Abstract
We test whether heavy or binge drinkers are overly optimistic about probabilities of adverse consequences from these activities or are relatively accurate about these probabilities. Using data from a survey in eight cities, we evaluate the relationship between subjective beliefs and drinking. We assess accuracy of beliefs about several outcomes of heavy/binge drinking: reduced longevity, liver disease onset, link between alcohol consumption and Driving While Intoxicated (DWI), probability of an accident after drinking, accuracy of beliefs about encountering intoxicated drivers on the road, and legal consequences of DWI—ranging from being stopped to receiving fines and jail terms. Overall, there is no empirical support for the optimism bias hypothesis. We do find that persons consuming a lot of alcohol tend to be more overconfident about their driving abilities and ability to handle alcohol. However, such overconfidence does not translate into over-optimism about consequences of high levels of alcohol consumption.
Keywords: Drinking and driving, subjective beliefs, arrest, optimism bias
There is much interest in understanding the role of subjective beliefs in explaining individual behavior. Such research is considered to be an important stepping stone towards using data on subjective beliefs in empirical analysis of economic decisions rather than relying on assumptions about individual expectations, e.g., Manski (2004). Yet there is a lot that is not understood about the nature and formation of subjective beliefs.
In the absence of data on subjective beliefs, economists have made a variety of assumptions about individual expectations in empirical research. Rust and Phelan (1997), in estimating their model, assume “rational expectations,” i.e., individuals’ subjective probability measures coincide on average with objectively estimable population probability measures. In particular, subjective beliefs of each individual i at time t are replaced by an objective probability measure that is estimated as a function of observable individual characteristics, and behaviors using population level data. Subjective beliefs have been analyzed in a number of contexts such as: earnings expectations/job search (Lancaster and Chesher 1983); Social Security expectations and retirement savings (Dominitz et al. 2002); consumption expectations/consumption in retirement (Hurd and Rohwedder 2003); mortality expectations; consumption and bequests (Gan et al. 2004); job loss expectations and consumption (Stephens 2004); retirement and mortality expectations; and savings and retirement (Van der Klaauw and Wolpin 2005). Snowberg and Wolfers (2010) studied the phenomenon of gamblers over-betting for long shots in horse races and under-betting on favorites.
Some scholars have maintained that rather than having rational expectations, people have biased subjective beliefs and that such biased beliefs, more specifically underestimating the adverse consequences of their choices, lead people to engage in behaviors that are harmful to themselves and others (Weinstein 1980; Hansen et al. 1991; Dejoy 1992; Weinstein and Klein 1995).1 This phenomenon is referred to as “optimism bias.”2 A case in point may be heavy and binge drinking, which can lead to chronic diseases, fights, other forms of disruptive behavior (e.g., Gmel et al. (2012)), and driving while intoxicated (DWI). Heavy and binge drinking substantially raises the probability of DWI (Sloan et al. 1995).
This study tests whether persons who engage in heavy or binge drinking are overly optimistic about the probabilities of adverse consequences from these activities. We use data from a survey conducted for this study in eight geographically dispersed U.S. cities to evaluate the relationship between subjective beliefs and drinking behaviors. We gauge accuracy of beliefs in two ways. The first is to compare accuracy of subjective beliefs with objective probabilities and other values obtained from various secondary sources. The second is to determine whether subjective beliefs elicited at one interview are systematically related to realizations of the same outcomes reported by survey respondents a year later. Although the second approach is conceptually preferable because it matches subjective and objective probabilities for the same individuals and thus reflects peculiarities of our sample, objective probabilities for several study outcomes we would have liked to analyze are too low to permit a within sample before (subjective belief) versus after (realized outcome) comparison.3 We assess accuracy of beliefs about a wide range of possible outcomes of heavy and binge drinking (e.g., reduced longevity or onset of liver disease). We also assess accuracy of beliefs about the link between alcohol use and passing the legal threshold for intoxication, the probability of getting into an accident conditional on alcohol consumption, the share of drivers on the road who have had too much to drink, and the legal consequences for DWI. The legal consequences of DWI range from the probability of being stopped to fines and jail terms conditional on a conviction. For within sample comparisons, the subjective probabilities of these outcomes occurring during the following year are: drinking and driving at all; being arrested for DWI; being cited for driving 15 miles per hour or more above the speed limit; and being in a DWI related motor vehicle accident.
Our empirical analysis leads to these conclusions. First, the comparisons of subjective beliefs with objective data reveal that persons are more often pessimistic than optimistic about the adverse outcomes we studied. Binge and heavy binge drinkers, if anything, tend to be more pessimistic about the adverse outcomes from excessive drinking than “other drinkers,” persons who consume alcohol but not in excess according to our study’s criteria for “heavy” or “binge” drinking. Second, three of the four within sample comparisons show that more individuals overestimate the probability of outcomes a year later than underestimate them. But third, we find evidence that binge and heavy binge drinkers think that their driving ability and ability to tolerate alcohol is better than average. This Lake Wobegon effect often underlies claims of optimism bias.4 Yet such overconfidence does not translate systematically to more optimistic subjective beliefs of binge and heavy drinkers. We conclude that the evidence overall implies that optimism bias does not explain why some adults consume large amounts of alcohol.
Section 1 describes our data. In Section 2, we compare accuracy of subjective beliefs from our survey with corresponding objective values obtained from secondary sources. In Section 3, we compare accuracy of subjective beliefs with data on realized outcomes reported by the same survey respondents a year later. Section 4 presents results on the Lake Wobegon effect and on focal responses to questions eliciting subjective beliefs. Section 5 describes our results in the context of previous research, reconciles our findings on accuracy of subjective beliefs with those on the Lake Wobegon effect, and discusses implications of our findings.
1. Data
Data on subjective beliefs come from a survey conducted for purposes of this research while data on corresponding objective probabilities come from various secondary sources described below in sections in which we present specifications and results for specific outcomes.
1.1. Survey of Alcohol and Driving (SAD)
Battelle Memorial Institute conducted a three-wave survey of drinkers and drivers in eight cities in four states during 2009-2012: Raleigh, North Carolina (NC) and Hickory, NC; Philadelphia, Pennsylvania (PA) and Wilkes-Barre, PA; Seattle, Washington (WA) and Yakima, WA; and Milwaukee, Wisconsin (WI) and La Crosse, WI. The cities were selected to yield a broad geographic spread and both large and small cities. Fatalities from DWI-related accidents are highest in WA and lowest in NC (Mothers Against Drunking Driving 2012). Since the study focuses on DWI, SAD excluded persons reporting during the screener interview: no alcohol consumption or no driving in the past month. Respondents had to be at least age 18. The participant recruitment process was designed to oversample persons who consumed large amounts of alcohol and were prone to DWI to allow us to study the decision-making processes and behaviors of such individuals in detail.
This survey, the Survey of Alcohol and Driving (SAD), included detailed information on drinking, drinking and driving behaviors, risk perceptions, addiction, use of substances other than alcohol, knowledge of statutes and judicial practices with regard to DWI, personal attributes and attitudes, demographic characteristics, and income. When possible, questionnaire design was guided by questions that have been asked in prior surveys, albeit not all asked in the same instrument. The first wave of three was conducted using Computer Assisted Telephone Interviews (CATI). The other two waves were conducted by Computer Assisted Self-Administered Interviews (CASI). Wave 2 (CASI-1) contained questions on subjective beliefs. Wave 3 (CASI-2), also conducted by CASI, asked about realizations of beliefs elicited a year earlier in CASI-1. This study is based on data from all three waves. The CATI and CASI-1 and CASI-2 included 1,634, 1,359, and 1,187 individuals, respectively, the latter due to sample attrition.
1.2. Survey of Attorneys
During 2009-2010, we surveyed 62 attorneys in the eight cities in which the SAD was conducted. The questionnaire elicited information on a variety of topics, including the share of drunk drivers on the road, arrest resolution process, and characteristics of the attorneys’ clientele. We use these data for the analysis of the accuracy of the probability of being jailed conditional on being convicted of DWI.
1.3. State Data on DWI Arrests
We obtain information on individual arrests from each of the four study states for 2009. These data contain detailed information on the arrest resolution process and outcomes. We aggregate these data to the level of individual SAD cities from which we derive objective probabilities.
2. Comparisons of Subjective Beliefs and Objective Probabilities from Other Sources
2.1. Accuracy of Beliefs About Longevity
2.1.1. Overview
To assess accuracy of beliefs about longevity, we compare objective probabilities of survival based on our empirical analysis of survival using data from the Health and Retirement Study (HRS) for 1996-2008. The HRS is a national longitudinal survey of persons who were 51-61 in 1992 and their spouses/partners—who could be of any age. HRS participants were interviewed every other year.5 Using the parameter estimates from the analysis of survival with HRS data and data from the SAD, we compute objective probabilities of survival to each age. We focus on the probability of survival to age 60 for respondents who were age 36 or less when beliefs were elicited by the SAD and the probability of survival to age 75 for persons who were older than this. Past research has indicated that subjective survival expectations elicited by the HRS match objective life table values (Smith et al. 2001; Hurd and McGarry 2002; Hudomiet and Willis 2012).
2.1.2. Objective Probabilities of Survival
We estimate conditional hazard rates for mortality using HRS. The mean age of HRS participants was 58.8 years in 1996 (SD = 5.4), with ages ranging from 27 to 86.6 During 1996-2008, 16.2 percent died (of the 9,497 persons in the sample alive in 1996).
We estimate the relationship between observables likely to affect mortality using a hazard function for persons of all baseline ages, which allows for unobserved heterogeneity and assumes a Weibull distribution. The hazard function at year t for individual i in the HRS sample with observable explanatory variables Xi is given by:
(1), |
where λ0(t) is the baseline hazard for the Weibull distribution with the shape parameter μ and exp(Xt′θ) is the proportional hazard with parameters θ. A time invariant-specific unobserved heterogeneity multiplicative term ηi is distributed gamma with mean 1 and variance σ (e.g., Lancaster 1979). Time to failure is years from the interview date to date of death. All survivors at the 2008 HRS interview are treated as censored. Parameters are estimated using maximum likelihood.
The objective probability of living to a given age is
(2a) |
and,
(2b) |
where , , and are estimated from equation (1), and t is the number of years to age 60, 75 and their life expectancies.
We obtain baseline data from the 1996 HRS and follow persons through the 2008 HRS. The Xi include explanatory variables for drinker type, alcohol addiction, health, demographic characteristics and cognitive status. We exclude non-drinkers from the analysis sample since they were excluded from the SAD.
Drinker type consists of four groups. Heavy drinkers consumed 14+ drinks per week for men under age 65 or 7+ drinks for women and men over age 65. Binge drinkers consumed 5+ drinks for men and 4+ drinks for women on an occasion during the three months before the 1996 interview, but were not heavy drinkers. Heavy binge drinkers satisfy criteria for both binge and heavy drinkers. The omitted reference group is other drinkers.
