Skip to main content
Global Advances in Health and Medicine logoLink to Global Advances in Health and Medicine
. 2013 Mar 1;2(2):64–75. doi: 10.7453/gahmj.2012.061

In Support of Clinical Case Reports: A System of Causality Assessment

作为临床病例报告的支持:因果关系评估体系

En apoyo de los informes de casos clínicos: sistema de evaluación de la causalidad

Helmut Kiene 1,, Harald J Hamre 2, Gunver S Kienle 3
PMCID: PMC3833527  PMID: 24416665

Abstract

The usefulness of clinical research depends on an assessment of causality. This assessment determines what constitutes clinical evidence. Case reports are an example of evidence that is frequently overlooked because it is believed they cannot address causal links between treatment and outcomes. This may be a mistake. Clarity on the topic of causality and its assessment will be of benefit for researchers and clinicians.

This article outlines an overall system of causality and causality assessment. The system proposed involves two dimensions: horizontal and vertical; each of these dimensions consists of three different types of causality and three corresponding types of causality assessment. Included in this system are diverse forms of case causality illustrated with examples from everyday life and clinical medicine. Assessing case causality can complement conventional clinical research in an era of personalized medicine.

Key Words: Case reports, case causality, causality assessment, causality system, evidence-based medicine, cognition-based medicine, expanded evidence, review

INTRODUCTION

The clinical case report has been a major driver in the advancement of medical therapy. In 2008, for instance, the publication of a few case reports revolutionized treatment for severe hemangioma in infants.1 In many medical areas, such as pediatric surgery, case reports constitute large portions of the body of evidence.2 In the field of medicine as a whole, the number of MEDLINE-listed case reports substantially exceeds the number of published clinical studies (unpublished observation). Even so, case reports have an ambivalent reputation. While appreciated as “cornerstones of medical progress,”3 they are also disregarded as the “least publishable piece of medical literature”4 and range around the lowest levels of the modern medical evidence hierarchy.5 Although when done well they can be convincing and valuable to the practitioner, they are dubious to the methodologist because it is unclear how the causal relation between treatment and outcome should be assessed in single cases.

The topic of causality poses difficulties in epistemology. Causality was the source of major conflicts: Aristotle broke with Plato over causality more than 2000 years ago.6 It was again about the causality issue when David Hume, in the 18th century, challenged the rationality of all empirical science.7 Three decades later, Immanuel Kant proclaimed the necessity of renewing human thinking, again starting out with the causality debate.8 And the advent of modern physics made even Kant's endeavor appear to have been in vain.9 Bertrand Russell, finally, wanted to strike the word causality from the philosophical vocabulary because he was convinced there could be no such thing.10 Similarly, Ludwig Wittgenstein claimed the belief in causality to be superstition.11

Causality-negating verdicts, however, do not mean much in everyday life. When a car breaks down and is taken to a garage, the driver is concerned about the cause of the breakdown and wants a causal repair. Likewise, when a form of medical therapy is being applied, a crucial question is whether it improves or heals the disease or symptom, ie, whether it yields therapeutic causality.

There should be little wonder, then, that the causality debate is still alive, perhaps with even more professional input than ever.12-14 Inspirations come from many related fields: determinism15 and probabilism,16 conditionalism17 and counterfactuals,18 universals19 and contexts,20 logic,21 and formalism.13 Recent developments have led to the acknowledgment that there are manifold meanings of causation and causality. As Nancy Cartwright pointed out, “causation” is one word but many things22; there is plurality in causality.23

We wanted to integrate this plurality into an overall system and clarify the position of the clinical case report in that system. With that in mind, we conducted an investigation on two levels.

  • Regarding medicine, we screened 4 years of the former Lancet rubric for case letters, as well as case reports from other journals and from medical textbooks. We also discussed case assessment with many practitioners and analyzed the types of criteria by which the cause-effect relations in individual treatments can be identified.

