Abstract
The ethical landscape in the field of genomics is rapidly shifting. Plummeting sequencing costs, along with ongoing advances in bioinformatics, now make it possible to generate an enormous volume of genomic data about vast numbers of people. The informational richness, complexity, and frequently uncertain meaning of these data, coupled with evolving norms surrounding the sharing of data and samples and persistent privacy concerns, have generated a range of approaches to the ethical management of genomic information. As calls increase for the expanded use of broad or even open consent, and as controversy grows about how best to handle incidental genomic findings, these approaches, informed by normative analysis and empirical data, will continue to evolve alongside the science.
Descriptive keywords: ethics, informed consent, privacy, identifiability, data sharing, return of results
Old but persistent challenges
From the inception of the Human Genome Project (HGP), the National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI) at the NIH has been committed to the support of research addressing the ethical and societal aspects of genetics and genomics. Through its Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications (ELSI) Program, NHGRI allocates 5% of its annual extramural research budget to support studies on these issues [1]. No other area of biomedical research has sustained such a high level of commitment - backed by dollars - to the examination of ethical issues; the field of genomics is, in this way, unique.
Since 1990, NHGRI’s ELSI Program has supported studies by academic investigators from many disciplines, including genetics and genomics, bioethics and philosophy, the social sciences (e.g., psychology, sociology, political science, economics, communication studies, and history), health services, public policy, and law, [2] (also see: http://www.genome.gov/17515635). These studies, and others conducted without NHGRI support, have led to the publication of thousands of papers, ranging from examinations of ethical issues in genetic and genomic research and clinical translation, to analyses of legal, public policy, and broader societal issues that the emerging technologies raise more generally [3].
Few ethical issues are capable of easy resolution, so it is unsurprising that many of the same issues that were hotly contested 20 years ago are still debated today. However, as the age of genetics (with its primary focus on single-gene disorders, traditional linkage analyses and targeted resequencing) has evolved gradually into the age of genomics (focused first on SNP chip microarray technology, and now, increasingly, on whole exome and whole genome sequencing), a few issues stand out as especially challenging. These issues - which can be classified under the broad rubric of the ethical management of genomic information - are the subject of this review.
Why the ethical management of genomic data is so challenging
Plummeting sequencing costs, along with ongoing advances in bioinformatics, now make it possible to generate an enormous volume of genomic data about vast numbers of people. Depending on the cost calculation method used, the cost of sequencing the first human genome was somewhere around $300 million (see: http://www.genome.gov/10002192); today, it is less than $8,000 (see: http://www.genome.gov/sequencingcosts), and prospects for the “$1,000 genome” and even cheaper genomes are within sight [4]. Data from genome-wide association studies (GWAS), from whole genome and whole exome scans, and from other high-throughput technologies are proliferating [5, 6]. Although the ethical challenges associated with the management of information have always been present in the field, the greater comprehensiveness and informativeness of today’s genomic data now makes these challenges even greater, as was recently recognized in a report by the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues [7].
First, unlike targeted genetic data of 20–30 years ago, or even the more comprehensive (but often not very informative) SNP data of 10 years ago, the whole exome and whole genome sequence data now being generated will eventually be able to reveal many of a person’s specific health risks - even if the data emerge from research or diagnosis related to a specific condition [8]. The growing informational richness of genomic data not only facilitates the range of questions it can be mined to help answer, but magnifies its potential for misuse.
Second, because of its comprehensiveness, genomic information – even when stripped of traditional identifiers – has, at least in some sense, the potential to re-identify the individual from whom it was obtained [8]. This characteristic, coupled with the data’s overall richness, amplifies concerns about who should be able to have – and control -access to it. Until recently, it was thought that re-identifying a sample or data from which traditional identifiers had been removed required a reference sample or data from the same person available for comparison [9], However, we now know that it is possible, in some cases, to identify the source of a sample or data by consulting genetic genealogy databases (readily available on the Internet) that link Y chromosome short tandem repeat (STR) data to particular surnames, and then combining that information with other publicly available data (e.g., information about age, state of residence, or facts contained in obituaries) [10]. Although the actual extent of this previously under-appreciated risk is still unknown, the risk will almost certainly grow in the future, as more people are sequenced and as the genetic genealogy industry grows. Indeed, the Advance Notice of Proposed Rulemaking (ANPRN), a pending set of revisions to the Common Rule (the regulations that apply to all U.S. federally funded research conducted with human subjects) explicitly recognizes the potential for re-identification inherent in all genomic data (see: http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/FR-2011-07-26/html/2011-18792.htm).
Finally, the complexity and frequently uncertain meaning of the information being generated today through whole genome analyses, compared to the more limited (and thus often more easily interpreted) information typically derived through earlier, more targeted genetic tests, enhances the possibility that the information, if shared, will be misunderstood [8]. This is creating new challenges for researchers and clinicians, who must increasingly decide which, if any, individual findings they should offer to return to those whose samples they have analyzed [11, 12]. Incidental findings (findings unrelated to the disorder that initially motivated the research or testing) are inevitable – not merely possible - in GWAS and in whole genome and whole exome scans, and as will be discussed later, these present particular challenges [8, 13–16].