We measure level of addiction to alcohol using the CAGE, a widely used screening tool. The CAGE is a screening test for alcohol dependence consisting of four questions: Have you felt you should Cut down on your drinking? Have people Annoyed you by criticizing your drinking? Have you ever felt Guilty about your drinking? and Have you ever had to drink first thing in the morning to steady your nerves or get rid of a hangover (Eye-opener)? We define binary variables for counts of one, two, and three or four affirmative responses with a binary variable for a count of zero omitted.
Demographic variables are female gender, age, Black race, Hispanic ethnicity, other race, currently married, and educational attainment (in years). Self-rated health is represented by a set of binary variables for very good, good, fair, and poor health, excellent health omitted.
We include several measures for cognition, all based on questions from the HRS (see Appendix Table 1A). The first measure (“recall”), adapted from the HRS, includes an exercise in counting backwards to assess attention and processing speed, and an object naming test to assess language, and recall of the date and name of the Vice President of the United States and the Governor of the state in which the respondent resided. The answers to the questions are summed to form a score with a range of 0 to 8. Second, to measure working memory, we include a serial 7 subtraction test based on a sequence of 5 questions, starting with 100 minus 7, with the next question based on the respondent’s answer to the first question minus 7, and so on. The maximum (best) score on this variable is 5. Third, we include a measure of the respondent’s numeracy. The numeracy question sought to learn whether or not the respondent was able to make percentage calculations. The explanatory variable for numeracy is a count of the number of correct answers to the three questions about numeracy. The fourth cognition measure is for a self-report of memory. Respondents were asked, “How would you rate your memory at the present time?” Response categories were excellent, very good, good, fair, poor. We combine responses to form a single binary variable for very good or good memory and a single binary variable for fair or poor memory, with excellent memory omitted.
The validity and reliability of the HRS cognition measures has been established (Ofstedal et al. 2005); several papers have assessed strengths and weaknesses of the HRS cognition measures (Plassman et al. 1994; Lachman and Spiro 2002; Crimmins et al. 2011).
Research has demonstrated that quantitative responses of individuals lower in numeracy are more sensitive to how questions are framed (Peters et al. 2006; Dickert et al. 2011); using more sophisticated questions than the SAD used, Frederick (2005) found that numeracy was systematically related to differences in individual preferences, e.g., risk tolerance. Numeracy has been linked to better performance on tasks requiring relatively intensive number processing or numeric assessment (Del Missier et al. 2010; Del Missier et al. 2012) and lower sensitivity to question framing effects (Peters et al. 2006; Peters et al. 2011). Individuals rely on memory in making choices when such information is readily retrievable from memory (Bettman et al. 1998). Poor memory may relate to less accurate assessments about the advantages and disadvantages of particular choices.
2.1.3. Hazard Results for Obtaining Objective Probabilities
Drinker type has no effect on survival (Table 1, hazard results). Nor does level of addiction to alcohol, cognitive status, race/ethnicity, or educational attainment (with health included). Decreases in health increase the probability of death monotonically from excellent (omitted) to poor health. Older persons at baseline have poor survival prospects.
Table 1. Objective Probability of Mortality.
Descriptive Statistics SAD |
Descriptive Statistics HRSa |
Hazard Results |
||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Coefficients | Hazard Ratios | |||||||
|
||||||||
Variables | Mean | Std. dev. |
Mean | Std. dev. |
Coefficient | Std. error |
Hazard ratio |
95% Conf. interval |
A. Alcohol consumption characteristics |
||||||||
Drinking categories | ||||||||
Heavy drinker | 0.05 | 0.21 | 0.06 | 0.23 | −0.26 | 0.21 | 0.77 | [0.51, 1.17] |
Binge drinker | 0.40 | 0.49 | 0.14 | 0.35 | 0.15 | 0.13 | 1.16 | [0.90, 1.49] |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.23 | 0.42 | 0.11 | 0.31 | 0.15 | 0.14 | 1.16 | [0.89, 1.51] |
Other drinker | 0.32 | 0.47 | 0.69 | 0.46 | - | - | - | - |
CAGE = 0 | 0.38 | 0.49 | 0.73 | 0.45 | - | - | - | - |
CAGE = 1 | 0.24 | 0.43 | 0.14 | 0.34 | 0.05 | 0.13 | 1.05 | [0.81, 1.36] |
CAGE = 2 | 0.21 | 0.41 | 0.079 | 0.27 | −0.11 | 0.17 | 0.90 | [0.65, 1.24] |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.17 | 0.38 | 0.053 | 0.22 | 0.17 | 0.17 | 1.19 | [0.85, 1.67] |
B. Health characteristics | ||||||||
Self-rated health | ||||||||
Excellent | 0.25 | 0.43 | 0.23 | 0.42 | - | - | - | - |
Very good | 0.44 | 0.50 | 0.36 | 0.48 | 0.43** | 0.16 | 1.54 | [1.13, 2.10] |
Good | 0.22 | 0.42 | 0.27 | 0.45 | 0.93** | 0.16 | 2.54 | [1.85, 3.49] |
Fair | 0.06 | 0.24 | 0.10 | 0.31 | 1.48** | 0.19 | 4.39 | [3.01, 6.39] |
Poor | 0.02 | 0.13 | 0.03 | 0.18 | 2.31** | 0.28 | 10.12 | [5.90, 17.38] |
Cognition status | ||||||||
Recall | 7.41 | 0.81 | 7.52 | 0.79 | −0.049 | 0.055 | 0.95 | [0.85, 1.06] |
Serial-7 subtraction | 4.56 | 0.90 | 3.88 | 1.47 | −0.044 | 0.034 | 0.96 | [0.90, 1.02] |
Numeracy | 2.45 | 0.77 | - | - | - | - | - | - |
Memory = excellent | 0.16 | 0.36 | 0.07 | 0.25 | - | - | - | - |
Memory = very good / good | 0.72 | 0.45 | 0.69 | 0.46 | −0.051 | 0.184 | 0.95 | [0.66, 1.36] |
Memory = fair / poor | 0.12 | 0.33 | 0.24 | 0.43 | −0.328 | 0.20 | 0.72 | [0.49. 1.07] |
C. Demographic characteristics | ||||||||
Female | 0.54 | 0.50 | 0.51 | 0.50 | −0.64** | 0.11 | 0.53 | [0.43, 0.65] |
Age | 43.4 | 12.51 | 58.77 | 5.43 | 0.086** | 0.011 | 1.09 | [1.07, 1.11] |
Non-Hispanic white | 0.86 | 0.34 | 0.81 | 0.39 | - | - | - | - |
Hispanic | 0.03 | 0.16 | 0.06 | 0.24 | −0.13 | 0.19 | 0.88 | [0.60, 1.28] |
Black | 0.11 | 0.32 | 0.12 | 0.32 | −0.12 | 0.14 | 0.89 | [0.67, 1.17] |
Other race | 0.04 | 0.19 | 0.02 | 0.15 | −0.35 | 0.33 | 0.70 | [0.36, 1.35] |
Currently married | 0.46 | 0.50 | 0.77 | 0.42 | −0.2 | 0.11 | 0.82 | [0.66, 1.01] |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | 15.6 | 1.94 | 12.95 | 2.85 | 0.023 | 0.018 | 1.02 | [0.99, 1.06] |
D. City | ||||||||
Raleigh | 0.39 | 0.49 | ||||||
Hickory | 0.06 | 0.23 | ||||||
Philadelphia | 0.11 | 0.32 | ||||||
Wilkes-Barre | 0.05 | 0.22 | ||||||
Seattle | 0.16 | 0.37 | ||||||
Yakima | 0.04 | 0.19 | ||||||
La Crosse | 0.08 | 0.27 | ||||||
Milwaukee | 0.11 | 0.31 | ||||||
E. Mortality | ||||||||
Prob. of death (through 2008) | - | - | 0.13 | 0.34 | - | - | - | - |
Intercept | −11.5** | 0.89 | - | - | ||||
Shape parameter | 1.585** | 0.081 | 1.585** | 0.081 | ||||
Log likelihood | −2086.8 | −2086.8 | ||||||
Number of observations | 1,359 | 4,957 | 4,957 | 4,957 |
Baseline characteristics are from HRS data wave 3, 1996.
HRS data are for 1996-2008.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
2.1.4. Subjective versus Objective Probabilities of Survival
To compare the subjective beliefs with corresponding objective probabilities of survival obtained from the above analysis of HRS data, we compute the difference in the subjective and objective probabilities of survival, the former from SAD and the latter predicted from our analysis of HRS.7
Respondents who were aged under 36 were asked, “On a scale from 0 to 10, with 0 being ‘not at all likely’ and 10 being ‘very likely,’ what is the chance you will be alive at age 60?” We convert the 0-10 scale for the questions about subjective beliefs about living to age 60 to probabilities. The same question was asked of persons aged 36+ except age 60 was changed to age 75. The mean subjective probability of living to 60 of persons under 36 (29.0% of the sample) is 0.87 and for persons 36+, the mean subjective probability of living to 75 is 0.84.
The dependent variable is the difference in subjective and objective probabilities of living to a particular age. Positive values in this analysis imply optimism and conversely for negative values. We estimate the difference in probabilities using ordinary least squares (OLS).
Young “other drinkers” were pessimistic about living to age 60, but older other drinkers were optimistic about living to age 75 (Table 2, Panel A, intercept, cols. 1 and 2). Young binge drinkers tended to be more optimistic about longevity than other young drinkers, but only slightly optimistic in absolute terms. There are no statistical differences from other drinkers by drinker type in the older group.
Table 2. Accuracy of Responses to Probability of Survival.