  • Regarding epistemology, we searched for an overall system that integrates the major forms of causality and their assessment methods. Such a system would eventually provide a basic framework for all clinical research. Within such a framework we could position the methods for single-case causality assessment and the causality criteria on which practitioners implicitly rely in individual therapeutic situations. This article outlines the system of causality and causality assessment, specifically in relation to medical therapy. The different notions of what is causality and how it can be assessed are put into this system.

The system does not reflect considerations and hypotheses about any hidden physical foundation of causality.24 It also does not present an overview of the array of statistical methods of causality assessment25 because statistics does not organize the system and only covers a fraction of it. Accordingly, the cases used to exemplify the different system aspects are examples from everyday life or are taken from medical therapy.

MAJOR PERSPECTIVES IN CAUSALITY: HORIZONTAL AND VERTICAL, GESTALT-LESS AND GESTALT-BASED

One major constituent of the system is gestalt. Gestalt theory was initiated by Christian von Ehrenfels26 and Max Wertheimer.27 “Gestalt” was defined as something that can be recognized independently of the specificity of its parts.28 The gestalt is what makes a figure, process, quality, or context directly recognizable as such. For example, a melody can be recognized independently of the incidental particularities of its tones, regardless of whether they are in high or low pitch, in fast or slow sequence, or from a piano or trumpet. Similarly, a characteristic figure in the visual field can be identified regardless of whether it is in this or that location, large or small, blue or red. Karl Duncker introduced the gestalt concept to the causality debate,29 and Paul Michotte elaborated on it.30 Already the early concepts of causality expounded by Plato and Aristotle had been related to gestalt as idea and form,31-33 but the currently dominant contributions to the methodology of causality assessment are those of Hume, John Stuart Mill, and Ronald Fisher, none of which relate to any aspect of gestalt.7,34,35 As shown in what follows, both gestalt-based and gestalt-less causalities, and their assessment methods are relevant parts of the causality system.

The second major perspective of causality involves its horizontal and vertical dimensions (Figure 1). Horizontal causality is currently the dominant concept. It refers to a relation in which A (the cause) temporally precedes B (the effect) and thereby somehow causes it. The second concept we call vertical causality. It is currently rather neglected. It refers to the cause of a horizontal A-B causality. In other words: What makes A cause B? What causes the A-B causality? This question obviously does not aim at a cause that temporally precedes the A-B succession but at a cause that exists in another dimension, simultaneous with the A-B succession. This cause we call the meta-cause, or vertical cause, of the horizontal A-B-causality.

graphic file with name gahmj.2012.061.g001.jpg

Figure 1 Two dimensions of causality.

As outlined in the following, the horizontal and vertical dimensions each contain three types of causality and three types of causality assessment.

HORIZONTAL CAUSALITY

The concept of horizontal causality can be unfolded by three basic questions. First, do cause and effect belong together as a unity, or are they separate? According to Kant, they form a unity in which the effect comes through the cause and follows out of it.36 However, Hume's and John Locke's descriptions make cause and effect appear to be two separate things.7,37 Second, if they are not one unity, is the gestalt of the cause equal to the gestalt of the effect? Yes, according to Leibniz, “causa aequat effectum.”38 However, according to Walch, D'Alembert, and Gatterer, such equality is not a necessity.39-41 Third, if they do not form a unit and are not necessarily similar, do cause and effect form a one-to-one relationship? According to Hume's model of constant cause-effect relations, one must assume one-to-one connections.7 However, according to Thomas Hobbes, a cause is constituted by the sum of accidentals that together produce the occurrence of the effect,42 and Leibniz even wrote (in seeming contradiction to his dictum of similarity) that an effect would be brought forth when not only two or 10 or 100 or 1000 but an infinite number of things work together.38 This is most definitely not a one-to-one relation of cause and effect. Modern approaches speak of multicausality, of interactions among causes, of “acting in concert.”43

These positions seem to be rather contradictory, but none of them must necessarily be false. Indeed, all of these cause-effect relationships can occur, depending on the appearance or non-appearance of gestalt factors. There are the three major types of horizontal causality, and thus three assessment methods (Figure 2).

graphic file with name gahmj.2012.061.g002.jpg

Figure 2 Three types of horizontal causality.