Although concerns about the ethical management of research and clinical data are by no means new to the field, the transition over the past 20 years from a narrowly “genetic” orientation to today’s much more comprehensive “genomic” one has been accompanied by shifts in the way the information is being conceptualized and managed. It is thus useful to step back and review systematically the events that have steered the course of these developments and the new challenges emerging as a result.
Pre-genomic approaches to the management of data
The genetic studies and test protocols that dominated the field 15–20 years ago were generally highly targeted, and tended to view the risks to participants or patients (apart from the physical risks associated with blood drawing) as straightforwardly informational [17–19]. Thus, consent materials in use prior to the mid-2000s, if they mentioned non-physical risks at all, tended to focus on the potential for breach of privacy, with insurance and employment usually listed as the two areas of main concern [20–22]. Data security measures of the time were, by today’s standards, remarkably “low tech,” often consisting of little more than coding samples and data and storing samples and data in locked freezers and cabinets. Still, consent forms, if they addressed the issue at all, typically described the risk of a security breach as low; at the time that assessment seemed reasonably accurate, predating as it did the development of massive, web-accessible genomic databases and expanded data sharing norms.
Early consent forms rarely addressed the issue of whether individual findings from studies would be returned to participants [20, 21]. The usual default presumption was that they would not be [23], because most findings emanating from studies of the time interrogated only limited regions of the genome, so the likelihood of generating incidental findings (apart from occasional evidence of undisclosed adoption or misattributed paternity [24]) was relatively low.
Another feature of early consent forms was their characteristically narrow scientific scope [8, 20, 21]. Most described only the immediate study for which samples were being collected or the specific disease being analyzed; although the possibility of sharing with close collaborators working on the same disease was sometimes mentioned, obtaining broad consent to an unspecified range of future uses was the exception, not the norm. Often, consent documents were simply silent about plans for any future sharing, and in such cases, the absence of an explicit prohibition against sharing was generally interpreted (or, at least over time came to be interpreted) as tacit permission to share [23].
In 1994, long-percolating concerns among bioethicists about the practice of using stored, linkable samples without obtaining new consent from those from whom they had been obtained culminated in the publication of a highly influential paper that recommended against continuing this practice [25]. Following this recommendation, consent documents gradually began to be written with greater specificity about whether, with whom, and for what purposes, samples and data would be shared. In practice, however, the recommendation was often interpreted as applying only to prospectively collected samples. Thus, as was recently called to public attention in a best-selling book, archived samples collected under widely varying and sometimes questionable consent conditions – and cell lines derived from such samples - are often still being used today [26] (Box 1).
Box 1. Henrietta Lacks.
The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lacks, a best-selling book by Rebecca Skloot (Fig I) published in 2010, told the story of the woman who provided the cancer tissue sample used to create the HeLa cell line in the 1950’s. Henrietta Lacks, a poor African American woman from the tobacco fields of Virginia, had never been told that her sample had been taken for research, much less how important it eventually became to the research community. After she died, her surviving family members continued to live in poverty, lacking access even to basic health care. The family’s reaction to the discovery years later about how their mother’s cells had been and were still being used was partly one of pride, but mainly one of suspicion and anger about her never having been told what would be done with her now-immortalized sample.
Figure I.
Cover for the popular book, “The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lacks.” Jacket Cover copyright © 2011 by Crown Publishers, an imprint of the Crown Publishing Group, a division of Random House, Inc., from THE IMMORTAL LIFE OF HENRIETTA LACKS by Rebecca Skloot. Used by permission of Crown Publishers, a division of Random House, Inc.
The movement toward broader sharing and expanding genomic applications
The field of genomics has long been distinguished by steadfast adherence to the principle of broad data release. This commitment, first enshrined in the 1996 “Bermuda Principles” and subsequently reaffirmed, is aimed at maximizing the pace of research and ultimately, its benefit to society [27].
As targeted genetic research began to give way to research with a more genomic focus, the expectations regarding broad data sharing - and rules to enforce them - were gradually extended to apply not only to the data produced in large, community resource projects, but to genomic data more generally. The introduction of SNP chips and the development of improved statistical methods in the early 2000s, which suddenly made studies of common, complex conditions more tractable, contributed to this trend [28]. GWAS of common disease accelerated in the 2000s and quickly overshadowed the previous focus on single gene disorders. To be adequately powered, however, such studies typically required larger sample sizes (or datasets) than any single researcher could amass. This circumstance, along with improvements in informatics technology that made it cheaper and easier to share large amounts of data, provided further momentum for sharing, and set the stage for the 2008 adoption of the NIH GWAS Data Access Policy. That policy requires the deposition of summary-level information and aggregate genotype data in the open access portion of the NIH Database of Genotypes and Phenotypes (dbGaP), and the deposition of individual-level data (genotypes and phenotypes) in the controlled access portion of the database (see: http://grants.nih.gov/grants/guide/notice-files/NOT-OD-07-088.html). Under the policy, controlled access data are made available to any qualified researcher following review and approval by an NIH Data Access Committee (DAC) [29].