Survival to Age 60 | Survival to Age 75 | |||
---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||
Variables | Coefficient | Std. error |
Coefficient | Std. error |
|
||||
(1) | (2) | |||
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | 0.066 | 0.102 | −0.035 | 0.031 |
Binge drinker | 0.053* | 0.026 | 0.020 | 0.016 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.029 | 0.028 | 0.035 | 0.019 |
Intercept | −0.043 | 0.023 | 0.138** | 0.011 |
R2 | 0.013 | 0.007 | ||
Number of observations | 371 | 907 | ||
| ||||
Panel B. Full Specification | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | 0.038 | 0.101 | −0.054 | 0.029 |
Binge drinker | 0.070** | 0.026 | 0.028 | 0.016 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.042 | 0.031 | 0.008 | 0.019 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.008 | 0.024 | 0.005 | 0.017 |
CAGE = 2 | −0.006 | 0.025 | −0.010 | 0.018 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.003 | 0.027 | 0.067** | 0.021 |
Female | −0.001 | 0.019 | −0.040** | 0.014 |
Age | 0.006** | 0.002 | 0.004** | 0.001 |
Black | −0.010 | 0.029 | 0.015 | 0.022 |
Hispanic | −0.013 | 0.051 | −0.081 | 0.050 |
Other race | −0.020 | 0.047 | −0.048 | 0.045 |
Currently married | −0.023 | 0.024 | −0.046** | 0.014 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | 0.002 | 0.006 | −0.004 | 0.004 |
Self-rated health = very good | 0.026 | 0.022 | 0.040* | 0.017 |
Self-rated health = good | 0.085** | 0.027 | 0.094** | 0.020 |
Self-rated health = fair | 0.101* | 0.043 | 0.086** | 0.030 |
Self-rated health = poor | 0.212** | 0.074 | 0.244** | 0.051 |
Recall | −0.006 | 0.011 | −0.021* | 0.009 |
Serial-7 subtraction | −0.005 | 0.011 | −0.008 | 0.008 |
Numeracy | 0.025 | 0.013 | 0.005 | 0.010 |
Memory = very good / good | −0.027 | 0.024 | −0.047* | 0.019 |
Memory = fair / poor | −0.126** | 0.035 | −0.133** | 0.027 |
Intercept | −0.248* | 0.120 | 0.222* | 0.097 |
R2 | 0.116 | 0.139 | ||
Number of observations | 371 | 907 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
Results for drinker type are similar in the full specification (Panel B). Persons who tended to be optimistic were older, highly addicted to alcohol, and in poorer health. Persons with poorer recall and memory tended to be more pessimistic about their longevity.
Thus, our results on longevity are mixed. Persons under 36 tended to underestimate the probability of living to 60 but those 36+ overestimated the probability of living to 75. These results lend no support to the notion that heavy and binge drinkers are overly optimistic about their longevity prospects relative to other drinkers.
2.2. Accuracy of Beliefs about Harms of Drinking
In this sub-section, we report findings from analysis of subjective beliefs versus objective data on several negative outcomes of heavy and binge drinking.
2.2.1. Liver Diseases
Liver disease, alcoholic hepatitis (AH), and cirrhosis are important consequences of heavy drinking. For the subjective probability of getting liver disease, SAD asked “On a scale of 0 to 10, where 0 is 0% probability and 10 is 100% probability, what is the chance that long term heavy drinking will lead to liver disease?” On average, people estimated the probability to be 0.80. Based on the literature, we assume the objective probability of acquiring alcoholic hepatitis (AH) or cirrhosis conditional on heavy drinking, ranges from 0.1 to 0.5 (Naveau et al. 1997; McCullough et al. 2011; Mann et al. 2003).8 If a respondent gave a probability in this range, we consider the response to be accurate. We compute differences between subjective and actual responses for persons giving responses outside this range.
Including covariates for drinker type categories only, other drinkers overestimated the probability of getting alcohol-related liver disease by 0.33 (Table 3, Panel A, cols. 1), i.e., were pessimistic on average about this adverse outcome. These coefficients are robust to inclusion of additional explanatory variables. Heavy binge drinkers also overestimated this probability, but they were somewhat more accurate in their assessments. Accounting for the other covariates, heavy binge drinkers are still more accurate than other drinkers are (Panel B, col. 1).9
Table 3. Accuracy of Responses to Liver Disease and Intoxication Questions.
Probability of Getting Liver Disease if Drink to Excess |
No. Shots Needed to Be Over Legal Limit for DWI |
|||
---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||
Variables | Coefficient | Std.error | Coefficient | Std. error |
|
||||
(1) | (2) | |||
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | 0.004 | 0.022 | 0.049 | 0.220 |
Binge drinker | −0.019 | 0.011 | 0.32** | 0.110 |
Heavy binge drinker | −0.069** | 0.012 | 0.35** | 0.120 |
Intercept | 0.330* | 0.0079 | −0.87** | 0.079 |
R2 | 0.026 | 0.009 | ||
Number of observations | 1,346 | 1,349 | ||
| ||||
Panel B. Full Specification | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | −0.001 | 0.022 | 0.27 | 0.220 |
Binge drinker | −0.011 | 0.011 | 0.19 | 0.110 |
Heavy binge drinker | −0.064** | 0.013 | 0.41** | 0.130 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.014 | 0.012 | −0.17 | 0.110 |
CAGE = 2 | 0.005 | 0.013 | −0.16 | 0.120 |
CAGE = 3/4 | −0.003 | 0.014 | −0.046 | 0.130 |
Female | 0.014 | 0.010 | 0.66** | 0.092 |
Age | 0.001** | 0.000 | −0.012** | 0.004 |
Black | 0.018 | 0.015 | 0.66** | 0.140 |
Hispanic | −0.049 | 0.030 | −0.077 | 0.290 |
Other race | 0.035 | 0.027 | −0.11 | 0.260 |
Currently married | −0.005 | 0.010 | −0.013 | 0.094 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | −0.003 | 0.003 | −0.086** | 0.025 |
Self-rated health = very good | 0.002 | 0.011 | 0.026 | 0.110 |
Self-rated health = good | 0.001 | 0.013 | −0.15 | 0.130 |
Self-rated health = fair | 0.049* | 0.021 | −0.30 | 0.200 |
Self-rated health = poor | 0.091* | 0.035 | −0.65 | 0.340 |
Recall | −0.006 | 0.006 | 0.048 | 0.057 |
Serial-7 subtraction | −0.001 | 0.006 | 0.004 | 0.053 |
Numeracy | −0.013 | 0.007 | 0.005 | 0.065 |
Memory = very good / good | 0.010 | 0.013 | 0.012 | 0.120 |
Memory = fair / poor | −0.005 | 0.018 | 0.064 | 0.170 |
Intercept | 0.38** | 0.060 | 0.32 | 0.581 |
R2 | 0.061 | 0.10 | ||
Number of observations | 1,332 | 1,335 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
2.2.2. Consumption Needed for Intoxication
The SAD asked “Try to estimate the number of one and one-quarter ounce shots of liquor that you would have to drink to bring you over the legal limit.” On average, respondents estimated that it would take 3.0 shots (SD = 1.6) to reach the minimum blood-alcohol content level. Estimates of the objective number of shots needed to reach the minimum BAC level of 0.08, which would make them subject to a DWI arrest, are calculated by gender and body weight.10 For men, the mean number of shots needed to reach a BAC of 0.08 at the sample mean of weight is four shots; for women at mean weight, the number of shots is three. Thus, people seem to be fairly accurate in judging how many drinks are needed to reach an illegal BAC for driving.
Among drinker types, other drinkers, who are presumably less familiar with the intoxicating effects of drinking based on their personal experiences, underestimated i.e. were pessimistic about the shots needed by almost a drink to become legally intoxicated (−0.87, SE=0.079, Table 3, Panel A, col. 2). Heavy binge and binge drinkers were more accurate than other drinkers, implying learning by doing (Table 4, Panel A), but they were also pessimistic about this outcome on average. The parameter estimate for heavy drinkers is not statistically different from other drinkers and is robust to changes in specification (Panel B).
Table 4. Accuracy of Responses to Fraction of Drunk Drivers on Road.
Variables | Coefficient | Std. error |
---|---|---|
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||
| ||
Heavy drinker | −0.005 | 0.026 |
Binge drinker | 0.015 | 0.012 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.014 | 0.014 |
Intercept | 0.011 | 0.009 |
R2 | 0.001 | |
Number of observations | 1,321 | |
| ||
Panel B. Full Specification | ||
| ||
Heavy drinker | −0.009 | 0.025 |
Binge drinker | 0.007 | 0.013 |
Heavy binge drinker | −0.000 | 0.015 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.005 | 0.013 |
CAGE = 2 | 0.013 | 0.014 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.030 | 0.016 |
Female | 0.044** | 0.011 |
Age | 0.001* | 0.000 |
Black | 0.024 | 0.017 |
Hispanic | 0.015 | 0.034 |
Other race | 0.031 | 0.030 |
Currently married | −0.055** | 0.011 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | −0.002 | 0.003 |
Recall | −0.016* | 0.007 |
Serial-7 subtraction | −0.013* | 0.006 |
Numeracy | −0.037** | 0.008 |
Memory = very good / good | −0.024 | 0.014 |
Memory = fair / poor | −0.039 | 0.020 |
Intercept | 0.278** | 0.067 |
R2 | 0.112 | |
Number of observations | 1,309 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
2.3. Accuracy of Beliefs about Drunk Drivers on the Road
Individuals may avoid being involved in an alcohol related accident by not driving at times during which many drivers are intoxicated. For the subjective probability, SAD asked, “On average on a weekend evening, what percent of drivers on the road have had too much to drink?” We interpret “too much to drink” as a minimum BAC of 0.08. The mean subjective percent is 23.2 (SD = 17.9), which is above objective estimates from other sources.
There is a lack of consensus in the literature about the percent of drunk drivers on the road on an average weekend evening. Lacey et al. (2009) conducted a survey of drivers in 300 locations in 48 states during four two-hour periods. The authors calculated the percent drunk drivers at 2.2 for 2007. Estimates from other sources are considerably higher. Levitt and Porter (2001), using a novel approach, inferred the percent of drunk drivers between 8 pm to 5 am from national Fatal Accident Reporting System (FARS) data. Their estimates ranged from 13.6 to 29.6 percent. Even if the incidence of drunk driving has declined over time (see e.g., Lacey et al. 2009), these estimates, nevertheless, imply substantial amounts of drunk driving.
We use the Levitt and Porter (LP) method for the eight cities included in the SAD, using FARS data for 2009. LP computed national rather than city-specific estimates. We limit analysis to fatalities resulting from motor vehicle accidents occurring between 8 pm and 5 am. Although the SAD question referred to weekends, to have a sufficient number of observations for the smaller cities, we include data on 8 pm to 5 am accidents on weekdays as well as weekends. We rely on data from the police officer’s evaluation of whether or not a driver had been drinking as reported by the FARS. Estimated parameters that maximize the log likelihood are presented in the appendix (Table 2A). The relative ratio of drinking to sober drivers on the road varies plausibly, from 0.14 in Philadelphia to 0.15 in Seattle and 0.40 in Milwaukee to 0.57 in La Crosse. The latter is a college town in a state with comparatively high alcohol consumption levels.
All drinker type groups are accurate on average in assessing the objective shares of drunk drivers on the road (Table 4, Panel A). Results for drinker type from the full specification are similar to those from the limited specification. The positive intercept in the full specification implies that middle-aged, college educated, non-Hispanic white men with excellent cognition overestimate shares of drunk drivers on the road.11 Better recall, serial subtraction scores, and numeracy are associated with more accurate estimates of actual drunk driver shares (Panel B).