Type 1 Horizontal Causality: Cause and Effect Appear as a Unity

The wetness of the rain becomes the wetness of the street. In this example, taken from Duncker,29 the rain causes the wetness of the street: first the water is in the air (A, preceding), then it is on the street (B, following); from A to B there is an observable process, an evolvement (the falling of the water drops). The evolvement is the heart of this kind of causation. It embraces A and B, which are parts of it; it forms a bridge between the two.

The cause—the rain—obviously does not only consist of the preceding A, the water in the air, but also of the evolvement process, the falling of the rain water. Without this process, the preceding A (the water in the air) could not cause the following B (the water on the street). To understand this kind of causality, not only must events A and B be taken into account but perhaps even more importantly the process that stretches from A to B and connects the two. Wesley Salmon highlighted the importance of that process: “One of the fundamental changes which I propose in approaching causality is to take processes rather than events as basic entities.”44 Events would only be secondary entities, produced by interactions or furcations of the processes.

Still, looking at the process alone is not enough. In the rain example, the cause is constituted by both the preceding event, or state, and the evolvement process. Only the integration of these two components constitutes the cause. Also important is that the rain process has a gestalt that makes it recognizable as such, regardless of whether the rain occurs over a short or long period, over a large or small territory, and whether the raindrops are big or small, or more or less densely aggregated. What matters is the whole gestalt of the rain, and it is precisely this gestalt that allows the recognition of the rain as the cause of the street's wetness.

These two aspects—the process and its gestalt—need to be emphasized. That is why we call this kind of causation a causal gestalt process, or type 1 horizontal causality (Figure 2).

The method of identifying the rain as the cause of the street's wetness is rather simple. It does not require an experiment; plain observation is sufficient. What is necessary, however, is the observer's mental capacity to recognize the gestalt of the rain process. For an adult, this is not difficult. He or she can easily comprehend that the water is first in the air and then on the street and that there is an evolvement from the first situation to the second. However, a small child might not as easily comprehend this overall context.

The observational assessment of a causal gestalt process is a type 1 horizontal causality assessment. It can be relevant also when evaluating therapy, and examples are given in Box 1.

Box 1: Type 1 of Therapeutic Causality Assessment: Examples for Causal Gestalt Processes

Similar to the rain example on this page, there can be causal gestalt processes in therapeutic situations.

  • The implantation of a prosthesis (=cause) turns into the new wall of a ruptured aorta and thus prevents further extravazation (=therapeutic effect).

  • Endotracheal intubation, arterial stent insertion, or urethral catheterization, etc, creates an artificial lumen (=cause) that allows a normal passage of air, blood, or urine (=therapeutic effect).

Type 2 Horizontal Causality: Cause and Effect Appear Separate but With Gestalt Correspondence

The rhythm of finger movements becomes the rhythm of percussion sounds. In this example, also taken from Duncker,29 it is the movement of the fingers that causes the sounds. The finger movements (A) are the cause, and the sounds (B) are the effect. In this case, the causality is obvious because of the similarity (or equality) between the finger movements and the knocking sounds; there is a gestalt correspondence.

Consider another example. When a computer mouse is intentionally moved in a lemniscate (A) and the screen cursor also moves in a lemniscate (B), the mouse movement can be identified as the cause and the cursor movement as its effect. Again, the cause-effect relation can be immediately and easily recognized because of the gestalt correspondence between A and B.

In these examples, there is no plainly observable evolvement from A to B (from movement to sound, from mouse to cursor), but rather a correspondence between the gestalt of A and B: a causal gestalt correspondence. This is type 2 horizontal causality (Figure 2).