Two other developments occurring in the late 2000s helped further “pave the way” for expanded data sharing by (at least temporarily) helping to quell lingering concerns of some institutional review board (IRB) members about the associated risks. One development was the enactment of the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act (GINA) (see: http://www.eeoc.gov/laws/statutes/gina.cfm), which was initially greeted, at least by some, with optimism that it would “put to rest” public worries about possible misuses of genomic information, thus making protocols that relied on the use of shared data or incorporated plans for broad data sharing more ethically acceptable [30]. The second was the issuance by the Office of Human Research Protections (OHRP) of guidance reaffirming a previously-stated position that research using only de-identified materials falls outside the definition of “human subjects research” and thus outside the protections outlined in the Common Rule (see http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/policy/cdebiol.html). This guidance provided some (again, at least temporary) reassurance to IRBs that protocols involving the use of de-identified, archived samples or data, without re-consent, rested on firm ethical (or, at least regulatory) footing. It also bolstered the confidence of institutional officials charged with certifying the appropriateness of the data generated by investigators at their institutions for deposition into dbGaP.
The trend toward broader sharing of data has been accompanied by a trend toward broader sharing of samples, often through large biorepositories [31]. The new sequencing technologies make it possible to conduct genomic studies with much smaller quantities of material, increasing researchers’ willingness to share more of the valuable sample resources they have acquired.
Yet, today, a sense of discomfort remains among many IRB members, many bioethicists, and increasingly, many researchers, about the proliferation of genomic information across society and its concomitant potential for misuse. Reinforcing this unease has been the virtual explosion of genomic data occurring over the past two decades - in settings often far removed from research laboratories and clinics. DNA-based information is now used routinely in the criminal justice system, to establish paternity and other family relationships, to identify disaster victims in both military and civilian settings, to identify matches for bone marrow transplantation, and for a host of other applications [32–34]. New private sector activities based on genomic information have also arisen. 23andMe and other companies offering “direct-to-consumer” genetic tests have come into being [35–37], and growing public fascination with genealogy has given rise to a new industry in DNA ancestry testing [38, 39]. The availability and use of genomic information across society are, indeed, becoming ubiquitous.
Renewed concerns about identifiability and the trend toward broad consent
Alongside these developments, the past several years have seen a flurry of papers suggesting the existence of previously under-appreciated ways that various types of genomic data might potentially be re-identified [10, 40–42]. Correspondingly, a growing sense has emerged that participants in genomics research should be informed more explicitly that their information may be shared - even if their consent to each and every new use is not necessarily legally required. This has ushered in a trend toward the more frequent use of broad informed consent, and over the past five years, consent forms have increasingly been drafted to describe explicitly the possible downstream deposition of genomic (and sometimes clinical) information into public databases, where it can be shared with multiple researchers for use in many types of studies [43, 44]. Consent forms also increasingly seek express authorization for the distribution of samples to secondary researchers, as more researchers come to recognize the benefits of collaboration and as biobanks and biorepositories expand [45, 46].
Research participants vary in their receptivity to broad consent [47–49]. Although some reportedly prefer this approach [50], others - especially from populations that have historically suffered research abuses – have been less amenable [51, 52]. Indeed, although by no means universal, a sense of unease persists among many in the public about the inability to control future uses of their (or their family members’) genomic samples and data; this was demonstrated in two recent lawsuits challenging the research use of stored blood spots from state newborn screening programs without parental consent (Box 2) [53–56] Dashing some early hopes that GINA would significantly mitigate public concerns about the potential misuses of genomic information, evidence suggests that most people, if they are aware of GINA at all, view it as of likely limited effectiveness [57].)
Box 2. The newborn screening litigation.
In 2009, several parents in Texas filed a lawsuit when they became aware that blood spots collected from their newborn children through Texas’ newborn screening program were being used for research without parental consent or generally without the awareness of the public. In settlement of the lawsuit, the state agreed to destroy some 5 million stored newborn screening blood spots. Newborn blood spots being retained in Minnesota were ordered destroyed after that state’s Supreme Court, in response to a lawsuit filed by disgruntled parents. The court held that the retention of the blood spots violated the state’s Genetic Privacy Act, a law that requires informed, written consent for the collection, storage, use and dissemination of any genetic information. The newborn screening programs in Texas and Minnesota were not atypical, in that few states’ programs mandate parental consent for newborn screening or inform parents that the samples will be retained after being tested.
Figure I.
Messaging for public awareness campaign on state newborn screening program. Photo copyright © 2010 by Zazzle, Inc. Used by permission of Zazzle, Inc. and Citizens’ Council for Health Freedom.
It is important not to overstate the realistic current risk that someone who has provided a genomic sample or data for study will be identified by a random member of the public and then suffer tangible harm. Most genomic data today (especially those linked to clinical information) are shared through controlled access databases such as dbGaP, which have established procedures to restrict access to qualified investigators. Nevertheless, the recent study showing that some genomic data (specifically, Y chromosome STR markers) can be linked to surnames and, in conjunction with other public information, used to identify certain individuals [10], is a reminder that no method of de-identification is perfect [58]. In the (currently, relatively few) studies that have involved the deposition of sequence data that includes data on the Y chromosome in open access databases, the identification risks (at least to people in certain parts of the world – especially those with uncommon surnames or included in published pedigrees that have other data, such as age information, attached) may be greater than earlier appreciated.