2.4. Accuracy of Beliefs About Legal Consequences of Driving under the Influence
State legislatures have established penalties for drinking and driving with the intent of deterring such behavior. The SAD asked a series of questions about (1) the probability of conviction for DWI, given that the person has been pulled over and has had too much to drink; (2) conditional on the probability of being convicted for DWI, the probability that the person would receive a fine; (3) the amount of fines, given that the person has been charged a fine; (4) conditional on a DWI conviction, the probability of receiving some jail time; and (5) conditional on some jail time, the amount of jail time the person could expect to receive.
The SAD did not ask about the probability of arrest if a person drove after having had too much to drink. For this reason, we do not compare subjective and objective probabilities of arrest conditional on having had too much to drink. Unless otherwise indicated, the objective probabilities come from state arrest data.
2.4.1. Conviction
Using state arrest data for the objective benchmark, other drinkers are very accurate in estimating the probability of conviction conditional on arrest. The coefficient is 0.017 with a standard error of 0.017 (Table 5, Panel A, intercept, col. 1). Binge and heavy binge drinkers overestimated the probability of conviction conditional on being arrested, i.e., were too pessimistic about this outcome although they frequently admitted to drinking and driving.
Table 5. Accuracy of Responses to Legal Consequences of DWI: Conviction and Fines.
Probability of Conviction if Arrested |
Probability of Fine if Convicted |
Fine amount $ | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Variables |
|
|||||
Coefficient | Std. error | Coefficient | Std. error | Coefficient | Std. error | |
|
||||||
(1) | (2) | (3) | ||||
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | 0.060 | 0.046 | −0.031 | 0.063 | −100 | 94.8 |
Binge drinker | 0.073** | 0.022 | 0.028 | 0.03 | 57.8 | 45.8 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.15** | 0.025 | 0.022 | 0.034 | 85.1 | 52.5 |
Intercept | 0.017 | 0.017 | 0.227** | 0.022 | 223** | 34.3 |
R2 (Pseudo R2 for probit) | 0.022 | 0.001 | 0.004 | |||
Number of observations | 1,315 | 1,311 | 1,285 | |||
| ||||||
Panel B. Full Specificationb | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | 0.081 | 0.044 | −0.008 | 0.025 | −8.12 | 92.8 |
Binge drinker | 0.053* | 0.023 | 0.026* | 0.013 | 25.6 | 48.2 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.10** | 0.027 | 0.032* | 0.015 | 67.8 | 56.8 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.032 | 0.023 | −0.002 | 0.013 | 16.0 | 49.3 |
CAGE = 2 | 0.033 | 0.025 | 0.017 | 0.014 | 48.8 | 52.7 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.063* | 0.028 | 0.011 | 0.016 | 43.6 | 58.5 |
Female | −0.077** | 0.019 | −0.030** | 0.011 | −3.10 | 40.0 |
Age | 0.001 | 0.001 | 0.001 | 0.000 | −3.35* | 1.70 |
Black | −0.054 | 0.030 | −0.051** | 0.017 | −149* | 64.0 |
Hispanic | −0.079 | 0.061 | 0.012 | 0.035 | 55.6 | 127 |
Other race | 0.052 | 0.053 | −0.057 | 0.031 | 86.6 | 113 |
Currently married | −0.033 | 0.019 | −0.003 | 0.011 | 27.8 | 41.4 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | −0.013** | 0.005 | −0.001 | 0.003 | −9.22 | 10.7 |
Recall | 0.003 | 0.012 | −0.003 | 0.007 | −17.4 | 24.9 |
Serial-7 subtraction | 0.001 | 0.011 | 0.018** | 0.006 | 20.1 | 23.0 |
Numeracy | 0.006 | 0.013 | 0.010 | 0.008 | 2.00 | 28.2 |
Memory = very good / good | 0.021 | 0.025 | −0.017 | 0.014 | 1.83 | 52.3 |
Memory = fair / poor | −0.001 | 0.034 | −0.022 | 0.020 | 2.84 | 73.6 |
Prior DWI arrestc | 0.14* | 0.061 | 0.045 | 0.035 | 61.4 | 128 |
Intercept | 0.25* | 0.12 | −0.19** | 0.07 | 661 | 259 |
R2 (Pseudo R2 for probit) | 0.169 | 0.847 | 0.091 | |||
Number of observations | 1,303 | 1,299 | 1,274 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
Location binary variables (all 8 cities in the sample, with Raleigh being omitted reference group) are included in regression but not shown.
DWI conviction within past 3 years
p<0.01,
p<0.05
In the full specification, results for binge and heavy binge drinkers appear fairly robust to the addition of several covariates (Panel B, cols. 1, 2). We add covariates for the respondent’s self-report of having been arrested for DWI in the past three years and binary variables for the city in which the respondent resided (the latter results not shown). The parameter estimate on the prior arrest covariate is 0.14. The positive coefficient does not necessarily imply that persons reporting a previous DWI arrest were relatively pessimistic about the probability of conviction if arrested since the actual conviction rates are citywide, and we do not account for prior arrest records of offenders.
2.4.2. Fines
We also obtain data on the probability of being fined from state arrest records. Other drinkers overestimate the probability of being fined by 0.23 (Table 5, Panel A, col. 2); other drinkers do not differ from heavy, binge, and heavy binge drinkers in their estimates of the probability of being fined.
In the full specification (Panel B), parameter estimates on the binary variables for binge and heavy binge drinkers are positive and statistically significant, but similar in magnitude to the parameter estimates in the limited specification and not very large. The coefficient on prior DWI arrest is not statistically significant.
We obtain information on fine amounts for DWI from state statutes.12 We consider an answer correct if it is within the minimum to maximum range of statutory guidelines in the respondent’s state. In such cases, the dependent variable is set to 0. If the answer is incorrect, we measure the difference between the respondent estimate and the relevant lower or upper bound of the minimum to maximum range.
Considering estimated fines within the guidelines as correct, other drinkers overestimated the fine by $223 on average (Panel A, intercept, col. 3). We find no statistical differences between heavy, binge, and heavy binge drinkers and other drinkers in accuracy of magnitudes of fines. Adding covariates does not materially affect the parameter estimates for drinker type (Panel B).
2.4.3. Jail
We obtain estimates of objective probabilities of jail conditional on conviction from two alternative sources, arrest data and from our survey of attorneys. A deficiency of the arrest data is that they are for sentences rather than time actually served. Some persons are sentenced to jail, but the sentence is immediately converted to probation or community service. Like subjective beliefs, the data from attorneys are more likely to reflect actual jail perceptions.
Overall, using the state arrest data for the objective probabilities, other drinkers substantially underestimated the probability of jail conditional on a conviction for DWI (Table 6, Panel A, intercept, col. 1), i.e., were too optimistic. The coefficient is −0.33. Binge and heavy binge drinkers also underestimated the probability of jail, but were more accurate on average than other drinkers were. However, the differences between binge and heavy binge drinkers and other drinkers disappear when we add additional covariates (Panel B). Using objective data from attorneys rather than from arrest data (col. 2), other drinkers were quite accurate in their assessments of probabilities of jail conditional on a conviction, and there are no statistical differences between the other drinker types and other drinkers.
Table 6. Accuracy of Responses to Legal Consequences of DWI: Jail.
Probability of Jail if Convicted |
Probability of Jail if Convicted |
Jail Time (Days) | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||||
Arrest Data | Attorney Survey | |||||
|
||||||
Variables | Coefficient | Std.error | Coefficient | Std. error | Coefficient | Std. error |
|
||||||
(1) | (2) | (3) | ||||
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | 0.032 | 0.073 | −0.094 | 0.055 | −5.00 | 21.9 |
Binge drinker | 0.091** | 0.035 | 0.027 | 0.026 | −8.97 | 10.4 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.090* | 0.04 | 0.049 | 0.030 | −5.64 | 11.9 |
Intercept | −0.33** | 0.026 | 0.005 | 0.020 | 33.0** | 7.78 |
R2 (Pseudo R2 for probit) | 0.006 | 0.006 | 0.001 | |||
Number of observations | 1,302 | 1,302 | 1,300 | |||
| ||||||
Panel B. Full Specificationb | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | −0.004 | 0.038 | −0.004 | 0.037 | −5.76 | 22.3 |
Binge drinker | 0.014 | 0.019 | 0.014 | 0.019 | −9.47 | 11.2 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.019 | 0.022 | 0.019 | 0.023 | −6.75 | 13.1 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.044* | 0.020 | 0.044* | 0.020 | −8.69 | 11.6 |
CAGE = 2 | 0.026 | 0.021 | 0.026 | 0.021 | 7.96 | 12.3 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.062** | 0.023 | 0.062** | 0.023 | −5.99 | 13.8 |
Female | −0.010 | 0.016 | −0.010 | 0.016 | 0.98 | 9.4 |
Age | −0.000 | 0.001 | −0.000 | 0.001 | 0.60 | 0.4 |
Black | 0.025 | 0.026 | 0.025 | 0.026 | 16.4 | 15.1 |
Hispanic | 0.017 | 0.051 | 0.017 | 0.051 | 84.2** | 30.0 |
Other race | −0.029 | 0.045 | −0.029 | 0.045 | 46.4 | 26.6 |
Currently married | −0.049** | 0.016 | −0.049** | 0.016 | −11.7 | 9.7 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | −0.011* | 0.004 | −0.011* | 0.004 | −2.51 | 2.5 |
Recall | −0.016 | 0.010 | −0.016 | 0.010 | −5.87 | 5.8 |
Serial-7 subtraction | −0.016 | 0.009 | −0.016 | 0.009 | 8.44 | 5.4 |
Numeracy | −0.012 | 0.011 | −0.012 | 0.011 | −12.5 | 6.6 |
Memory = very good / good | 0.006 | 0.021 | 0.006 | 0.021 | 11.7 | 12.3 |
Memory = fair / poor | −0.008 | 0.029 | −0.008 | 0.029 | −8.93 | 17.2 |
Prior DWI arrestc | 0.094 | 0.051 | 0.094 | 0.051 | −20.8 | 30.2 |
Intercept | −0.377** | 0.10 | 0.56** | 0.10 | 71 | 60.7 |
R2 (Pseudo R2 for probit) | 0.752 | 0.57 | 0.048 | |||
Number of observations | 1,290 | 1,290 | 1,289 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
Location binary variables (all 8 cities in the sample, with Raleigh being omitted reference group) are included in regression but not shown.
DWI conviction within past 3 years
p<0.01,
p<0.05
For fines, data on jail sentences come from state statutes. As for fine amounts, other drinkers were pessimistic about jail term lengths (Panel A, col. 3), conditional on being convicted. And there are no statistical differences between the other drinker types and other drinkers. It is possible that respondents were more accurate than they appear to the extent that jail terms in the statutes are not enforced.