To identify such a correspondence as a causal relation, mere observation is insufficient. The researcher's active intervention is needed. As the researcher can know with certainty that he is causative in his own intentional actions and that he himself is thus causing the finger movements and the movement of the computer mouse, the following is a valid method of causality assessment. If the researcher intentionally creates A through his own action and if there is a gestalt correspondence between A and B, there can be certainty that the A-B relation is a causal relation. Both elements are needed: without the researcher's intentional causation, A and B and their correspondence could be affected by a third factor, a hidden cause, and without the gestalt correspondence, any change of B, even when following A, could come about by mere chance. When these two elements—the researcher's causation activity and the gestalt correspondence—are interconnected, one can be certain about the causality. This is type 2 causality assessment.

Notably, some gestalt correspondences can be described as mathematical laws: for example, a researcher actively induces an increase in the temperature of a gas (A), and that increase is associated with a proportional rise of gas pressure (B). In this situation, A can be recognized as the cause of B. This proportional or mathematical relation is a special sort of gestalt correspondence, often called mathematical functionality. Ernst Mach suggested substituting the concept of causality with the concept of functionality,45 but it cannot be a full substitute because it is only a part of type 2 causality assessment.

Type 2 assessment is also relevant for therapeutic evaluation. In the examples given in Box 2, the researcher's (the physician's) intentional activity is the treating of the patient, and the gestalt correspondences appear between the gestalt of the treatment course and the gestalt of the symptom course.

Box 2: Type 2 of Therapeutic Causality Assessment: Criteria and Examples for Causal Gestalt Correspondences

Similar to the everyday examples presented in the text, there can be causal gestalt correspondences in therapeutic situations between treatment patterns and patterns of symptom improvement. All of the following kinds of correspondence are criteria for therapeutic causality.

Weak criterion

  • Time-correspondence: Uncontrollable postpartum bleeding due to placenta accreta ceases immediately after vasopressin infiltration.46 (Time correspondence alone, though reasonably hinting at causality, is a weak criterion. Synchronic factors can be confounders and need extra control.)

Strong criteria

  • Time-pattern-correspondence: Hiccup present for 8 days stops on day 8 exactly when the patient smokes marijuana, recurs on day 9, and again disappears (persistently) on day 10 right after the patient smokes marijuana once more.47 Time-pattern correspondence is the basis of the traditional N-of-1 studies.48,49

  • Space-pattern-correspondence: Twenty-four hours after intracutaneous injections of botulinum toxin at 10 sites on a chronically hyperhidrotic palm, corresponding anhidrotic areas develop around the sites, finally flowing together and thus creating a persistent total anhidrosis.50 This is a correspondence between the space patterns of the treatment and the improvement.

  • Morphological correspondence: Conduction anesthesia creates an anesthetized area corresponding to the innervation area of a blocked nerve. Further correspondences exist when external fibers of the nerve, which are proximally innervating, are blocked and when the onset of anesthesia starts proximally, spreading to distant areas only later on.51

  • Dose-effect-correspondence: Catatonia ratings in a woman with schizoaffective disorder improve in inverse correspondence with zolpidem plasma concentrations.52

  • Dialogual correspondence: A 5-year-old autistic boy who has never spoken a word and only screamed chaotically his whole life receives Nordoff-Robbins interactive music therapy. Musical elements are presented by the piano therapist. The boy mimics them; he also mimics sung words and thus develops a growing vocabulary corresponding to those words. In this case, one can even hear the causality.53

  • Parallel-test-result-correspondence: A woman, bitten by a swan, presents an infected, swollen and deeply blue finger. After unsuccessful treatment with oral cephradine, a wound swab culture demonstrates Pseudomonas aeruginosa resistant to cephradine but sensitive to ciprofloxacin. The treatment is changed to ciprofloxacin, and the finger rapidly heals, corresponding to the tested sensitivity.54

  • Complex-prediction-and-observation correspondence: Chronic anal fissures with sustained internal sphincter hypertonia55 and subsequent reduced perfusion of the posterior midline anoderm56 are interpreted as ischemic ulcers.57 External application of isosorbide dinitrate is thus expected to induce a sequential process: first, a reduction of internal sphincter pressure; second, an increased perfusion; third, a reduction of fissure-related pain; and fourth, a healing of the fissure. Corresponding to the expected sequence, this healing sequence is observed.58

Type 3 Horizontal Causality: Cause and Effect Appear Separate and Without Gestalt Correspondence

When cause and effect are connected by neither a gestalt process nor a gestalt correspondence, one is dealing with gestalt-less causality (Figure 3).

graphic file with name gahmj.2012.061.g003.jpg

Figure 3 Three types of vertical causality.

