared intentionality that would convert quasi-social norms into human-like collectivized norms (Tomasello and Rakoczy, 2003; Rudolf von Rohr et al., 2011). Thus it seems natural selection has favored some important elements of the architecture of normative cognition – a disposition to learn prevalent norms (imitation) to comply with norms and enforce them (Boyd and Richerson, 1992; Henrich and Boyd, 2001; Boyd et al., 2003; Chudek and Henrich, 2011).

Cultural constraints on grammar

What is really interesting for the present discussion is when culture and a normative cognition start to interact in a way that starts to constrain grammar. Kulick (1992, p. 2) explains an example of where a linguistic niche is acquired and maintained through normative cognition and is clearly grammatical in nature. Kulick describes New Guinean communities that have “purposely fostered linguistic diversity because they have seen language as a highly salient marker of group identity…[they] have cultivated linguistic differences as a way of “exaggerating” themselves in relation to their neighbors … One community [of Buian language speakers], for instance, switched all its masculine and feminine gender agreements, so that its language’s gender markings were the exact opposite of those of the dialects of the same language spoken in neighboring villages; other communities replaced old words with new ones in order to “be different” from their neighbors’ dialects.”

Kulick (1992) also gives examples from the Selepet speakers of a New Guinean village who, overnight, decided to change their word for “no” from bia to bune explaining that they wanted to be distinct from other Selepet speakers in a neighboring village. The Buian gender agreement example does not sit easily in any of the core usage-based cognitive processes of categorization, analogy, chunking, and so on, that featured so prominently in the previous sections – at least not in a way that is predictive of the Buian structural change. Instead of principles of communicative efficiency, ease of understanding, informational organization, and so on we have to appeal to a different source of linguistic structure to explain the patterns we see, namely the kind of normative reasoning and cultural learning we discussed above (swopping gender agreement to be different from your neighbors does not really have anything to do with communicative efficiency, indeed, in the short term it probably reduces efficiency). So, the interesting examples are where grammatical structure itself is being shaped by culture and this has important implications for explaining linguistic patterns within usage-based approaches. Below we briefly introduce three examples:

  1. When a concept is sufficiently prominent in a culture, that is part of the shared values, it can predict what is left unsaid, as in the case of Amele a language spoken in New Guinea. It is an SOV language but when the meaning of “giving” is expressed the verb is omitted. For example
    Jo eu ihaciadigen
    House that show
    I will show that house to you
    The verb ihac means “to show” but in the example below the verb is omitted
    Naus Dege houten
    Name name pig
    Naus [gave] a pig to Dege
    (Everett, 2012, p. 194)
    Roberts (1998) argues that there is no verb “to give” because giving is so basic to Amele culture that this can be left backgrounded.
  2. Speakers of Wari’, an Amazonian Indian language, report on others’ thoughts, character, reactions, and other intentional states by means of a quotative structure. Regardless of whether people say something or not they are quoted as saying so in order to communicate what the speaker believes they were thinking. Everett (2012) argues this structure can be traced back to, and explained by, the way Amazonian Indians use a metaphor of “motives” and “will,” as in “the sky says it is going to rain,” “the Tapir says it will run from me,” and “John said he was tired of talking with us,” even when John did not say this, but he behaved as though he did. Because of this the verb “to say” is omitted and the quotation structure (capitalized below) in Wari’ acts as the verb:
    MA’ CO MAO NAIN GUJARÁ nanam ‘oro narima, taramaxicon
    ‘Who went to the city of Guajará?’ [said] the chief to the women.’
    (Everett, 2012, p. 196)
    In Wari a high cultural value is placed on evidence for beliefs and since intentions require first-hand evidence this created a linguistic niche filled by the quotative structure which does not commit the speaker to first-hand knowledge.
  3. Relatedly, Pirahã, another Amazonian language, requires evidence for assertions – a declarative has to be witnessed, heard from a third party or reasoned from the facts. Pirahã marks this with a suffix, for example – hiai (hearsay), sibiga (deduced or inferred), and xáágahá (observed). The verb and the objects implicated by the verb are obliged to be licensed by the verb’s evidential suffix. The culture places high value on evidence for declarations, which in turn is realized on the evidential suffix, which in turn controls the verbal frame. Because in most languages evidentials are limited to main clauses, the claim is that embedding clauses (recursion) is not possible in Pirahã on a clausal level – as a subordinate clause would not be licensed by the evidential, violating the cultural/grammatical constraints.

There are other intriguing lines of research that show how culture impinges on grammar, for example, Deixis, grammar, and culture (Perkins, 1992) describes an inverse correlation between the technological state of a culture and the complexity of their pronoun system. More generally, the key point here is that there exists a pattern of structural use, omission, and agreement that is difficult to predict without expanding the circle of explanations to include cultural as well as cognitive factors. The interpretations of these patterns are controversial (Corballis, 2011) and riddled with potential confounds but they do point to level of linguistic analysis that might be beyond usage-based cognitive principles.