Proposals for “open consent,” re-thinking current consent paradigms, and the “Citizen Science” movement
With growing recognition of the potential to re-identify individuals through their genomic data, some have suggested that continuing even to try to take measures to reduce this potential are misguided [59]. The Personal Genome Project (PGP) is premised on this view [60]. That project requires participants to forego any expectation of privacy in their genomic and personal health data; these data are shared openly over the Internet, for anyone to see. Before being accepted for participation in the PGP, volunteers must pass an “enrollment exam” demonstrating their understanding of genetics and of the risks entailed by participation [60].
PGP researchers themselves acknowledge that the participants in their project are highly self-selected and that the more pragmatic solution for the public at large will likely entail a two-fold approach: maximizing efforts to prevent re-identification while simultaneously informing prospective participants of the inherent limitations of those efforts more candidly than has often been done in the past [61]. This approach seems aligned with what most people actually expect; recent survey data show that most in the public are not willing to allow unfettered access to their genomic and phenotypic data, yet are realistic about the limits to which their identities can be protected and willing to accept something short of an absolute guarantee [62].
As was starkly illustrated in a recent lawsuit between university researchers and an American Indian tribe [63, 64] (Box 3), the key here may be improved transparency. Moving into the future, this may require placing less emphasis on technical “fixes” to informational risks (e.g., developing better firewalls or de-identification algorithms), or on checking to see whether the precise wording used in a 10-year old consent form is technically “adequate” to permit a particular newly-contemplated use of samples or data, or the deposition of data in public databases. Researchers may instead need to consider, for example, whether a proposed change in a project’s data release plan, or the discovery after a project’s inception of previously under-appreciated risks, should prompt them to communicate the proposed change or new risks and reiterate (where appropriate and feasible) the possibility of withdrawal - even if re-consent is not technically required. Researchers may also need to reconsider whether asking people for permission to have their genomic samples or data used in an unspecified, potentially unbounded, range of future studies, by as-yet unknown investigators in far-flung places, can lead to consent that is truly “informed” [65–68].
Box 3. The Havasupai case.
In 2010, a large settlement was reached between Arizona State University and the Havasupai Indian tribe, in a lawsuit involving a genetic study of diabetes. Samples taken from tribal members were used to study not only diabetes, but other topics (schizophrenia and population relatedness) that the tribe found objectionable. Although the language in the consent form for the study was quite broad, the focus of discussions with the tribe had been on diabetes. Had these other topics been clearly brought out during discussions about the research, the tribe’s willingness to participate would have diminished. Apart from the lessons this case provides about the importance of transparency, it illustrates the personal, cultural, and often spiritual significance that can be attached to blood or other biological materials. It also demonstrates the importance of making sure that a study is collectively, not just individually, acceptable when conducting research with American Indian tribes (which are sovereign nations) and with some other groups,
Figure I.
Havasupai Indian woman. Photo by Grand Canyon NPS / CC-BY-2.0. From Wikimedia Commons.
Some have suggested that in the new era of genomics, we may simply be “asking too much” of informed consent [69]. In recognition of this, the efficacy of tiered consent [49, 70], “opt-out mechanisms” [71], and innovative new approaches to community engagement [72] and research governance [73, 74] are now being explored with renewed vigor; however, much more work in this area remains to be done [75, 76].
A “health information altruist” model has recently been proposed, in which research participants agree to make samples or data available for a wide (potentially unlimited) range of studies, but in which they are actively involved as research “partners” and thereby retain in various respects a measure of control [77]. The goal of this model, and of other emerging “Citizen Science” models, is to speed the pace of discovery while more affirmatively showing respect for participants’ contributions to the research [78–81]. Reciprocity is an important feature of many such approaches, which often contemplate providing participants with extensive ongoing feedback about individual research findings.
Although some have lauded approaches of this type as the “wave of the future” [78, 79, 81], their generalizability to a range of populations and to the full panoply of possible research designs remains to be determined [82]. For example, a “health information altruist” model may be very well suited to certain highly educated people in particular cultures who are highly trusting of the biomedical research establishment and have little reason to worry about how the information from the study of their samples will be used. It may be completely unsuited to some others, who have little understanding of science or appreciation for genomic research, or who have historically experienced research abuses. Such a model may be well suited to certain epidemiologic studies, but unsuited to some small family studies that involve the potential for the discovery of information (such as information about certain neurological or psychiatric disorders, or information about family relatedness) that could potentially be stigmatizing – either to themselves or to others to whom they are closely related. The model may also be unworkable for some community resource projects.
Uncharted waters: Approaching the management of genomic incidental findings
One of the most contentious ethical issues in genomics research today relates to the management of the incidental findings that whole genome and whole exome studies inevitably uncover. Although genomics has already started to be introduced into the clinical care arena [83], most genomic data are still generated in research settings, where only a very limited ethical duty to offer individual results to participants (as distinct from aggregate findings) has traditionally been recognized [84]. Increasingly, however, researchers and bioethicists are re-thinking this, especially in cases where the research uncovers information that may be clinically actionable or have significant personal utility [85, 86]. Growing evidence suggests that many research participants desire, and in fact expect, to receive individual research results, regardless of whether they can do anything with the information [87–90], and some have suggested that withholding information that may have clinical (or even merely personal) utility is unduly paternalistic [79].