The lack of gestalt relation makes a direct approach to this kind of causality impossible. However, an indirect approach has been developed. A pure chance constellation—the exact opposite of causality—can be constructed by using a multitude of study objects and randomly allocating them to a treatment or to a control group and only treating the treatment group with the test procedure while not treating or differently treating the other group. In other words, one conducts a randomized controlled trial (RCT).35 If under these randomized conditions the groups' outcomes differ more than would plausibly happen through mere chance alone (the demarcation line is usually drawn at the probability value of .05), one will indeed have assessed a causal relation between the treatment and the outcome difference. This causal result is called statistically significant when P< .05. One can speak here of a causal probabilistic correlation.

In a causal probabilistic correlation, the occurrence of A raises the probability of the occurrence of B.59 The A can be called a probabilistic cause and the B a probabilistic effect. For such probabilistic causality, the terminology often is changed from speaking of “causes” to talking of “conditions” or “conditional factors.” For further comments, see Box 3.

Box 3: Terminological Comments: “Causes” and “Conditions”

For probabilistic causality, the terminology often is changed from speaking of “causes” to talking of “conditions” or “conditional factors.” Contextual conditions, however, are also of relevance for non-probabilistic causalities. For example, rain can cause the wetness of the street only when the air temperature is high enough that for the rain not to freeze and turn to hail. On the other extreme, the rain can only wet the street when the street's temperature is low enough so that the water does not immediately evaporate. Similarly, finger movements can cause percussion sounds only when an environment of air allows for the origination and transmission of sound. Such conditions are necessary for the respective causality to occur. Still, in these examples, the causes in question can be clearly identified through the gestalt relations: through the process of the raining water (first in the air and then on the street) or through the correspondence of the rhythm (primarily in the fingers and secondarily in the sound). A different situation arises when there is no gestalt relation between cause and effect and thus the cause in question is not pre-eminently designated above all the other conditional factors. In such a situation, one may as well refrain from the word “cause” and, as in epidemiology, talk of “conditional factors,” “impact factors,” “effect-modifiers,” “confounders,” etc.60

Among conditional factors, different kinds can be discerned—those that are necessary and those that are unnecessary to produce the occurrence of the effect and those that are sufficient for it and those that are insufficient. To make matters even more complicated, there can be factors that are neither necessary nor sufficient but can still contribute to the effect occur-rence.43 John Mackie analyzed the interrelations of necessary, unnecessary, sufficient, and insufficient factors and arrived at a conclusion that might seem a little confusing: causal factors can be an insufficient but necessary part of a condition that is in itself unnecessary but sufficient for the result. This situation has been called an INUS condition.17

Notably, the conduct of an RCT requires more intentional activity than the assessment of type 2 causality. In an RCT, the researcher (or the team) is active not only in regard to the cause, ie, conducting the patient treatment, but is also active in regard to the effect, ie, actively controlling the pure chance conditions for the effect observation. Thus, an RCT includes causation activity and control activity. Accordingly, the RCT constitutes type 3 causality assessment. For a deeper understanding, it is helpful to see how the RCT design incorporates four major methodological paradigms. Box 4 describes these paradigms as well as the difference between the RCT and other type 3 assessment methods.

Box 4: Methodical Paradigms Within the Randomized Controlled Trial

The randomized controlled trial (RCT) incorporates four methodological paradigms, formulated during the past four centuries.

17th century. Experimentation was posited as the basis of all reliable empirical research by Francis Bacon in his famous Novum Organon Scientiarum.66 (For the specific assessment of causality, John Locke37 claimed that experimentation was mandatory). Experimentation goes beyond mere observation and involves actively influencing and manipulating the investigated object. Still, manipulation alone does not guarantee a valid assessment of (type 3) causality without the following methodical elements.