The same argument can be applied at different levels of granularity depending on which source of cultural variation we are focused on. We have known since the work of Labov and Trudgill that heterogeneity in language structure correlates with socio-linguistic variables of class, social network, and ethnicity, for example – all of which could analyzed within a normative framework. What this means is that usage-based cognitive constraints permit a possible space of languages but might not entail any particular language – the boundaries of the space of cognition do not make contact with that of language in way that allows those predictions. The rather weak predictive synthesis between these domains is in some sense a consequence of the “cognitive commitment” which seeks to make linguistics “merely” consonant with aspects of cognition. The integration of cultural constrains with cognitive constraints will place further limits on the space of possible and impossible languages, creating tighter predictions. This would be an example of reductionism – or consilience to use E. O. Wilson’s term – in the better sense of the word: where each domain of understanding is grounded in the next but with no domain being dispensable and where the emphasis is on unifying, integrating or synthesizing aspects of knowledge.

Conclusion

Usage-based theories of representation see language as a complex adaptive system; the interaction between cognition and use. Findings from language acquisition research, typology, and psycholinguistics are converging on the idea that language representations are fundamentally built out of use and generalizations over those usage events. Interestingly, none of the fundamental mechanisms of the usage-based approach are required to be a language-specific adaptation. Language shows creativity, categories, and recursion because people think creatively, categorically, and recursively. Here we have also drawn special attention to a set of culturally generated structural patterns that seem to lie beyond the explanation of the core usage-based cognitive processes. As well as addressing the need for greater clarity on the mechanisms of generalizations and the fundamental units of grammar, we suggest one of the next big challenges for usage-based theory will be unify the anthropological linguistic data with usage-based cognition.

Conflict of Interest Statement

The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.

Acknowledgments

Thank you to Anna Theakston, Elena Lieven, Inbal Arnon and Patricia Brooks who provided insightful comments on this paper. This work was funded by a postdoctoral research fellowship from the Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology, Leipzig.

Footnotes

1In fact even this idiom shows some flexibility in tense: he is going to kickØ the bucket vs. he has kicked the bucket.