2.5. Overall Optimism
Using responses to the above items, we create an optimism index, a count of all responses for which the respondent was optimistic. Since respondents sometimes did not answer all 10 items included in the index, we include a covariate for the number of items for which we have data from the respondent. Since the dependent variable is a count variable, we use ordered logit analysis. The mean fraction of optimistic responses is 0.22.
In the limited specification (Table 7, Panel A), binge and especially heavy binge drinkers are overall less often optimistic than their other drinker counterparts. Statistical significance for binge and heavy binge drinker is lost in the full specification, but the odds ratios, albeit slightly higher than in the limited specification, are not very different. Alcohol-addicted individuals are less likely to be optimistic than persons without this addiction.
Table 7. Optimism Index.
Variables | Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
---|---|---|
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||
| ||
Heavy drinker | 1.083 | 0.669 - 1.753 |
Binge drinker | 0.750* | 0.596 - 0.944 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.563** | 0.432 - 0.734 |
Number of questions answered | 2.024** | 1.811 - 2.263 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.053 | |
Number of observations | 1,359 | |
| ||
Panel B. Full Specification | ||
| ||
Heavy drinker | 1.023 | 0.626 - 1.670 |
Binge drinker | 0.877 | 0.682 - 1.128 |
Heavy binge drinker | 0.795 | 0.591 - 1.069 |
Number of questions answered | 2.138** | 1.895 - 2.411 |
CAGE = 1 | 0.667** | 0.514 - 0.866 |
CAGE = 2 | 0.740* | 0.562 - 0.975 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 0.676* | 0.498 - 0.918 |
Female | 1.650** | 1.337 - 2.037 |
Age | 1.010* | 1.001 - 1.019 |
Black | 2.467** | 1.752 - 3.475 |
Hispanic | 1.392 | 0.709 - 2.735 |
Other race | 0.472* | 0.256 - 0.867 |
Currently married | 1.145 | 0.924 - 1.419 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | 1.019 | 0.963 - 1.078 |
Self-rated health = very good | 1.068 | 0.833 - 1.369 |
Self-rated health = good | 1.002 | 0.748 - 1.342 |
Self-rated health = fair | 0.584* | 0.370 - 0.923 |
Self-rated health = poor | 1.018 | 0.454 - 2.280 |
Recall | 1.039 | 0.913 - 1.183 |
Serial-7 subtraction | 0.964 | 0.852 - 1.090 |
Numeracy | 1.086 | 0.934 - 1.264 |
Memory = very good / good | 1.053 | 0.795 - 1.394 |
Memory = fair / poor | 1.086 | 0.729 - 1.618 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.073 | |
Number of observations | 1,345 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
3. Within Sample Comparisons of Subjective Beliefs and Objective Probabilities
The second wave of the SAD (CASI-1) contained several questions about the probabilities of outcomes expected to occur during the following year, asked on a scale of 0-100. The third wave (CASI-2) was fielded a year later and asked about realizations of the same outcomes. Unfortunately, for our analysis, only nine CASI-2 respondents reported having been arrested for a DWI in the past year. Only heavy binge and binge drinkers were among the nine persons charged with this offense (Fig. 1). Yet subjective probabilities of being arrested for a DWI in the next year rise monotonically from other drinker, to heavy, binge, and heavy binge drinker. All drinker types were too pessimistic about the probability of a DWI arrest in the following year.
Among the other subjective beliefs elicited in the second wave are probabilities of any binge drinking, a citation for driving over 15 miles per hour above the speed limit and a motor vehicle accident. A minority of respondents who experienced an accident were charged with a driving violation (13.6%).
Respondents were too pessimistic about the probabilities of being cited for speeding and of having an accident, and too optimistic about not drinking and driving during the following year. Subjective beliefs for being cited and having an accident do not exhibit the same patterns by drinker types as DWI arrests. However, the pattern for drinking and driving by drinker type is similar to that for DWI arrests. The three outcomes about which respondents were too pessimistic reflect randomly occurring events beyond respondents’ control. By contrast, drinking and driving is fully under the individual’s own control, and respondents were too optimistic about this outcome.
We use logit analysis of a binary variable for whether or not the person actually drank and drove, was cited for driving more than 15 miles per hour over the speed limit, or had an accident during the previous year as reported at the third survey wave. We add a covariate for subjective beliefs for each of three outcomes as reported in CASI-1.
The odds ratios on the covariates for the subjective probabilities of drinking and driving are 27.3 and 3.08, respectively, and are statistically significant (Table 8, Panel A, cols. 1, 2). The odds ratio for the subjective probability of an accident is 2.43, but this result is not statistically significant. Overall, these results imply that people can indeed predict the future.13 Odds ratios for drinker type in the drinking and driving analysis rise monotonically from other drinker to heavy binge drinker. Heavy binge drinkers were also more likely to have been cited for speeding, even after accounting for subjective beliefs about this outcome.
Table 8. Ability of Past Subjective Beliefs to Predict Future Outcomes.
Realized Drinking-Driving | Realized >15 mph Citation | Realized Accident | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||||
Variables | Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
|
||||||
(1) | (2) | (3) | ||||
Panel A. Limited Specificationa | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | 1.399 | 0.654 - 2.989 | 1.092 | 0.240 - 4.969 | 0.580 | 0.172 - 1.955 |
Binge drinker | 2.855** | 1.985 - 4.105 | 1.152 | 0.575 - 2.305 | 0.748 | 0.460 - 1.215 |
Heavy binge drinker | 4.801** | 3.193 - 7.219 | 2.211* | 1.105 - 4.423 | 1.066 | 0.634 - 1.790 |
Subjective beliefs | 27.31** | 14.93 - 49.97 | 3.083** | 1.459 - 6.513 | 2.430 | 0.669 - 8.834 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.214 | 0.031 | 0.007 | |||
Number of observations | 1,150 | 1,153 | 1,152 | |||
| ||||||
Panel B. Full Specification | ||||||
| ||||||
Heavy drinker | 1.329 | 0.589 - 3.000 | 1.463 | 0.305 - 7.031 | 0.616 | 0.175 - 2.167 |
Binge drinker | 1.688* | 1.120 - 2.545 | 0.757 | 0.358 - 1.602 | 0.696 | 0.406 - 1.193 |
Heavy binge drinker | 2.538** | 1.591 - 4.048 | 1.494 | 0.677 - 3.294 | 0.868 | 0.473 - 1.592 |
Subjective beliefs | 10.28** | 5.534 - 19.08 | 2.603* | 1.159 - 5.844 | 1.852 | 0.466 - 7.362 |
History | 3.856** | 2.786 - 5.336 | 3.055** | 1.667 - 5.599 | 2.780** | 1.783 - 4.335 |
CAGE = 1 | 1.092 | 0.730 - 1.634 | 1.230 | 0.599 - 2.524 | 0.595 | 0.317 - 1.117 |
CAGE = 2 | 1.217 | 0.808 - 1.832 | 0.725 | 0.315 - 1.671 | 1.012 | 0.561 - 1.826 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 1.154 | 0.727 - 1.831 | 1.305 | 0.595 - 2.863 | 1.547 | 0.854 - 2.801 |
Female | 0.607** | 0.441 - 0.835 | 1.033 | 0.578 - 1.845 | 0.901 | 0.571 - 1.420 |
Age | 0.983* | 0.969 - 0.996 | 0.970* | 0.945 - 0.996 | 0.996 | 0.978 - 1.015 |
Black | 0.806 | 0.490 - 1.325 | 0.933 | 0.390 - 2.234 | 1.164 | 0.604 - 2.244 |
Hispanic | 1.786 | 0.660 - 4.832 | (omitted) | - | 0.323 | 0.040 - 2.593 |
Other race | 0.729 | 0.253 - 2.096 | (omitted) | - | 2.817 | 0.983 - 8.070 |
Currently married | 0.944 | 0.676 - 1.317 | 1.163 | 0.625 - 2.162 | 0.829 | 0.513 - 1.338 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | 0.940 | 0.864 - 1.024 | 0.894 | 0.768 - 1.042 | 1.002 | 0.890 - 1.129 |
Recall | 1.113 | 0.907 - 1.367 | 0.973 | 0.687 - 1.378 | 0.875 | 0.669 - 1.145 |
Serial-7 subtraction | 1.037 | 0.861 - 1.248 | 1.092 | 0.788 - 1.514 | 0.971 | 0.757 - 1.244 |
Numeracy | 1.069 | 0.849 - 1.344 | 0.938 | 0.629 - 1.400 | 1.159 | 0.830 - 1.618 |
Memory = very good / good | 1.758* | 1.126 - 2.746 | 0.744 | 0.360 - 1.536 | 1.036 | 0.563 - 1.907 |
Memory = fair / poor | 2.168* | 1.183 - 3.975 | 1.604 | 0.630 - 4.083 | 1.743 | 0.819 - 3.709 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.285 | 0.096 | 0.067 | |||
Number of observations | 1,139 | 1,092 | 1,140 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
Results in the full specification for drinker type and subjective beliefs are similar although adding covariates reduces the magnitudes of the odds ratios, and the odds ratio for heavy binge drinker loses significance in the analysis of speeding citations. The odds ratios on “History” of prior DWI arrests, speeding citations, and accident are all above 2.0 and statistically significant. Even after accounting for subjective beliefs, there is considerable information content in histories of prior citations, arrests, and accidents—information used by motor vehicle insurers in setting premiums.
Overall, these results imply that individuals have fairly accurate beliefs about future events, particularly those under their control. They are sometimes too optimistic, but this is not a general pattern.
4. Other Findings
Two other findings are relevant for interpreting our key results. First, people may think that probabilities of both good and adverse outcomes apply to others and not to themselves. SAD asked respondents to assess their driving skills relative to others, “How would you rate yourself as a driver relative to other drivers?” Response options were: much better; better; about the same; worse; and much worse. The odds of binge and heavy binge drinkers viewing their driving ability as relatively favorable are substantially increased over the omitted reference group, other drinkers (Table 9).
Table 9. Self-rated Ability.