18th century. Repeated succession (association, conjunction) is a further methodical key. David Hume drew attention to it when he figured that one only observes space relations, time relations, and correlated associations. The reasons for such associations are not accessible. Hume thus called A a “cause” and B an “effect” when, neighboring in space and time, any repetition of A is always followed by B: “We may define a cause to be an object, followed by another, and where all the objects similar to the first [A] are followed by objects similar to the second [B]”.7 This seminal definition led to the famous problem of induction,67 but even without that problem, the mere association of A and B does not suffice for causality. For example, when every morning, just after Mr Smith leaves his house, the hour hand on his watch moves to the 8 o'clock position, it is not his step out the door that causes the clock's hand to move. Nicolas Malebranche called it a dangerous fallacy to conclude from associations,68 and modern epidemiology sees it as trivial common sense: associations do not guarantee causality.69

19th century. Comparison is the next methodological key, prominently established by John Stuart Mill.34 Mill turned his attention to complex settings in which various preceding factors are followed by various outcomes and when the question arises of how to identify that a preceding factor is indeed a cause of a certain outcome and, vice versa, how to identify an outcome as indeed an effect of a certain preceding factor. Different from Hume, Mill focused not only on succession but also on comparison, introducing two assessment methods: the method of agreement and the method of difference (and their sub-specifications: the methods of residues and variation). Mill talks about agreement when out of several factorial sets all contain a factor A and they all are followed by the same outcome B. In contrast, he talks about difference when out of several sets only one contains factor A and only that set is followed by outcome B or vice versa, when only one set contains a certain outcome B, which is the sole outcome preceded by factor A. However, Mill himself criticized these methods. He pointed out that only the method of difference could offer certainty and only for the identification of effects and not causes. Even then, Mill did not clarify what amount of repetition and what degree of comparativeness is needed for the method of difference to be reliable.

20th century. Randomization was the final element, introduced by R. A. Fisher when conceiving the randomized controlled trial (RCT) in 1935.35 The RCT includes all three aforementioned elements: experimentation, as the study objects are intentionally manipulated; repeated succession, as the study contains not only a singular object but a group of objects; and comparison, as the study contains both a treatment and a control group and only the treatment group receives the test treatment. In addition to these three elements, the RCT includes an allocation of the study objects to a treatment or a control group by a pure chance procedure, by randomization. With the RCT, Fisher followed the tradition of Bacon, Hume, and Mill but spun it in a new direction. Whereas the tradition of its predecessors was pure empiricism, the RCT implements mathematics; whereas Hume and Mill looked for criteria of direct causality assessment (and either totally or partially failed), the RCT uses an indirect criterion, contrasting causality with a mathematical model of anti-causality against pure chance. A remarkable particularity of the RCT lies in the fact that it assesses causality by determining the quantitative difference of the group outcomes. As a consequence, assessing the causality in an RCT also involves assessing the superiority of the group 1 vs group 2 outcome. In an RCT, assessing causality and assessing superiority are the same.

Other epidemiological approaches to causality also employ experimentation (each medical treatment is an experimental action), repeated succession (of treatment and outcome), and comparison (of treatment and control groups). They do not, however, employ randomization but try to compensate for it with methodical elements such as sample restriction, stratification, matching, statistical adjustment, or Bayesian techniques. Still, compared to the RCT design, these approaches suffer from methodological shortcomings, and the RCT is therefore considered the gold standard of therapeutic causality assessment: “The most accurate (or valid) answer to a question of causality.”61 However, it is only the gold standard for type 3 assessment and not for all forms of causality assessment. When the full causality system is taken into consideration, the gold status of the RCT is relative.

Notably, all epidemiological approaches to causality apply cohort comparison.43,70-77 Even so-called N-of-1 studies compare cohorts, not of patients but of treatment phases.48,49

A curiosity in this context is the well-known list of epidemiological causality criteria published by Austin B. Hill78 who, after World War II, conducted the first widely renowned RCT in medicine; from this list neither any single criterion nor their sum total is specific for causality.