Others, however, have insisted that bombarding people with more information than can realistically be digested, especially when its significance is uncertain, is counterproductive [11, 91]. A number of practical issues have also been raised, including the inability of most clinicians to understand information of this type well enough to help patients interpret it, and the scarcity of genetic counseling resources [92–96].
The fact that much genomic research today is done using samples and data obtained from biorepositories and biobanks complicates the situation [13, 14, 46]. For example, what, if any, duties are owed by secondary or tertiary researchers, who have likely had no direct contact with the person who provided the samples or data, and who more often than not will be working with de-identified material [97, 98]? Must they notify the researcher (or clinician) who originally collected the sample so the participant or patient can be re-contacted - and if so, how many years into the future does this duty extend? Should the duty to re-contact extend to cases in which people were told during the recruitment process that they would never be re-contacted [99, 100]? What if they had never even been told that their sample or data might be made available someday for other researchers to study, much less of the possibility that important health-related information might eventually be found? Research to examine these and related questions [7], much of it supported by NHGRI’s ELSI Program, is currently underway.
Concluding remarks
Bioethicists consulted by genomics researchers, clinicians, IRBs, and others are often asked to provide “model” consent language or other definitive guidance to help navigate safely through a range of challenging questions related to the responsible management of information in the new genomic era. Surely by now, it is thought, consensus must have been reached on at least the major issues. However, such calls for simple, straightforward solutions miss the point that while many of the ethical quandaries represent new variations on old themes, they continue to resist easy resolution. While much normative and empirical research is underway to address these complex questions, new issues will inevitably arise as we advance still further into the genomic age, opening up yet other areas of debate and avenues for exploration.
Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications (ELSI) in the genomic era
Frameworks and policies to meet ELSI challenges
Privacy concerns and the limits to consent
Transparency and engaging patients in genomic research
Acknowledgments
The authors thank Mark Guyer for his thoughtful comments on the manuscript.
Footnotes
Publisher's Disclaimer: This is a PDF file of an unedited manuscript that has been accepted for publication. As a service to our customers we are providing this early version of the manuscript. The manuscript will undergo copyediting, typesetting, and review of the resulting proof before it is published in its final citable form. Please note that during the production process errors may be discovered which could affect the content, and all legal disclaimers that apply to the journal pertain.
Contributor Information
Jean E. McEwen, Email: jm522n@nih.gov, Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications Program, Division of Genomics and Society, National Human Genome Research Institute, National Institutes of Health, 5535 Fishers Lane, Suite 4076, Bethesda, MD 20892-9305.
Joy T. Boyer, Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications Program, Division of Genomics and Society, National Human Genome Research Institute, National Institutes of Health, 5535 Fishers Lane, Suite 4076, Bethesda, MD 20892-9305.
Kathie Y. Sun, Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications Program, Division of Genomics and Society, National Human Genome Research Institute, National Institutes of Health, 5535 Fishers Lane, Suite 4076, Bethesda, MD 20892-9305.
References
- 1.McEwen JE, et al. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences (eLS) John Wiley & Sons, Ltd; 2009. ELSI Research Programme of the NHGRI. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Walker RL, Morrissey C. Charting ELSI’s future course: lessons from the recent past. Genet Med. 2012;14:259–267. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.60. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Morrissey C, Walker RL. Funding and Forums for ELSI Research: Who (or What) is Setting the Agenda? AJOB Prim Res. 2012;3:51–60. doi: 10.1080/21507716.2012.678550. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Sboner A, et al. The real cost of sequencing: higher than you think! Genome Biol. 2011;12:125. doi: 10.1186/gb-2011-12-8-125. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Kilpinen H, Barrett JC. How next-generation sequencing is transforming complex disease genetics. Trends Genet. 2012 doi: 10.1016/j.tig.2012.10.001. In press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Mardis ER. A decade’s perspective on DNA sequencing technology. Nature. 2011;470:198–203. doi: 10.1038/nature09796. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues. 2012. Privacy and Progress in Whole Genome Sequencing. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Tabor HK, et al. Genomics really gets personal: how exome and whole genome sequencing challenge the ethical framework of human genetics research. Am J Med Genet A. 2011;155A:2916–2924. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34357. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.McGuire AL, Gibbs RA. No Longer De-Identified. Science. 2006;312:370–371. doi: 10.1126/science.1125339. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Gymrek M, et al. Identifying Personal Genomes by Surname Inference. Science. 2013;339:321–324. doi: 10.1126/science.1229566. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Evans JP, Rothschild BB. Return of results: not that complicated? Genet Med. 2012;14:358–360. doi: 10.1038/gim.2012.8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Berg JS, et al. Deploying whole genome sequencing in clinical practice and public health: meeting the challenge one bin at a time. Genet Med. 2011;13:499–504. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e318220aaba. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Wolf SM, et al. Managing incidental findings and research results in genomic research involving biobanks and archived data sets. Genet Med. 2012;14:361–384. doi: 10.1038/gim.2012.23. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Wolf SM. The Role of Law in the Debate over Return of Research Results and Incidental Findings: The Challenge of Developing Law for Translational Science. Minn J L Sci & Tech. 2012;13:435–449. doi: 10.2139/ssrn.2117289. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Simon C, et al. Individual genetic and genomic research results and the tradition of informed consent: exploring US review board guidance. J Med Ethics. 2012;38:417–422. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100273. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Simon CM, et al. Informed consent and genomic incidental findings: IRB chair perspectives. J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics. 2011;6:53–67. doi: 10.1525/jer.2011.6.4.53. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Roche PA, Annas GJ. Protecting genetic privacy. Nat Rev Genet. 2001;2:392–396. doi: 10.1038/35072029. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Fuller BP, et al. Privacy in genetics research. Science. 1999;285:1359–1361. doi: 10.1126/science.285.5432.1359. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Annas GJ. Privacy rules for DNA databanks. Protecting coded ‘future diaries’. JAMA. 1993;270:2346–2350. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Weir RF, Horton JR. DNA banking and informed consent -- part 1. IRB. 1995;17:1–4. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Weir RF, Horton JR. DNA banking and informed consent -- part 2. IRB. 1995;17:1–8. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Rothstein MA. Genetic privacy and confidentiality: why they are so hard to protect. J Law Med Ethics. 1998;26:198–204. 178. doi: 10.1111/j.1748-720x.1998.tb01420.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Hull SC, et al. Genetic research involving human biological materials: a need to tailor current consent forms. IRB. 2004;26:1–7. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Lucassen A, Parker M. Revealing false paternity: some ethical considerations. Lancet. 2001;357:1033–1035. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(00)04240-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Clayton EW, et al. Informed consent for genetic research on stored tissue samples. JAMA. 1995;274:1786–1792. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Skloot R. The Immortal Life of Henrietta Lacks. Crown Publishers; 2010. [Google Scholar]
- 27.Guyer M. Statement on the rapid release of genomic DNA sequence. Genome Res. 1998;8:413. doi: 10.1101/gr.8.5.413. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.LaFramboise T. Single nucleotide polymorphism arrays: a decade of biological, computational and technological advances. Nucleic Acids Res. 2009;37:4181–4193. doi: 10.1093/nar/gkp552. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Mailman MD, et al. The NCBI dbGaP database of genotypes and phenotypes. Nat Genet. 2007;39:1181–1186. doi: 10.1038/ng1007-1181. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.McGuire AL, Majumder MA. Two cheers for GINA? Genome Med. 2009;1:6. doi: 10.1186/gm6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.McCarty CA, et al. The eMERGE Network: a consortium of biorepositories linked to electronic medical records data for conducting genomic studies. BMC Med Genomics. 2011;4:13. doi: 10.1186/1755-8794-4-13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Kimmelman J. Risking ethical insolvency: a survey of trends in criminal DNA databanking. J Law Med Ethics. 2000;28:209–221. doi: 10.1111/j.1748-720x.2000.tb00661.x. discussion 222–203. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Noble AA. DNA fingerprinting and civil liberties. J Law Med Ethics. 2006;34:149–152. doi: 10.1111/j.1748-720X.2006.00023.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.McDonald J, Lehman DC. Forensic DNA analysis. Clin Lab Sci. 2012;25:109–113. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Caulfield T, McGuire AL. Direct-to-consumer genetic testing: perceptions, problems, and policy responses. Annu Rev Med. 2012;63:23–33. doi: 10.1146/annurev-med-062110-123753. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Hogarth S, et al. The current landscape for direct-to-consumer genetic testing: legal, ethical, and policy issues. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet. 2008;9:161–182. doi: 10.1146/annurev.genom.9.081307.164319. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Lee SS, Crawley L. Research 2.0: social networking and direct-to-consumer (DTC) genomics. Am J Bioeth. 2009;9:35–44. doi: 10.1080/15265160902874452. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Wagner JK. Interpreting the implications of DNA ancestry tests. Perspect Biol Med. 2010;53:231–248. doi: 10.1353/pbm.0.0158. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Royal CD, et al. Inferring genetic ancestry: opportunities, challenges, and implications. Am J Hum Genet. 2010;86:661–673. doi: 10.1016/j.ajhg.2010.03.011. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Homer N, et al. Resolving individuals contributing trace amounts of DNA to highly complex mixtures using high-density SNP genotyping microarrays. PLoS Genet. 2008;4:e1000167. doi: 10.1371/journal.pgen.1000167. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Schadt EE, et al. Bayesian method to predict individual SNP genotypes from gene expression data. Nat Genet. 2012;44:603–608. doi: 10.1038/ng.2248. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Im HK, et al. On sharing quantitative trait GWAS results in an era of multiple-omics data and the limits of genomic privacy. Am J Hum Genet. 2012;90:591–598. doi: 10.1016/j.ajhg.2012.02.008. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.McGuire AL, et al. To share or not to share: a randomized trial of consent for data sharing in genome research. Genet Med. 2011;13:948–955. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3182227589. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.McGuire AL, et al. Ethical and practical challenges of sharing data from genome-wide association studies: the eMERGE Consortium experience. Genome Res. 2011;21:1001–1007. doi: 10.1101/gr.120329.111. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Haga SB, Beskow LM. Ethical, legal, and social implications of biobanks for genetics research. Adv Genet. 2008;60:505–544. doi: 10.1016/S0065-2660(07)00418-X. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Fullerton SM, et al. Meeting the governance challenges of next-generation biorepository research. Sci Transl Med. 2010;2:15cm13. doi: 10.1126/scitranslmed.3000361. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Trinidad SB, et al. Genomic research and wide data sharing: views of prospective participants. Genet Med. 2010;12:486–495. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e3181e38f9e. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Lemke AA, et al. Public and biobank participant attitudes toward genetic research participation and data sharing. Public Health Genomics. 2010;13:368–377. doi: 10.1159/000276767. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Oliver JM, et al. Balancing the risks and benefits of genomic data sharing: genome research participants’ perspectives. Public Health Genomics. 2012;15:106–114. doi: 10.1159/000334718. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Simon CM, et al. Active choice but not too active: public perspectives on biobank consent models. Genet Med. 2011;13:821–831. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e31821d2f88. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Haga SB, O’Daniel J. Public perspectives regarding data-sharing practices in genomics research. Public Health Genomics. 2011;14:319–324. doi: 10.1159/000324705. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Goldenberg AJ, et al. Patient perspectives on group benefits and harms in genetic research. Public Health Genomics. 2011;14:135–142. doi: 10.1159/000317497. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.(2009) Beleno v. Texas Dept of Health Services. W.D. Tex. 2. Plaintiffs’ Complaint No. SA-09-CA-188-FB. (http://www.genomicslawreport.com/wp-content/uploads/2010/01/Beleno-complaint.pdf)
- 54.Lowery A. Newborn Screening Settlement, News Release. Texas Dept of State Health Services, Statement, December 22, 2009. 2009 ( http://www.dshs.state.tx.us/news/releases/20091222.shtm)
- 55.Bearder v. Minnesota. Minnesota Supreme Court. A10–0101. 2011 Nov 16; 2011. ( http://www.lawlibrary.state.mn.us/archive/supct/1111/OPA100101-1116.pdf)
- 56.Botkin JR, et al. Retention and research use of residual newborn screening bloodspots. Pediatrics. 2013;131:120–127. doi: 10.1542/peds.2012-0852. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Klitzman R. Views of discrimination among individuals confronting genetic disease. J Genet Couns. 2010;19:68–83. doi: 10.1007/s10897-009-9262-8. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Greely HT. The uneasy ethical and legal underpinnings of large-scale genomic biobanks. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet. 2007;8:343–364. doi: 10.1146/annurev.genom.7.080505.115721. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Angrist M. Eyes wide open: the personal genome project, citizen science and veracity in informed consent. Per Med. 2009;6:691–699. doi: 10.2217/pme.09.48. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Ball MP, et al. A public resource facilitating clinical use of genomes. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. 2012;109:11920–11927. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1201904109. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Lunshof JE, et al. From genetic privacy to open consent. Nat Rev Genet. 2008;9:406–411. doi: 10.1038/nrg2360. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Kaufman DJ, et al. Public opinion about the importance of privacy in biobank research. Am J Hum Genet. 2009;85:643–654. doi: 10.1016/j.ajhg.2009.10.002. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.Mello MM, Wolf LE. The Havasupai Indian tribe case--lessons for research involving stored biologic samples. N Engl J Med. 2010;363:204–207. doi: 10.1056/NEJMp1005203. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 64.After Havasupai litigation, Native Americans wary of genetic research. American Journal of Medical Genetics Part A. 2010;152A doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.33592. fm ix-fm ix. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Hayden EC. Informed consent: a broken contract. Nature. 2012;486:312–314. doi: 10.1038/486312a. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 66.Kronenthal C, et al. Broadening research consent in the era of genome-informed medicine. Genet Med. 2012;14:432–436. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.76. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67.Walker L, et al. dbGaP data access requests: a call for greater transparency. Sci Transl Med. 2011;3:113cm134. doi: 10.1126/scitranslmed.3002788. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.Trinidad SB, et al. Research ethics. Research practice and participant preferences: the growing gulf. Science. 2011;331:287–288. doi: 10.1126/science.1199000. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 69.Henderson GE. Is informed consent broken? Am J Med Sci. 2011;342:267–272. doi: 10.1097/MAJ.0b013e31822a6c47. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 70.Trinidad SB, et al. Informed Consent in Genome-Scale Research: What Do Prospective Participants Think? AJOB Prim Res. 2012;3:3–11. doi: 10.1080/21507716.2012.662575. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71.Brothers KB, et al. Two large-scale surveys on community attitudes toward an opt-out biobank. Am J Med Genet A. 2011;155A:2982–2990. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34304. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72.O’Daniel JM, et al. Enhancing geneticists’ perspectives of the public through community engagement. Genet Med. 2012;14:243–249. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.29. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 73.O’Doherty KC, et al. From consent to institutions: designing adaptive governance for genomic biobanks. Soc Sci Med. 2011;73:367–374. doi: 10.1016/j.socscimed.2011.05.046. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 74.Kaye J. The tension between data sharing and the protection of privacy in genomics research. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet. 2012;13:415–431. doi: 10.1146/annurev-genom-082410-101454. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 75.Rotimi CN, Marshall PA. Tailoring the process of informed consent in genetic and genomic research. Genome Med. 2010;2:20. doi: 10.1186/gm141. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 76.McGuire AL, Beskow LM. Informed consent in genomics and genetic research. Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet. 2010;11:361–381. doi: 10.1146/annurev-genom-082509-141711. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 77.Kohane IS, Altman RB. Health-information altruists--a potentially critical resource. N Engl J Med. 2005;353:2074–2077. doi: 10.1056/NEJMsb051220. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 78.Kaye J, et al. From patients to partners: participant-centric initiatives in biomedical research. Nat Rev Genet. 2012;13:371–376. doi: 10.1038/nrg3218. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 79.Terry SF. The Tension Between Policy and Practice in Returning Research Results and Incidental Findings in Genomic Biobank Research. Minn J L Sci & Tech. 2012;13:691–736. [Google Scholar]
- 80.Schadt EE. The changing privacy landscape in the era of big data. Mol Syst Biol. 2012;8:612. doi: 10.1038/msb.2012.47. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 81.Conley JM, et al. Enabling responsible public genomics. Health Matrix Clevel. 2010;20:325–385. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 82.Rodriguez L, et al. The Complexities of Genomic Identifiability. Science. 2013;339:275–276. doi: 10.1126/science.1234593. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 83.Desai AN, Jere A. Next-generation sequencing: ready for the clinics? Clin Genet. 2012;81:503–510. doi: 10.1111/j.1399-0004.2012.01865.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 84.Beskow LM, Burke W. Offering individual genetic research results: context matters. Sci Transl Med. 2010;2:38cm20. doi: 10.1126/scitranslmed.3000952. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 85.Bredenoord AL, et al. Disclosure of individual genetic data to research participants: the debate reconsidered. Trends Genet. 2011;27:41–47. doi: 10.1016/j.tig.2010.11.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 86.Meyer MN. The kindness of strangers: the donative contract between subjects and researchers and the non-obligation to return individual results of genetic research. Am J Bioeth. 2008;8:44–46. doi: 10.1080/15265160802485045. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 87.Bollinger JM, et al. Public preferences regarding the return of individual genetic research results: findings from a qualitative focus group study. Genet Med. 2012;14:451–457. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.66. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 88.Murphy J, et al. Public expectations for return of results from large-cohort genetic research. Am J Bioeth. 2008;8:36–43. doi: 10.1080/15265160802513093. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 89.Bovenberg J, et al. Always expect the unexpected: Legal and social aspects of reporting biobank research results to individual research participants. Centre for Society and Genomics; 2009. p. 92. [Google Scholar]
- 90.Kaufman D, et al. Subjects matter: a survey of public opinions about a large genetic cohort study. Genet Med. 2008;10:831–839. doi: 10.1097/GIM.0b013e31818bb3ab. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 91.Kohane IS, et al. Taxonomizing, sizing, and overcoming the incidentalome. Genet Med. 2012;14:399–404. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.68. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 92.Ossorio P. Taking aims seriously: repository research and limits on the duty to return individual research findings. Genet Med. 2012;14:461–466. doi: 10.1038/gim.2012.5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 93.Bledsoe MJ, et al. Practical implementation issues and challenges for biobanks in the return of individual research results. Genet Med. 2012;14:478–483. doi: 10.1038/gim.2011.67. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 94.Kaufman DJ, et al. Risky business: risk perception and the use of medical services among customers of DTC personal genetic testing. J Genet Couns. 2012;21:413–422. doi: 10.1007/s10897-012-9483-0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 95.McGuire AL, Burke W. Health system implications of direct-to-consumer personal genome testing. Public Health Genomics. 2011;14:53–58. doi: 10.1159/000321962. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 96.Giovanni MA, et al. Health-care referrals from direct-to-consumer genetic testing. Genet Test Mol Biomarkers. 2010;14:817–819. doi: 10.1089/gtmb.2010.0051. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 97.Richardson HS, Cho MK. Secondary researchers’ duties to return incidental findings and individual research results: a partial-entrustment account. Genet Med. 2012;14:467–472. doi: 10.1038/gim.2012.12. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 98.McGeveran W, et al. Deidentification and Reidentification in Returning Individual Findings from Biobank and Secondary Research: Regulatory Challenges and Models for Management. Minn J L Sci & Tech. 2012;13:485–540. [Google Scholar]
- 99.Maschke KJ. Returning Genetic Research Results: Considerations for Existing No-Return and Future Biobanks. Minn J L Sci & Tech. 2012;13:559–574. [Google Scholar]
- 100.Fatehi L, Hall RF. Enforcing the Rights of Human Sources to Informed Consent and Disclosures of Incidental Findings from Biobanks and Researchers: State Mechanisms in Light of Broad Regulatory Failure. Minn J L Sci & Tech. 2012;13:575–654. [Google Scholar]