References

  1. Alegre M., Gordon P. (1999). Frequency effects and the representational status of regular inflections. J. Mem. Lang. 40, 41–61 10.1006/jmla.1998.2607 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  2. Allport D. A. (1985). “Distributed memory, modular systems and dysphasia,” in Current Perspectives in Dysphasia, eds Newman S. K., Epstein R. (Edinburgh: Churchill Livingstone; ) 32–60 [Google Scholar]
  3. Ambridge B., Goldberg A. (2008). The island status of clausal complements: evidence in favor of an information structure explanation. Cogn. Linguist. 19, 357–389 10.1515/COGL.2008.014 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  4. Ambridge B., Lieven E. V. M. (2011). Child Language Acquisition: Contrasting Theoretical Approaches. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  5. Ambridge B., Pine J. M., Rowland C. F. (2011). Children use verb semantics to retreat from overgeneralization errors: a novel verb grammaticality judgment study. Cogn. Linguist. 22, 303–323 10.1515/cogl.2011.012 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  6. Ambridge B., Pine J. M., Rowland C. F., Chang F. (2012a). The roles of verb semantics, entrenchment and morphophonology in the retreat from dative argument structure overgeneralization errors. Language 88, 45–81 10.1353/lan.2012.0000 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  7. Ambridge B., Pine J. M., Rowland C. F. (2012b). Semantics versus statistics in the retreat from locative overgeneralization errors. Cognition 123, 260–279 10.1016/j.cognition.2012.01.002 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  8. Ambridge B., Pine J. M., Rowland C. F., Chang F., Bidgood A. (2013). The retreat from overgeneralization in child language acquisition: word learning, morphology and verb argument structure. Wiley Interdiscip. Rev. Cogn. Sci. 4, 47–62 10.1002/wcs.1207 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Ambridge B., Pine J. M., Rowland C. F., Young C. R. (2008). The effect of verb semantic class and verb frequency (entrenchment) on children’s and adults’ graded judgements of argument-structure overgeneralization errors. Cognition 106, 87–129 10.1016/j.cognition.2006.12.015 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Arnon I. (2011). “Units of learning in language acquisition,” in Experience, Variation and Generalization: Learning a First Language, Trends in Language Acquisition Research Series, eds Arnon I., Clark E. V. (Amsterdam: John Benjamins; ) 167–178 [Google Scholar]
  11. Arnon I., Neal S. (2010). More than words: frequency effects for multi-word phrases. J. Mem. Lang. 62, 67–82 10.1016/j.jml.2009.09.005 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  12. Aslin R. N., Pisoni D. B., Hennessy B. L., Perry A. J. (1981). Discrimination of voice onset time by human infants: new findings and implications for the effect of early experience. Child Dev. 52, 1135–1145 10.2307/1129499 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Austin J. L. (1962). How To Do Things With Words. Oxford: University Press [Google Scholar]
  14. Baayen R. H., Dijkstra T., Schreuder R. (1997). Singulars and plurals in Dutch: evidence for a parallel dual-route model. J. Mem. Lang. 37, 94–117 10.1006/jmla.1997.2509 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  15. Bannard C., Lieven E. (2009). “Repetition and reuse in child language learning,” in Formulaic Language. Volume II: Acquisition, Loss, Psychological reality, Functional Explanations, eds Corrigan R., Moravcsik E., Ouali H., Wheatley K. (Amsterdam: John Benjamins; ), 297–321 [Google Scholar]
  16. Bannard C., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2009). Modeling children’s early grammatical knowledge. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 106, 17284–17289 10.1073/pnas.0905638106 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Bannard C., Matthews D. (2010). Stored word sequences in language learning the effect of familiarity on children’s repetition of four-word combinations. Psychol. Sci. 19, 3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Bock J. K., Irwin D. E. (1980). Syntactic effects of information availability in sentence production. J. Verbal Learning Verbal Behav. 19, 467–484 10.1016/S0022-5371(80)90321-7 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  19. Bod R. (2009). From exemplar to grammar: a probabilistic analogy-based model of language learning. Cogn. Sci. 33, 752–793 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2009.01031.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Bowerman M., Choi S. (2001). “Shaping meanings for language: universal and language-specific in the acquisition of semantic categories,” in Language Acquisition and Conceptual Development, eds Bowerman M., Levinson S. C. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; ). [Google Scholar]
  21. Boyd B., Richerson P. J. (1992). Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethol. Sociobiol. 13, 171–195 10.1016/0162-3095(92)90032-Y [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  22. Boyd R., Gintis H., Bowles S., Richerson P. J. (2003). The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 100, 3531–3535 10.1073/pnas.0630443100 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  23. Braine M. D. S., Brooks P. J. (1995). “Verb argument structure and the problem of avoiding an over general grammar,” in Beyond Names for Things: Young Children’s Acquisition of Verbs, eds Tomasello M., Merriman W. E. (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; ), 352–376 [Google Scholar]
  24. Brooks P. J., Sekerina I. A. (2006). “Shallow processing of universal quantification: a comparison of monolingual and bilingual adults,” in Proceedings of the 28th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, Austin, 2450 [Google Scholar]
  25. Brooks P. J., Tomasello M. (1999). Young children learn to produce passives with nonce verbs. Dev. Psychol. 35, 29–44 10.1037/0012-1649.35.1.29 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Burnard L. (2000). User Reference Guide for the British National Corpus. Technical Report. Oxford: Oxford University Computing Services [Google Scholar]