The RCT is generally considered the gold standard for therapeutic causality assessment: the “most accurate (or valid) answer to a question of causality.”61 This view, however, is not correct. The RCT is the gold standard for only type 3 causality assessment.

The System of horizontal causality and Its assessment

From type 1 to type 3 of horizontal causality, there is an increasing loss of the observable connection between cause and effect (Figure 2), moving from unity to gestalt correspondence and finally to no gestalt relation whatsoever. This increasing separation makes it increasingly difficult to achieve a reliable assessment of the causality, necessitating a parallel increase of experimental activity: Type 1 assessment is free of experimental activity, type 2 assessment requires causation activity and type 3 assessment requires causation plus control activity. The type 1 assessment is no experiment; the type 2 assessment is a gestalt-based experiment; and the type 3 assessment is a statistic-based experiment, ie, an RCT.

Notably, assessments of type 2 and 3 causality, but not of type 1, comply with the interventionist positions of Scheler, Dingler, and Wright, who claimed that for a causal relation to be comprehensible, one needs to reconstruct it in the context of experimental activity.62 On the other hand, assessments of type 1 and 2, but not of type 3, comply with the possibilities of single-case situations. Duncker, Michotte, and Ducasse already described possibilities of individualized causality assess ment.19,30,65 Yet because of the dominance of the RCT-oriented methodological tradition (Box 4), it is necessary to emphasize that neither repeated observation nor parallel comparison are indispensable general elements of causality assessment. This is also true in therapy. Here, too, single-case assessments are a realistic perspective (Boxes 1 and 2). An expansion of the concept of evidence is accordingly necessary and needs to be explicitly established in modern evidence-based medicine.

Apart from determining how to assess a cause-effect relation, questions arise about possible repetitions and about the generalizability of type 1, 2, and 3 assessments. Before these further questions can be answered, the dimension of vertical causality must be considered.

VERTICAL CAUSALITY

While horizontal causality focuses on the temporally preceding cause (A) and its effect (B), vertical causality establishes the cause of A-B causality. This shift is particularly relevant when A and B appear to be separate: what makes A cause B, or what causes the A-B causality? These questions address a metacause, or a vertical cause, of the horizontal A-B causality (Figure 3). The metacause can be defined as the instance that makes A and B follow each other, and which, once known, makes it possible to precisely infer from the cause (A) the effect (B).

The vertical dimension has largely been overlooked in the modern discourse on causality. Hume, the central reference figure in that discourse, assumed it impossible to assess the reason, or meta-cause, of a causal relation.7 This assumption has had a great impact for centuries but is unfounded. As shown in the following, three types of vertical causality exist, with three corresponding types of assessment.

Only when the horizontal cause (A) and the vertical cause (the metacause that connects A and B) are taken together, can one talk of the whole cause, and full reason, of an effect. “Causa, seu ratio,” wrote Baruch Spinoza.79

Type 1 Vertical Causality: Metacause Is Inherent in the Unity of Cause and Effect

Type 1 vertical causality is identical to type 1 horizontal causality: it is the causal gestalt process illustrated by the rain example. Why is the cause (the rain) followed by the effect (the wetness of the street)?

There is a simple reason for the cause (the rain) being followed by the effect (the street's wetness): it is the process of the rain itself. The reason, the metacause, is fully inherent in the causal gestalt process of the rain, and the process is self-explanatory in regard to the causality involved. Thus, not only can the horizontal cause-effect relation be plainly observed in such a causal gestalt process but also its inherent metacause.

As previously mentioned, this kind of causality assessment is also relevant for medical therapeutic evaluation, and examples are presented in Box 1.

Type 2 Vertical Causality: Two-component Metacause Bridges Cause and Effect

When evolvement from the cause to the effect is not plainly observable, another type of metacause can often still be assessed: the type 2 vertical causality. This kind of causality is surrounded by many misconceptions and misunderstandings, and these are determining the key problems in the philosophy of science.