Handle Alcohol Better | Rate Self as Better Driver | |||
---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||
Variables | Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
Odds ratio | Confidence interval |
|
||||
(1) | (2) | |||
Panel A. Limited specificationa | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | 2.013** | 1.251 - 3.241 | 1.328 | 0.785 - 2.247 |
Binge drinker | 3.179** | 2.504 - 4.037 | 1.353* | 1.053 - 1.739 |
Heavy binge drinker | 7.399** | 5.579 - 9.812 | 1.703** | 1.273 - 2.280 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.056 | 0.005 | ||
Number of observations | 1,351 | 1,167 | ||
| ||||
Panel B. Full specification | ||||
| ||||
Heavy drinker | 2.311** | 1.412 - 3.785 | 1.159 | 0.674 - 1.995 |
Binge drinker | 2.940** | 2.264 - 3.817 | 1.460** | 1.110 - 1.921 |
Heavy binge drinker | 5.063** | 3.712 - 6.906 | 1.654** | 1.194 - 2.292 |
CAGE = 1 | 1.204 | 0.926 - 1.567 | 0.810 | 0.608 - 1.079 |
CAGE = 2 | 1.234 | 0.933 - 1.632 | 0.963 | 0.712 - 1.303 |
CAGE = 3/4 | 1.906** | 1.385 - 2.625 | 0.682* | 0.480 - 0.971 |
Female | 0.252** | 0.201 - 0.315 | 0.546** | 0.432 - 0.690 |
Age | 0.986** | 0.977 - 0.995 | 1.011* | 1.001 - 1.021 |
Black | 1.268 | 0.897 - 1.791 | 1.230 | 0.845 - 1.792 |
Hispanic | 1.092 | 0.556 - 2.145 | 0.927 | 0.413 - 2.085 |
Other race | 0.446* | 0.234 - 0.852 | 0.927 | 0.449 - 1.915 |
Currently married | 0.878 | 0.705 - 1.094 | 0.865 | 0.684 - 1.095 |
Edu. attainment (yrs.) | 0.962 | 0.908 - 1.019 | 0.948 | 0.890 - 1.009 |
Self-rated health = very good | 1.070 | 0.834 - 1.375 | 0.669** | 0.509 - 0.880 |
Self-rated health = good | 1.068 | 0.791 - 1.443 | 0.597** | 0.429 - 0.830 |
Self-rated health = fair | 1.169 | 0.733 - 1.865 | 0.465** | 0.273 - 0.793 |
Self-rated health = poor | 1.284 | 0.564 - 2.926 | 1.154 | 0.443 - 3.003 |
Recall | 1.067 | 0.934 - 1.219 | 1.022 | 0.879 - 1.189 |
Serial-7 subtraction | 1.037 | 0.912 - 1.178 | 0.993 | 0.866 - 1.139 |
Numeracy | 1.151 | 0.989 - 1.341 | 0.990 | 0.836 - 1.171 |
Memory = very good / good | 1.322 | 0.994 - 1.759 | 0.655** | 0.479 - 0.896 |
Memory = fair / poor | 1.254 | 0.836 - 1.882 | 0.496** | 0.314 - 0.782 |
Pseudo R2 | 0.114 | 0.032 | ||
Number of observations | 1,337 | 1,156 |
Other drinker is the omitted reference group.
p<0.01,
p<0.05
CASI-1 also asked, “Compared to the average driver, do you think that you can safely handle much more alcohol, somewhat more, about the same, somewhat less, or much less alcohol than the average driver?” As with perceived driving ability, we find that binge and heavy binge drinkers are more optimistic about their ability to handle alcohol. Thus, juxtaposed against our main findings, which do not support optimism bias in the context of alcohol consumption, is the same kind of finding that has led scholars to hypothesize that optimism bias underlies decisions about harmful choices.14
Although heavy and heavy binge drinkers tend to think that they are more capable than others, evidence from our analysis of data from the SAD suggests that this belief does not generally translate to subjective beliefs about specific outcomes of high levels of drinking.15 A criticism of this line of questioning is that the results may be due to question framing. In particular, questions comparing the individual’s subjective probability of an adverse outcome to the same individual’s assessment of the probability faced by the “average” person may yield biased results. First, average is not defined and individuals are likely to have different reference groups. Also, people may be reluctant to state that they are “below average” or more “vulnerable than average” (Viscusi 2002), especially if they often engage in the activity to which the question refers.
Second, some studies infer from focal responses (0, 50, 100%) that people do not have well formed subjective beliefs about important personal outcomes conditional on their personal choices.16 A preponderance of “50%” responses may be particularly indicative of lack of a firm subjective belief. Figure 2 shows the frequency of responses to questions in the SAD phrased in the second person, and Figure 3 shows the frequency distributions for questions phrased in the third person. As seen in Fig. 3, there are indications of focal responses for the probability of being convicted conditional on an arrest and for the probability of jail conditional on conviction, but little or no indications of focal responses for the other outcomes.
5. Discussion and Conclusions
The motivation for this study was to determine whether people engage in risky drinking behavior because they underestimate the adverse consequences from their actions. Overall, our results indicate that optimism bias does not explain why people engage in heavy, binge, and heavy binge drinking.17
As an alternative to the optimism bias hypothesis, persons who drink frequently and consume large amounts of alcohol daily could be more familiar with the risks of such behaviors. Even advocates of optimism bias have indicated that such bias should decrease with personal experience (Weinstein 1987). In our study, there is some evidence in support of such learning by doing from our analysis of the probability of getting liver disease from long-term drinking, the number of drinks required to reach a BAC of 0.08, and the probability of jail conditional on conviction, but not for the other study outcomes.
Underlying measurement of accuracy of beliefs is the notion or premise that the objective probability is known. For one of our study measures, there is no consensus among experts about what the underlying objective values are. There is disagreement in the literature and among persons who have gained practical experience—such as the attorneys and police we surveyed in the study cities18—about the percent of drunk drivers on the road on weekend evenings. Even if the city-specific estimates we use are rough, as they undoubtedly are, it is noteworthy that the subjective beliefs of the respondents to SAD do not differ systematically from the objective estimates.
Dionne et al. (2007) used survey data on drinking and driving behaviors, knowledge of regulations, attitudes toward drinking and driving, and personal characteristics to assess the accuracy of subjective beliefs about the risk of impaired driving. Unlike our sample, half of their sample persons had been convicted for impaired driving. Their main result relevant to our findings is that no variable measuring drinking behaviors had much influence on risk perceptions. There is some evidence in the Dionne et al. study that individuals who “do not drink” or “do not drink an hour before driving” are more likely to overestimate the risk of having an accident occasioning a police report while drinking and driving. Similarly, individuals who “do not drink” are more likely to overestimate the risk of having an accident causing bodily injuries or death while drinking and driving. Dionne et al. did not analyze these explanatory variables for heavy, binge, and heavy binge drinkers, and the SAD excluded non-drinkers since the survey’s main focus was on determinants of drinking and driving.
If drivers on the whole are aware or even pessimistic about the adverse consequences of excessive alcohol use, why do they engage in such behaviors? One possibility is that people do not intend to engage in risky behaviors, but do so because they lack self-control (Gul and Pesendorfer 2001). This is a possible explanation of our finding that SAD respondents’ subjective probabilities about drinking and driving in the following year exceeded the actual probabilities.
Several indicators of self-control were elicited by the SAD, but they are not analyzed in this study. The SAD asked a series of 12 questions to elicit estimates of the respondent’s impulsivity and self-control. Compared to other drinkers, binge and heavy binge drinkers exhibited higher levels of impulsivity/lack of self-control than other drinkers did.
A second possibility is that individuals make rational choices in regards to their alcohol consumption. On some level, the benefits of alcohol consumption behaviors, such as socializing in connection with drinking, may outweigh the adverse consequences. The SAD got at this by asking, “How important is it for your social life to be able to enjoy a few drinks with your friends?” Binge and heavy binge drinkers were significantly more likely to state that drinking was quite important or very important to their social lives. Heavy drinkers attached higher importance to drinking for their social lives then other drinkers did, but the difference between heavy and other drinkers was not quite significant at conventional levels.
Third, the cost of the adverse consequences may be less for persons who consume a lot of alcoholic beverages. For example, the SAD asked about the costs of a DWI arrest to the respondent’s personal life. Heavy and heavy binge drinkers were less likely to state that the cost of a DWI arrest was high.
Our study has several strengths. First, it is based on data from eight geographically diverse cities with different cultures and attitudes towards drinking. Second, the SAD oversampled heavy and binge drinkers in order to examine the details of their behaviors. Third, given that the SAD was conducted in multiple waves, we are able to measure outcomes for the same individuals for which we have past subjective beliefs about the probabilities that these same outcomes would occur. Fourth, we compare subjective beliefs to objective data from a variety of secondary sources. Fifth, we analyze subjective beliefs about specific outcomes and overconfidence in the same study. Sixth, although our focus was on accuracy of risk perceptions among persons by drinker type, we also consider a multitude of factors involved in high levels of alcohol use. Seventh, our conclusions are based on analysis of risk perceptions about a variety of issues as they pertain to consequences of heavy and binge drinking.
We also acknowledge some weaknesses in our study. First, rejecting the notion that optimism bias does not explain high levels of alcohol use is not equivalent to rejecting optimism bias in all decision-making contexts or accepting rationality as universally applicable. At a minimum, our conclusion about optimism bias applies to binge and heavy binge drinking, which imposes important negative consequences on drinkers and others. On the general applicability of the rationality assumption, as McFadden (1999) stated in a review, “Rationality for Economists?”, even by the late 1990s there was a large body of economic literature and even more evidence from other disciplines questioning the validity of the rationality assumption, irrespective of the details of how rationality is defined in operational terms. Scholars have acknowledged that there is heterogeneity among individuals, and the mix of behavioral types may be critical to market outcomes (Fehr-Duda et al. 2010). Even if risk perceptions are accurate, there are other potential forms of irrationality, for example, whether persons consider the utility of all likely states of the world pertinent to a particular decision, and time and risk dimensions of decisions (Zeckhauser and Viscusi 2008; Frederick and Loewenstein 2008), and the extent to which they rely on heuristics (Katsikopoulos and Gigerenzer 2008).
The objective probabilities we used could vary among individuals with particular attributes in ways we are unable to measure, which is a second and more specific limitation. For example, the objective probabilities of conviction, fines, and jail are for each city. There is likely to be variation in the objective probabilities according to personal attributes, which the arrest data from the four states did not allow us to measure. Third, in a minority of outcomes we analyze in this study (survival and liver disease), the SAD measured subjective probabilities crudely, i.e., on a scale of 0-10 rather than on a scale of 0-100. The 0-10 scale converted to probabilities is coarser than one would ideally like. Thus, a 2 can indicate a probability ranging from 0.15 to 0.24. Viscusi and Hakes (2003) questioned the validity of such scales as measures of probabilities. They found that the 0-10 scale used to elicit subjective probabilities does not satisfy all properties associated with probabilities. But Manski and Molinari (2010), who analyzed data from the HRS from which our survival questions are drawn, found that a substantial fraction of persons answered probability questions in multiples of ten. This implies that many people may not be able to give probabilities in more than one significant figure.