  27. Bybee J. (1999). Use impacts morphological representation. Behav. Brain Sci. 22, 1016–1017 10.1017/S0140525X99252223 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  28. Bybee J. (2010). Language, Usage and Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  29. Bybee J., Perkins R., Pagliuca W. (1994). The Evolution of Grammar: Tense, Aspect and Modality in the Languages of the World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press [Google Scholar]
  30. Cameron-Faulkner T., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2003). A construction based analysis of child directed speech. Cogn. Sci. 27, 843–873 10.1207/s15516709cog2706_2 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  31. Cameron-Faulkner T., Lieven E. V., Theakston A. L. (2007). What part of no do children not understand? A usage-based account of multiword negation. J. Child Lang. 34, 251–282 10.1017/S0305000906007884 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Christiansen M. (2000). “Using artificial language learning to study language evolution: exploring the emergence of word order universals,” in The Evolution of Language: 3rd International Conference, eds Dessalles J. L., Ghadakpour L. (Paris: Ecole Nationale Superieure des Telecommunications; ), 45–48 [Google Scholar]
  33. Christiansen M., Chater N. (2008). Language as shaped by the brain. Behav. Brain Sci. 31, 489–509 10.1017/S0140525X08005281 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Chudek M., Henrich J. (2011). Culture-gene coevolution, norm-psychology and the emergence of human prosociality. Trends Cogn. Sci. 15, 218–226 10.1016/j.tics.2011.03.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  35. Clark H. H. (1996). Using Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  36. Clifton C., Frazier L. (1989). “Comprehending sentences with long-distance dependencies,” in Linguistic Structure in Language Processing, eds Carlson G. N., Tanenhaus M. K. (Dordrecht: Kluwer; ), 273–317 [Google Scholar]
  37. Corballis M. C. (2011). The Recursive Mind. Princeton: Princeton University Press [Google Scholar]
  38. Cosmides L., Tooby J. (2008). “Can a general deontic logic capture the facts of human moral reasoning? How the mind interprets social exchange rules and detects cheaters,” in Moral Psychology, Volume 1: The Evolution of Morality, ed. Armstrong W. S. A. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ), 53–120 [Google Scholar]
  39. Crain S., Lillo-Martin D. (1999). An Introduction to Linguistic Theory and Language Acquisition. Malden, MA: Blackwell [Google Scholar]
  40. Croft W. (1991). Syntactic Categories and Grammatical Relations: The Cognitive Organization of Information. Chicago: University of Chicago Press [Google Scholar]
  41. Croft W. (2001). Radical Construction Grammar: Syntactic Theory In Typological Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press [Google Scholar]
  42. Croft W., Bhattacharya T., Kleinschmidt D., Smith D. E., Jaeger T. F. (2011). Greenbergian universals, diachrony and statistical analysis. Linguist. Typol. 15, 433–453 [Google Scholar]
  43. Croft W., Cruse D. A. (2004). Cognitive linguistics. Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  44. Culbertson J., Smolensky P., Legendre G. (2012). Learning biases predict a word order universal. Cognition 122, 306–329 10.1016/j.cognition.2011.10.017 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Cummins D. D. (1996a). Evidence of deontic reasoning in 3- and 4-year-olds. Mem. Cognit. 24, 823–829 10.3758/BF03201105 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  46. Cummins D. D. (1996b). Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning. Mind Lang. 11, 160–190 10.1111/j.1468-0017.1996.tb00039.x [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  47. Dąbrowska E. (2012). Different speakers, different grammars: individual differences in native language attainment. Linguist. Approach. Biling. 2, 219–253 10.1075/lab.2.3.01dab [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  48. Daelemans W., van den Bosch A. (2005). Memory-Based Language Processing. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  49. Dąbrowska E. (2008). The effects of frequency and neighbourhood density on adult speakers’ productivity with Polish case inflections: an empirical test of usage-based approaches to morphology. J. Mem. Lang. 58, 931–951 10.1016/j.jml.2007.11.005 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  50. Dąbrowska E., Street J. (2006). Individual differences in language attainment: comprehension of passive sentences by native and non-native English speakers. Lang. Sci. 28, 604–615 10.1016/j.langsci.2005.11.014 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  51. Diessel H. (2007). Frequency effects in language acquisition, language use, and diachronic change. New Ideas Psychol. 25, 108–127 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.02.002 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  52. Diessel H. (2011). “Grammaticalization and language acquisition,” in The Oxford Handbook of Grammaticalization, eds Narrog H., Heine B. (Oxford: Oxford University Press; ) 130–141 [Google Scholar]
  53. Dunn M., Greenhill S. J., Levinson S. C., Gray R. D. (2011). Evolved structure of language shows lineage-specific trends in word-order universals. Nature 473, 79–82 10.1038/nature09923 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  54. Ellis N. C. (2002). Frequency effects in language processing: a review with implications for theories of implicit and explicit language acquisition. Stud. Second Lang. Acquis. 24, 143–188 10.1017/S0272263102002140 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  55. Ellis N. C., Simpson-Vlach R., Maynard C. (2008). Formulaic language in native and second-language speakers: psycholinguistics, corpus linguistics, and TESOL. TESOL Q. 42, 375–396 [Google Scholar]
  56. Elman J. (2009). On the meaning of words and dinosaur bones: lexical knowledge without a lexicon. Cogn. Sci. 33, 547–582 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2009.01023.x [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Evans N., Levinson S. (2009). The myth of language universals: language diversity and its importance for cognitive science. Behav. Brain Sci. 32, 429–492 10.1017/S0140525X0999094X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Everett D. (2012). Language: The Cultural Tool. London: Profile Books Ltd [Google Scholar]
  59. Fedzechkina M., Jaeger T., Newport E. (2011). “Functional biases in language learning: evidence from word order and case-marking interaction,” in Proceedings of CogSci, Austin [Google Scholar]
  60. Ferreira V. S., Yoshita H. (2003). Given-new ordering effects on the production of scrambled sentences in Japanese. J. Psycholinguist. Res. 32, 669–692 10.1023/A:1026146332132 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  61. Fillmore C., Kay P., O’Connor M. (1988). Regularity and idiomaticity in grammatical constructions: the case of let alone. Language 64, 501–538 10.2307/414531 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  62. Finley S., Badecker W. (2008). “Right-to-left biases for vowel harmony: evidence from artificial grammar,” in Proceedings of the 38th North East Linguistic Society Annual Meeting, Amherst [Google Scholar]
  63. Fodor J. D. (1995). “Thematic roles and modularity,” in Cognitive Models of Speech Processing, ed. Altmann G. T. M. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ), 434–456 [Google Scholar]
  64. Foley R. A., Lahr M. M. (2011). The evolution of the diversity of cultures. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 366, 1080–1089 10.1098/rstb.2010.0370 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  65. Frank M. C., Goodman N. D., Tenenbaum J. B. (2009). Using speakers’ referential intentions to model early cross-situational word learning. Psychol. Sci. 20, 2009. 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2009.02335.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  66. Franks J., Bransford J. (1971). Abstraction of visual patterns. J. Exp. Psychol. 90, 65–74 10.1037/h0031349 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  67. Frazier L. (1987). “Sentence processing: a tutorial review,” in Attention and Performance XII: The Psychology of Reading, ed. Coltheart M. (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; ) 559–586 [Google Scholar]
  68. Frazier L. (1989). “Against lexical generation of syntax,” in Lexical representation and process, ed. Marslen-Wilson W. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ) 505–528 [Google Scholar]
  69. Gentner D., Markman A. (1997). Structure mapping in analogy and similarity. Am. Psychol. 52, 45–56 10.1037/0003-066X.52.1.45 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  70. Gentner D., Markman A. B. (1995). “Similarity is like analogy: structural alignment in comparison,” in Similarity in Language, Thought and Perception, ed. Cacciari C. (Brussels: Brepols; ), 111–147 [Google Scholar]
  71. Gentner D., Medina J. (1998). Similarity and the development of rules. Cognition 65, 263–297 10.1016/S0010-0277(98)00002-X [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Gerken L. A., Wilson R., Lewis W. (2005). 17-Month-olds can use distributional cues to form syntactic categories. J. Child Lang. 32, 249–268 10.1017/S0305000904006786 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  73. Gibson E. (1998). Linguistic complexity: locality of syntactic dependencies. Cognition 68, 1–76 10.1016/S0010-0277(98)00035-3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  74. Gildea D., Temperley D. (2010). Do grammars minimize dependency length? Cogn. Sci. 34, 286–310 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2009.01073.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Givón T. (1995). Functionalism and Grammar. Amsterdam: Benjamins [Google Scholar]
  76. Givón T. (1979). On Understanding Grammar. New York: Academic Press [Google Scholar]
  77. Gleitman L. (1990). The structural sources of verb meanings. Lang. Acquis. 1, 3–55 10.1207/s15327817la0101_2 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  78. Gleitman L. R., January D., Nappa R., Trueswell J. C. (2007). On the give and take between event apprehension and utterance formulation. J. Mem. Lang. 57, 544–569 10.1016/j.jml.2007.01.007 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  79. Goldberg A. (2006). Constructions at Work: The Nature of Generalisations in Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press [Google Scholar]
  80. Goldberg A. (2009). Essentialism gives way to motivation. Behav. Brain Sci. 32, 455–456 10.1017/S0140525X09990677 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  81. Goldberg A., Casenhiser D., Sethuraman N. (2004). Learning argument structure generalizations. Cogn. Linguist. 15, 289–316 10.1515/cogl.2004.011 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  82. Goldin-Meadow S. (2007). Pointing sets the stage for learning language – and creating language. Child Dev. 78, 741–745 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2007.01029.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  83. Goldstone R. L. (1994). The role of similarity in categorization: providing a groundwork. Cognition 52, 125–157 10.1016/0010-0277(94)90065-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  84. Goldstone R. L., Medin D. L. (1994). “Interactive activation, similarity, and mapping: an overview,” in Advances in Connectionist and Neural Computation Theory, Vol. 2: Analogical Connections, eds Holyoak K., Barnden J. (Hillsdale, NJ: Ablex; ), 321–362 [Google Scholar]