In conclusion, based on our findings, optimism bias is not likely to be an important cause of heavy and binge drinking. Focusing on other explanations of such risky behavior is warranted. Risk perceptions are important to study because they underlie decision making. This study adds to the evidence base which implies it is appropriate to move away from optimism bias as a likely causal mechanism underlying potentially harmful personal choices.
Acknowledgements
This research was supported by a grant (R01-AA-017913-03) from the National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism, a part of the National Institutes of Health. This sponsor had no involvement in study design, collection, analysis and interpretation of data, in the writing of the manuscript or in the decision to submit the manuscript for publication.
Appendix
Table 1A. Cognition Questions: Health and Retirement Study and Survey of Alcohol and Driving.
HRS | SAD | |
---|---|---|
1.Date Naming Respondents were asked to report “today’s date,” including the month, day, year, and day of week. |
1.Almost same question asked. Day of week omitted. |
|
2.Object Naming “What do you usually use to cut paper?” “What do you call the kind of prickly plant that grows in the desert?” |
2.Almost same questions asked. People was substituted for you in the “cut paper” question. |
|
Recall | 3.President/Vice President Naming Respondents were asked to name the current President and Vice President of the United States. |
3.Question about President not asked. We also asked respondent to name the current Governor of the state. |
4.Backwards Count starting from 20 and 86. | 4.Only asked for backwards counting from 20. |
|
Serial 7 | The interviewer asked the respondent to subtract 7 from 100, and continue subtracting 7 from each subsequent number for a total of five trials. It was up to the respondent to remember the value from the prior subtraction, such that the interviewer did not repeat the difference said by the respondent after each trial. |
Same questions asked. |
1.“Next I would like to ask you some questions which assess how people use numbers in everyday life. If the chance of getting a disease is 10 percent, how many people out of 1,000 would be expected to get the disease?” |
1.Same question asked. | |
Numeracy | 2.“If 5 people all have the winning numbers in the lottery and the prize is two million dollars, how much will each of them get?” |
2.Same question asked. |
3.“Let’s say you have $200 in a savings account. The account earns ten percent interest per year. How much would you have in the account at the end of two years?” |
3.Almost same question asked. One year was substituted for two. |
|
Memory | 1. Self-rated Memory (present) “How would you rate your memory at the present time?” “Would you say it is excellent, very good, good, fair, or poor?” |
1. Same question asked. |
2. Self-rated Memory (compared to past) “Compared with (previous wave interview month-year/two years ago), would you say your memory is better now, about the same, or worse now than it was then?” |
2. Question not asked. | |
3. Memory was assessed using two word list recall tasks (immediate free-recall and delayed free recall) |
3. Question not asked. |
Table 2A. Relative Likelihood of Causing a Fatal Crash: Drinking vs. Sober Drivers.
Variables | Raleigh (1) |
Hickory (2) |
Philadelphia (3) |
Wilkes-Barre (4) |
Seattle (5) |
Yakima (6) |
Milwaukee (7) |
La Crosse (8) |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Relative two-car fatal crash risk for drinking drivers (θ) |
1.000 | 5.828 | 4.529 | 1.000 | 4.907 | 26.763 | 1.000 | 1.750 |
Relative one-car fatal crash risk for drinking drivers (λ) |
2.934 | 1.878 | 8.110 | 6.080 | 20.602 | 27.763 | 7.917 | 5.554 |
Ratio of drinking to sober drivers on the road (N) |
0.304 | 0.293 | 0.136 | 0.263 | 0.150 | 0.086 | 0.400 | 0.571 |
Degrees of freedom used in estimation |
3 | 3 | 3 | 3 | 3 | 3 | 3 | 3 |
Log likelihood | −3,459 | −1,020 | −5,270 | −2,782 | −2,265 | −1,807 | −1,082 | −8,887 |
Footnotes
For example, Jolls et al. (1998) state: “A common feature of human behavior is overoptimism: People tend to think that bad events are far less likely to happen to them than to others. Thus, most people think that their probability of a bad outcome is far less than others’ probability, although of course this cannot be true for more than half the population.” (p.1524). Korobkin and Ulen (2000) state: “Even when actors know the actual probability distribution of a particular event, their predictions as to the likelihood that that event will happen to them are susceptible to the “overconfidence bias”: the belief that good things are more likely than average to happen to us and bad things are less likely than average to happen to us. Demonstrating that a particular individual is overconfident is difficult to do, because the individual might well differ from the statistically average person in positive ways.” (p. 1091). In our study, we are able to make within sample comparisons, which mitigates the issue addressed in the previous sentence. For studies combining optimism bias with analysis of high levels of alcohol consumption, see Hansen et al. (1991) and Dillard et al. (2009).
A search in Web of Science under the term “optimism bias” yielded 799 results (accessed 10/28/2012).
Further, data from secondary sources for the study cities on some outcomes we analyze in the within sample comparisons are not available (citations for driving over 15 miles per hour above the speed limit and for motor vehicle accidents).
The Lake Wobegon effect is when there is a belief that “my family members and I are better than average.” This is named after a fictional town in Minnesota and is used to represent the natural human tendency to overestimate one’s capabilities. For a critical evaluation of the Lake Wobegon effect, see Kruger (1999).
For a description of the Health and Retirement Study, see http://hrsonline.isr.umich.edu (accessed 10/28/12).
Compared to a mean age of 43.4 for respondents to the SAD.
There are several differences in sample composition between the SAD and HRS. Heavy binge drinkers are over twice as common in the SAD and other drinkers are only half as common in the SAD. The mean CAGE index is over twice as high in the SAD than in the HRS. Forty-six percent of the SAD respondents were married at the time of the survey as compared with 77 percent of the HRS. Mean educational attainment is almost three years higher in the SAD and income over $10,000 higher than HRS. The unemployment rate is five times higher in the SAD than in the HRS, but this difference can be explained by the fact that the HRS is for 1996 and the SAD was conducted in 2010. The fraction of persons out of the labor force is four times higher in the HRS than in the SAD, but this can be explained by the age differences in respondents to the two surveys. Although older on average, HRS respondents had a longer mean financial planning horizon.
Naveau et al. (1997) analyzed data from a cohort study of 1,604 persons with alcoholism and found approximately 20 percent for alcoholic hepatitis prevalence. In Mandayam et al. (2004), 6-41 percent of heavy drinkers developed cirrhosis. Lacey et al. (2009) reported a range of cirrhosis prevalence of 1-5.7 percent in heavy drinkers.
While these results are consistent with past research showing overestimation by smokers of the probability of getting lung cancer (Viscusi 1990) and heart disease (Khwaja et al. 2009), another possibility is that some respondents were thinking about the probability of getting fatty liver conditional on heavy drinking. The objective probability of fatty liver under such circumstances is at least 0.9.
Men’s data are from Watson et al. (1981); women’s data are from United States Department of Transportation (1992).
This overestimate could have occurred because our objective estimates using LP’s method refer to the entire week rather than the weekend in the SAD question.
Washington: Rev. Code Wash. (ARCW) § 46.61.5055; North Carolina: N.C. Gen. Stat. § 20-179; Pennsylvania: 75 Pa.C.S. § 3804; Wisconsin: Wis. Stat. § 346.65.
Other studies reaching this conclusion are Smith et al. (2001), Finkelstein and McGarry (2006), and Fang et al. (2008).
See the quotations in footnote 1.
Another strand of literature refers to systematic overconfidence of one’s own ability. For example, some CEOs may be overconfident about their own managerial ability (on such overconfidence, see e.g., Griffin and Tversky (1992); Sunstein (1997); Klayman et al. (1999); Bénabou and Tirole (2002); DellaVigna and Pollet (2009)).
This issue is discussed by Hurd and McGarry (2002); Manski and Molinari (2010); Bruine de Bruin and Carman (2012).
An alternative to the optimism bias view is that people who engage in risky behaviors are aware of these probabilities. In fact, they learn about the probabilities from direct experiences (Hakes and Viscusi 1997) and from peers who also engage in risky behavior. This is the prevailing view of economists who conduct research on risk perceptions, based for example on smokers’ and drinkers’ perceptions (Viscusi 1990; Lundborg and Lindgren 2002; Lundborg 2007; Khwaja et al. 2007; and Sloan and Platt 2011). This does not eliminate the possibility that specific population subgroups underestimate probabilities of harm from risky behaviors, e.g., young drivers whose risk perceptions become more similar to those of older drivers as they gain driving experience (Jonah 1986; Deery and Fildes 1999). Even if individuals’ risk perceptions are inaccurate, there is an argument that obtaining such information may be costly and the cost will not be incurred for choices irrelevant to the decision maker (Benjamin and Dougan 1997; Benjamin et al. 2001).
We rely on objective estimates using the Levitt and Porter (2001) method above since these estimates are based on objective motor vehicle mortality data rather than subjective beliefs of attorneys and police.