  85. Goldstone R. L., Medin D. L., Gentner D. (1991). Relational similarity and the non-independence of features in similarity judgments. Cogn. Psychol. 23, 222–264 10.1016/0010-0285(91)90010-L [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  86. Griffin Z. M., Bock K. (2000). What the eyes say about speaking. Psychol. Sci. 11, 274–279 10.1111/1467-9280.00255 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. Hare M., McRae K., Elman J. L. (2003). Sense and structure: meaning as a determinant of verb subcategorization preferences. J. Mem. Lang. 48, 281–303 10.1016/S0749-596X(02)00516-8 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  88. Hare M., McRae K., Elman J. L. (2004). Admitting that admitting verb sense into corpus analyses makes sense. Lang. Cogn. Process. 19, 181–224 10.1080/01690960344000152 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  89. Harris P. L., Núñez M. (1996). Understanding of permission rules by preschool children. Child Dev. 67, 1572–1591 10.2307/1131719 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  90. Harris R. (1981). The Language Myth. London: Duckworth [Google Scholar]
  91. Hawkins J. A. (1994). A Performance Theory of Order and Constituency. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  92. Hawkins J. A. (2007). Processing typology and why psychologists need to know about it. New Ideas Psychol. 25, 87–107 10.1016/j.newideapsych.2007.02.003 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  93. Hebb D. O. (1949). The Organization of Behavior. New York: Wiley & Sons [Google Scholar]
  94. Heine B., Kuteva T. (2007). The Genesis of Grammar: A Reconstruction. Oxford: Oxford University Press [Google Scholar]
  95. Henrich J., Boyd R. (2001). Why people punish defectors: weak conformist transmission can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in cooperative dilemmas. J. Theor. Biol. 208, 79–89 10.1006/jtbi.2000.2202 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  96. Hoff-Ginsberg E. (1986). Function and structure in maternal speech: their relation to the child’s development of syntax. Dev. Psychol. 22, 155–163 10.1037/0012-1649.22.2.155 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  97. Hoff-Ginsberg E. (1990). Maternal speech and the child’s development of syntax: a further look. J. Child Lang. 17, 85–99 10.1017/S0305000900013118 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  98. Hopper P., Thompson S. (1980). Transitivity in grammar and discourse. Language 56, 215–299 10.2307/412659 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  99. Hupp J. M., Sloutsky V. M., Culicover P. W. (2009). Evidence for a domain-general mechanism underlying the suffixation preference in language. Lang. Cogn. Process. 24, 876–909 10.1080/01690960902719267 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  100. Ibbotson P. (2011). Abstracting grammar from social-cognitive foundations: a developmental sketch of learning. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 15, 331–343 10.1037/a0025609 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  101. Ibbotson P., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2013a). The attention-grammar interface: eye-gaze cues structural choice in children and adults. Cogn. Linguist. 24, (in press). [Google Scholar]
  102. Ibbotson P., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2013b). The communicative contexts of grammatical aspect use in English. J. Child Lang. (in press). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  103. Ibbotson P., Theakston A., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2011). The role of pronoun frames in early comprehension of transitive constructions in English. Lang. Learn. Dev. 7, 24–39 10.1080/15475441003732914 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  104. Ibbotson P., Theakston A., Lieven E., Tomasello M. (2012). Prototypical transitive semantics: developmental comparisons. Cogn. Sci. 36, 1–21 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2012.01249.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  105. Ibbotson P., Tomasello M. (2009). Prototype constructions in early language acquisition. Lang. Cogn. 1, 59–85 [Google Scholar]
  106. Jaeger F., Tily H. (2011). On language ‘utility’: processing complexity and communicative efficiency. Wiley Interdiscip. Rev. Cogn. Sci. 2, 323–335 10.1002/wcs.126 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  107. Janicki K. (2006). Language Misconceived: Arguing for Applied Cognitive Sociolinguistics. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates [Google Scholar]
  108. Jurafsky D. (2003). “Probabilistic modeling in psycholinguistics: linguistic comprehension and production,” in Probabilistic Linguistics, eds Bod R., Hay J., Jannedy S. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; ), 39–95 [Google Scholar]
  109. Kapatsinski V., Radicke J. (2009). “Frequency and the emergence of prefabs: evidence from monitoring,” in Formulaic Language: Volume 2. Acquisition, Loss, Psychological Reality, Functional Explanation, eds Corrigan R., Moravcsik E. A., Ouali H., Wheatley K. M. (Amsterdam: Benjamins; ), 499–520 [Google Scholar]
  110. Kirjavainen M., Theakston A. L., Lieven E. V. (2009). Can input explain children’s me-for-I errors? J. Child Lang. 36, 1091–1114 10.1017/S0305000909009350 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  111. Kirkham N., Slemmer J., Johnson S. (2002). Visual statistical learning in infancy: evidence for a domain general learning mechanism. Cognition 83, B35–B42 10.1016/S0010-0277(02)00004-5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  112. Kulick D. (1992). Language Shift and Cultural Reproduction: Socialization, Self, and Syncretism in a Papua New Guinean Village. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  113. Küntay A. C., Slobin D. (1996). “Listening to a Turkish mother: some puzzles for acquisition,” in Social Interaction, Social Context and Language: Essays in Honor of Susan Ervin-Tripp, eds Slobin D., Gerhardt J., Kyratis A., Guo T. (Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; ), 265–286 [Google Scholar]
  114. Langacker R. (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Vol. I Stanford: Stanford University Press [Google Scholar]
  115. Langacker R. (1991). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Vol. II Stanford: Stanford University Press [Google Scholar]
  116. Lyons D. E., Young A. G., Keil F. C. (2007). The hidden structure of overimitation. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 104, 19751–19756 10.1073/pnas.0704452104 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  117. MacDonald M. C., Christiansen M. H. (2002). Reassessing working memory: comment on Just and Carpenter (1992) and Waters and Caplan (1996). Psychol. Rev. 109, 35–54 10.1037/0033-295X.109.1.35 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  118. MacWhinney B. (2005). The emergence of linguistic form in time. Connect. Sci. 17, 191–211 10.1080/09540090500177687 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  119. MacWhinney B., Bates E. A. (1978). Sentential devices for conveying givenness and newness: a cross-cultural developmental study. J. Verbal Learning Verbal Behav. 17, 539–58 10.1016/S0022-5371(78)90326-2 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  120. Marcus G., Vijayan S., Bandi Rao S., Vishton P. (1999). Rule learning by seven-month-old infants. Science 283, 77–80 10.1126/science.283.5398.77 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  121. Maurits L., Perfors A., Navarro D. (2010). “Why are some word orders more common than others? A uniform information density account,” in Annual Conference on Neural Information Processing Systems, Lake Tahoe [Google Scholar]
  122. Mayr E. (1942). Systematics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press [Google Scholar]
  123. McRae K., Spivey-Knowlton M. J., Tanenhaus M. K. (1998). Modeling the influence of thematic fit (and other constraints) in on-line sentence comprehension. J. Mem. Lang. 38, 283–312 10.1006/jmla.1997.2543 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  124. Munakata Y., McClelland J. L. (2003). Connectionist models of development. Dev. Sci. 6, 413–429 10.1111/1467-7687.00302 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  125. Næss Å. (2007). Prototypical Transitivity. Typological Studies in Language, 72. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company [Google Scholar]
  126. Nelson K. E. (1977). Facilitating children’s syntax. Dev. Psychol. 13, 101–107 10.1037/0012-1649.13.2.101 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  127. Nielsen M., Tomaselli K. (2010). Overimitation in Kalahari Bushman children and the origins of human cultural cognition. Psychol. Sci. 21, 729–736 10.1177/0956797610368808 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  128. Ninio A. (2011). Syntactic Development, its Input and Output. Oxford: Oxford University Press [Google Scholar]
  129. Nowak M. A., Komarova N. L., Niyogi P. (2001). Evolution of universal grammar. Science 291, 114–118 10.1126/science.291.5501.114 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  130. Perfors A., Tenenbaum J., Wonnacott E. (2010). Variability, negative evidence, and the acquisition of verb argument constructions. J. Child Lang. 37, 607–642 10.1017/S0305000910000012 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  131. Perkins R. D. (1992). Deixis, Grammar and Culture. Amsterdam: John Benjamins [Google Scholar]
  132. Pinker S. (1989). Learnability and Cognition: The Acquisition of Argument Structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press [Google Scholar]
  133. Pinker S. (1994). How could a child use verb syntax to learn verb semantics? Lingua. 92, 377–410 10.1016/0024-3841(94)90347-6 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  134. Pinker S. (1999). Words and Rules: The Ingredients of Language. New York: Basic Books [Google Scholar]
  135. Popper K. (1957). The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul [Google Scholar]
  136. Prat-Sala M., Branigan H. P. (2000). Discourse constraints on syntactic processing in language production: a cross-linguistic study in English and Spanish. J. Mem. Lang. 42, 168–182 10.1006/jmla.1999.2668 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  137. Quine W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press [Google Scholar]
  138. Reali F., Christiansen M. H. (2007). Word chunk frequencies affect the processing of pronominal object-relative clauses. Q. J. Exp. Psychol. 60, 161–170 10.1080/17470210600971469 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  139. Roberts J. R. (1998). “Give in Amele. In The linguistics of giving,” in Typological Studies in Language 36, ed. Newman J. (Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company; ), 1–33 [Google Scholar]
  140. Rowland C. F., Pine J. M. (2000). Subject-auxiliary inversion errors and wh-question acquisition: what children do know? J. Child Lang. 27, 157–181 10.1017/S0305000999004055 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  141. Rowland C. F., Pine J. M., Lieven E. V., Theakston A. L. (2003). Determinants of the order of acquisition of Wh- questions: re-evaluating the role of caregiver speech. J. Child Lang. 30, 609–635 10.1017/S0305000902005445 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. Rudolf von Rohr C., Burkart J. M., van Schaik C. P. (2011). Evolutionary precursors of social norms in chimpanzees: a new approach. Biol. Philos. 26, 1–30 10.1007/s10539-010-9240-4 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  143. Saffran J. R. (2001). Words in a sea of sounds: the output of statistical learning. Cognition 81, 149–169 10.1016/S0010-0277(01)00132-9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  144. Saffran J. R., Aslin R. N., Newport E. L. (1996). Statistical learning by 8-month old infants. Science 274, 1926–1928 10.1126/science.274.5294.1926 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  145. Saffran J. R., Wilson D. P. (2003). From syllables to syntax: multi-level statistical learning by 12-month-old infants. Infancy 4, 273–284 10.1207/S15327078IN0402_07 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  146. Scott R. M., Fisher C. (2012). 2.5-Year-olds use cross-situational consistency to learn verbs under referential uncertainty. Cognition 122, 163–180 10.1016/j.cognition.2011.10.010 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  147. Searle J. R. (1969). Speech Acts. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press [Google Scholar]