JEL Classifications: I12, D83, D8
References
- Bénabou R, Tirole J. Self-confidence and personal motivation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2002;117(3):871–915. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin DK, Dougan W. Individuals’ estimates of the risks of death: Part I—A reassessment of the previous evidence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1997;15(2):115–133. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin DK, Dougan WR, Buschena D. Individuals’ estimates of the risks of death: Part II—New evidence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2001;22(1):35–57. [Google Scholar]
- Bettman JR, Luce MF, Payne JW. Constructive consumer choice processes. Journal of Consumer Research. 1998;25(3):187–217. [Google Scholar]
- Bruine de Bruin W, Carman KG. Measuring risk perceptions: What does the excessive use of 50% mean? Medical Decision Making. 2012;32(2):232–236. doi: 10.1177/0272989X11404077. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Crimmins EM, Kim JK, Langa KM, Weir DR. Assessment of cognition using surveys and neuropsychological assessment: The health and retirement study and the aging, demographics, and memory study. The Journals of Gerontology Series B: Psychological Sciences and Social Sciences. 2011;66B(suppl 1):i162–i171. doi: 10.1093/geronb/gbr048. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Deery HA, Fildes BN. Young novice driver subtypes: Relationship to high-risk behavior, traffic accident record, and simulator driving performance. Human Factors: The Journal of the Human Factors and Ergonomics Society. 1999;41(4):628–643. doi: 10.1518/001872099779656671. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dejoy DM. An examination of gender differences in traffic accident risk perception. Accident Analysis and Prevention. 1992;24(3):237–246. doi: 10.1016/0001-4575(92)90003-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Del Missier F, Mantyla T, Bruine de Bruin W. Decision-making competence, executive functioning, and general cognitive abilities. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making. 2012;25(4):331–351. [Google Scholar]
- Del Missier F, Mantyla T, Bruine de Bruin W. Executive functions in decision making: An individual differences approach. Thinking & Reasoning. 2010;16(2):69–97. [Google Scholar]
- DellaVigna S, Pollet JM. Investor inattention and Friday earnings announcements. The Journal of Finance. 2009;64(2):709–749. [Google Scholar]
- Dickert S, Kleber J, Peters E, Slovic P. Numeracy as a precursor to pro-social behavior: The impact of numeracy and presentation format on the cognitive mechanisms underlying donation decisions. Judgment and Decision Making. 2011;6(7):638–650. [Google Scholar]
- Dillard AJ, Midboe AM, Klein WMP. The dark side of optimism: Unrealistic optimism about problems with alcohol predicts subsequent negative event experiences. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2009;35(11):1540–1550. doi: 10.1177/0146167209343124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dionne G, Fluet C, Desjardins D. Predicted risk perception and risk-taking behavior: The case of impaired driving. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2007;35(3):237–264. [Google Scholar]
- Dominitz J, Manski CF, Heinz J. Social security expectations and retirement savings decisions. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper Series, No. 8718. 2002 [Google Scholar]
- Fang H, Keane MP, Silverman D. Sources of advantageous selection: Evidence from the medigap insurance market. Journal of Political Economy. 2008;116(2):303–350. [Google Scholar]
- Fehr-Duda H, Bruhin A, Epper T, Schubert R. Rationality on the rise: Why relative risk aversion increases with stake size. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2010;40(2):147–180. [Google Scholar]
- Finkelstein A, McGarry K. Multiple dimensions of private information: Evidence from the long-term care insurance market. American Economic Review. 2006;96(4):938–958. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Frederick S. Cognitive reflection and decision making. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2005;19(4):25–42. [Google Scholar]
- Frederick S, Loewenstein G. Conflicting motives in evaluations of sequences. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2008;37(2/3):221–235. [Google Scholar]
- Gan L, Gong G, Hurd M, McFadden D. Subjective mortality risk and bequests. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper Series, No. 10789. 2004 [Google Scholar]
- Gmel G, Labhart F, Fallu J-S, Kuntsche E. The association between drinking motives and alcohol-related consequences—room for biases and measurement issues? Addiction. 2012;107(9):1580–1589. doi: 10.1111/j.1360-0443.2012.03892.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Griffin D, Tversky A. The weighing of evidence and the determinants of confidence. Cognitive Psychology. 1992;24(3):411–435. [Google Scholar]
- Gul F, Pesendorfer W. Temptation and self-control. Econometrica. 2001;69(6):1403–1435. [Google Scholar]
- Hakes J, Viscusi WK. Mortality risk perceptions: A Bayesian reassessment. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1997;15(2):135–150. doi: 10.1023/a:1007782217912. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hansen WB, Raynor AE, Wolkenstein BH. Perceived personal immunity to the consequences of drinking alcohol: The relationship between behavior and perception. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1991;14(3):205–224. doi: 10.1007/BF00845452. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hudomiet P, Willis RJ. Estimating second order probability beliefs from subjective survival data. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper Series, No. w18258. 2012 doi: 10.1287/deca.2013.0266. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hurd MD, McGarry K. The predictive validity of subjective probabilities of survival. The Economic Journal. 2002;112(482):966–985. [Google Scholar]
- Hurd MD, Rohwedder S. The retirement-consumption puzzle: Anticipated and actual declines in spending at retirement. National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper Series, No. 9586. 2003 [Google Scholar]
- Jolls C, Sunstein CR, Thaler R. A behavioral approach to law and economics. Stanford Law Review. 1998;50(5):1471–1550. [Google Scholar]
- Jonah BA. Accident risk and risk-taking behaviour among young drivers. Accident Analysis & Prevention. 1986;18(4):255–271. doi: 10.1016/0001-4575(86)90041-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Katsikopoulos KV, Gigerenzer G. One-reason decision-making: Modeling violations of expected utility theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2008;37(1):35–56. [Google Scholar]
- Khwaja A, Silverman D, Sloan F, Wang Y. Are mature smokers misinformed? Journal of Health Economics. 2009;28(2):385–397. doi: 10.1016/j.jhealeco.2008.12.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Khwaja A, Sloan F, Chung S. The relationship between individual expectations and behaviors: Mortality expectations and smoking decisions. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2007;35(2):179–201. [Google Scholar]
- Klayman J, Soll JB, González-Vallejo C, Barlas S. Overconfidence: It depends on how, what, and whom you ask. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 1999;79(3):216–247. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1999.2847. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Korobkin RB, Ulen TS. Law and behavioral science: Removing the rationality assumption from law and economics. California Law Review. 2000;88(4):1051–1144. [Google Scholar]
- Kruger J. Lake Wobegon be gone! The ‘below-average effect’ and the egocentric nature of comparative ability judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1999;77(2):221–232. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.77.2.221. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lacey JH, Kelley-Baker T, Furr-Holden D, Voas RB, Romano E, Torres P, Trippetts AS, Ramirez A, Brainard K, Berning A. 2007 National roadside survey of alcohol and drug use by drivers: Alcohol results. National Highway Traffic Safety Administration; 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Lachman M, Spiro A. Critique of cognitive measures in the health and retirement study (HRS) and the asset and health dynamics among the oldest old (AHEAD) study (HRS data monitoring committee report) National Institute on Aging; Bethesda, MD: 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Lancaster T, Chesher A. An econometric analysis of reservation wages. Econometrica. 1983;51(6):1661–1676. [Google Scholar]
- Levitt SD, Porter J. How dangerous are drinking drivers? Journal of Political Economy. 2001;109(6):1198–1237. [Google Scholar]
- Lundborg P. Smoking, information sources, and risk perceptions—new results on Swedish data. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2007;34(3):217–240. [Google Scholar]
- Lundborg P, Lindgren O. Risk perceptions and alcohol consumption among young people. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2002;25(2):165–183. [Google Scholar]
- Mandayam S, Jamal MM, Morgan TR. Epidemiology of alcoholic liver disease. Seminars in Liver Disease. 2004;24(3):217–232. doi: 10.1055/s-2004-832936. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mann RE, Smart RG, Stoduto G, Adlaf EM, Vingilis E, Beirness D, Lamble R, Asbridge M. The effects of drinking-driving laws: A test of the differential deterrence hypothesis. Addiction. 2003;98(11):1531–1536. doi: 10.1046/j.1360-0443.2003.00501.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Manski CF. Measuring expectations. Econometrica. 2004;72(5):1329–1376. [Google Scholar]
- Manski CF, Molinari F. Rounding probabilistic expectations in surveys. Journal of Business & Economic Statistics. 2010;28(2):219–231. doi: 10.1198/jbes.2009.08098. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- McCullough AJ, O’Shea RS, Dasarathy S. Diagnosis and management of alcoholic liver disease. Journal of Digestive Diseases. 2011;12(4):257–262. doi: 10.1111/j.1751-2980.2010.00470.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- McFadden D. Rationality for economists? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1999;19(1-3):73–105. [Google Scholar]
- Mothers Against Drunking Driving [Accessed February 24, 2012];State statistics. 2012 http://www.madd.org/drunk-driving/campaign/state-stats/
- Naveau S, Giraud V, Borotto E, Aubert A, Capron F, Chaput JC. Excess weight risk factor for alcoholic liver disease. Hepatology. 1997;25(1):108–111. doi: 10.1002/hep.510250120. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Ofstedal MB, Fisher GG, Herzog AR. Documentation of cognitive functioning measures in the health and retirement study. University of Michigan; Ann Arbor, MI: 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Peters E, Hart PS, Fraenkel L. Informing patients: The influence of numeracy, framing, and format of side effect information on risk perceptions. Medical Decision Making. 2011;31(3):432–436. doi: 10.1177/0272989X10391672. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Peters E, Västfjäll D, Slovic P, Mertz CK, Mazzocco K, Dickert S. Numeracy and decision making. Psychological Science. 2006;17(5):407–413. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01720.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Plassman BL, Newman TT, Welsh KA, Helms M. Properties of the telephone interview for cognitive status: Application in epidemiological and longitudinal studies. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, & Behavioral Neurology. 1994;7(3):235–241. [Google Scholar]
- Rust J, Phelan C. How social security and medicare affect retirement behavior in a world of incomplete markets. Econometrica. 1997;65(4):781–831. [Google Scholar]
- Sloan F, Platt A. Information, risk perceptions, and smoking choices of youth. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2011;42(2):161–193. [Google Scholar]
- Sloan F, Reilly B, Schenzler C. Effects of tort liability and insurance on heavy drinking and drinking and driving. Journal of Law and Economics. 1995;38(1):49–77. [Google Scholar]
- Smith VK, Taylor DH, Sloan FA. Longevity expectations and death: Can people predict their own demise? American Economic Review. 2001;91(4):1126–1134. [Google Scholar]
- Snowberg E, Wolfers J. Explaining the favorite-longshot bias: Is it risk-love or misperceptions? National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper Series, No. 15923. 2010 [Google Scholar]
- Stephens M. Job loss expectations, realizations, and household consumption behavior. Review of Economics and Statistics. 2004;86(1):253–269. [Google Scholar]
- Sunstein CR. Behavioral analysis of law. The University of Chicago Law Review. 1997:1175–1195. [Google Scholar]
- United States Department of Transportation . Driving under the influence: A report to congress on alcohol limits. National Highway Traffic Safety Administration; Washington, D.C.: 1992. [Google Scholar]
- van der Klaauw W, Wolpin KI. Social security and the retirement and savings behavior of low income households. University of North Carolina-Chapel Hill and University of Pennsylvania; Mimeo: 2005. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Viscusi WK. Do smokers underestimate risks? Journal of Political Economy. 1990;98(6):1253–1269. [Google Scholar]
- Viscusi WK. Smoke-filled rooms: A postmortem on the tobacco deal. University of Chicago Press; Chicago: 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Viscusi WK, Hakes JK. Risk ratings that do not measure probabilities. Journal of Risk Research. 2003;6(1):23–43. [Google Scholar]
- Watson PE, Watson ID, Batt RD. Prediction of blood-alcohol concentrations in human-subjects: updating the Widmark Equation. Journal of Studies on Alcohol. 1981;42(7):547–556. doi: 10.15288/jsa.1981.42.547. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Weinstein ND. Unrealistic optimism about future life events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1980;39(5):806–820. [Google Scholar]
- Weinstein ND. Unrealistic optimism about susceptibility to health problems: Conclusions from a community-wide sample. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1987;10(5):481–500. doi: 10.1007/BF00846146. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Weinstein ND, Klein WM. Resistance of personal risk perceptions to debiasing interventions. Health Psychology. 1995;14(2):132–140. doi: 10.1037//0278-6133.14.2.132. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Zeckhauser RJ, Viscusi WK. Discounting dilemmas: Editors’ introduction. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 2008;37(2/3):95–106. [Google Scholar]