  148. Seidenberg M. S. (1997). Language acquisition and use: learning and applying probabilistic constraints. Science 275, 1599–1603 10.1126/science.275.5306.1599 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  149. Seidenberg M. S., Tanenhaus M. K., Leiman J. M., Bienkowski M. (1982). Automatic access of the meaning of ambiguous words in context: some limitations of knowledge-based processing. Cogn. Psychol. 14, 489–537 10.1016/0010-0285(82)90017-2 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  150. Sereno J. A., Jongman A. (1997). Processing of English inflectional morphology. Mem. Cognit. 25, 425–437 10.3758/BF03201119 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  151. Shannon C. E. (1951). Prediction and entropy of printed English. Bell Syst. Tech. J. 30, 50–64 [Google Scholar]
  152. Siskind J. M. (1996). A computational study of cross-situational techniques for learning word-to-meaning mappings. Cognition 61, 39–91 10.1016/S0010-0277(96)00728-7 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  153. Smith L., Yu C. (2008). Infants rapidly learn word-referent mappings via cross-situational statistics. Cognition 106, 1558–1568 10.1016/j.cognition.2007.06.010 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  154. St Clair M. C., Monaghan P., Ramscar M. (2009). Relationships between language structure and language learning: the suffixing preference and grammatical categorization. Cogn. Sci. 33, 1317–1329 10.1111/j.1551-6709.2009.01065.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  155. Street J., Dąbrowska E. (2010). More individual differences in language attainment: how much do adult native speakers of English know about passives and quantifiers? Lingua. 120, 2080–2094 10.1016/j.lingua.2010.01.004 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  156. Swinney D. A. (1979). Lexical access during sentence comprehension: (Re)consideration of context effects. J. Verbal Learning Verbal Behav. 18, 645–660 10.1016/S0022-5371(79)90284-6 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  157. Taylor J. (2002). Cognitive Grammar. Oxford Textbooks in Linguistics. New York: Oxford University Press Inc [Google Scholar]
  158. Taylor J. (2003). Linguistic categorization, 3rd Edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press [Google Scholar]
  159. Tennie C., Call J., Tomasello M. (2009). Ratcheting up the ratchet: on the evolution of cumulative culture. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 364, 2405–2415 10.1098/rstb.2009.0052 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  160. Theakston A. L. (2004). The role of entrenchment in children’s and adults’ performance on grammaticality-judgement tasks. Cogn. Dev. 19, 15–34 10.1016/j.cogdev.2003.08.001 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  161. Thelen E., Smith L. B. (1995). A dynamic systems approach to development of cognition and action. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 7, 512–514 10.1162/jocn.1995.7.4.512 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  162. Tomasello M. (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press [Google Scholar]
  163. Tomasello M. (2003). Constructing a Language: A Usage-Based Theory of Language Acquisition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press [Google Scholar]
  164. Tomasello M. (2004). What kind of evidence could refute the UG hypothesis? Commentary on Wunderlich. Stud. Lang. 28, 642–645 10.1075/sl.28.3.13tom [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  165. Tomasello M. (2008). Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge: MIT Press [Google Scholar]
  166. Tomasello M., Rakoczy H. (2003). What Makes Human Cognition Unique? From Individual to Shared to Collective Intentionality. Mind Lang. 18, 121–147 10.1111/1468-0017.00217 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  167. Tomlin R. S. (1986). Basic Word Order: Functional Principles. London: Croom Helm [Google Scholar]
  168. Tomlin R. S. (1995). “Focal attention, voice, and word order: an experimental, cross-linguistic study,” in Word Order in Discourse, eds Downing P., Noonan M. (Amsterdam: John Benjamins; ), 517–554 [Google Scholar]
  169. Tomlin R. S. (1997). “Mapping conceptual representations into linguistic representations: the role of attention in grammar,” in Language and Conceptualization, eds Nuyts J., Pederson E. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; ), 162–189 [Google Scholar]
  170. Waterfall H. R. (2006). A Little Change is a Good Thing: Feature Theory, Language Acquisition and Variation Sets. Ph.D. thesis, Chicago: University of Chicago [Google Scholar]
  171. Waterfall H. R., Edelman S. (2009). The neglected universals: learnability constraints and discourse cues, a commentary on Evans and Levinson. Behav. Brain Sci. 32, 471–472 10.1017/S0140525X09990756 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  172. Whiten A., McGuigan N., Marshall-Pescini S., Hopper L. M. (2009). Emulation, imitation, over-imitation and the scope of culture for child and chimpanzee. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. B Biol. Sci. 364, 2417–2428 10.1098/rstb.2009.0069 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  173. Wittgenstein L. (1953/2001). Philosophical Investigations. London: Blackwell Publishing [Google Scholar]
  174. Yu C., Ballard D. H. (2007). A unified model of early word learning: integrating statistical and social cues. Neurocomputing 70, 2149–2165 10.1016/j.neucom.2006.10.009 [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  175. Zipf G. K. (1935/1965). Psycho-Biology of Languages. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press [Google Scholar]

Articles from Frontiers in Psychology are provided here courtesy of Frontiers Media SA

RESOURCES