Particularly problematic was Hume's premise that it would never be possible to know the reason why a cause (A) is followed by its effect (B). As a consequence, Hume's only chance of assessing causality was to take a constant association of A and B as the criterion with which to identify a cause-effect relation: “We may define a cause to be an object, followed by another, and where all the objects similar to the first [A] are followed by objects similar to the second [B].”7 This definition became a highly influential directive, and it was the Humean notion of causality that Russell attacked at the beginning of the 20th century. Russell disqualified it as an ontological disaster. He further emphasized that the advanced empirical sciences do not at all assume the existence of such regularities and do not in the least aim at discovering them; what they search for are formulas, functional relations. Russell thus wanted to eliminate the word “cause” from philosophy.10

In contrast, Karl Popper enhanced the status of Hume's constant association of A and B and made it the general form of all laws of nature. Popper proclaimed that all laws must be written in the form of all-sentences: “whenever A, then B” or “all A are B.”80 Such laws can, for formal reasons, never be verified, but they can be falsified by single observations. Thus, taking Hume's definition of causality as the general template for the laws of nature, Popper arrived at his famous philosophy of scientific falsificationism.80-82 However, Popper had chosen a sort of “law” that, according to Russell, is nothing the advanced sciences would ever want to discover or even assume to exist. Their laws are not all-sentences but functional relations, mathematical formulas.

These laws, these functional relations or formulas of mathematical gestalt, can indeed be a connective tissue between causes and effects. For example, according to the gas law Inline graphic an increase in the temperature (ΔT) of a gas with constant mass and volume induces a proportional increase in the pressure (ΔT) of this gas: ΔTP. In this case, ΔT is the cause, ΔP is the effect, and the law Inline graphic is what connects the two. Thus, it is the law that enables one to derive that the cause (ΔT) will be followed by the effect (ΔP) and how that will happen. Accordingly, this law can be identified as the metacause of the ΔTP causality or at least as a part of the metacause. The law establishes a bridge between cause and effect.

Russell was correct: the advanced sciences strive to discover laws that are functional relations and not causalities. However, it is precisely these laws that allow the observation of a variety of causal relations that otherwise could not be seen. In particular, these laws allow causality assessment in the single-case situation: If the law, the formula, predicts a causal A-B relation and if the A-B relation is then observed in reality, the observer is right in identifying the concrete relation as causal. Seen from this perspective, the word “cause” should definitely not be dropped from scientific usage.

Taking an even closer look at the gas example, one can see that the metacause has two components. The first component comprises the material factors that constitute the gas: its mass (m), molar mass (M), volume (V), temperature (T), and pressure (P). The second component is the gas law Inline graphic that interconnects these material factors. Notably, the material factors and the law are equivalent to the Aristotelian causa materialis and causa formalis, respectively. In fact, all four components of Aristotle's concept of causality can be seen in the gas example33:

  • the causa efficiens is the initial rise in temperature;

  • the causa materialis comprises the specific constitutive material factors of the gas;

  • the causa formalis is the gas law that interconnects the material factors; and

  • even the causa finalis is present when there is an intentional act of increasing the gas temperature to increase the gas pressure.

From these components, the effect (increasing gas pressure) can be precisely inferred. Accordingly, Aristotle's concept of causality encompassed the total cause. Subtracting from this total cause the causa finalis means subtracting the human intention (which is not always present). Subtracting the causa materialis and the causa formalis means subtracting the metacause. What then is left is the causa effiens, the initial event. It was only this part of the total cause that Hume addressed and called “cause.” This limited view made it impossible to see any connection between “causes” and their effects.

Why and how are the material factors of a gas associated with the gas law, and how can such a mathematically formulated law, such a functional relation, be validated? The answer lies in the following: The identifications and measurements of the individual material factors (pressure, volume, mass, absolute temperature) are already incorporated in simple laws, and the integration of these simple laws eventually constitutes the complex gas law. Accordingly, an integrative, evolutive method of law assessment can be worked out and made operable. This method will be published in a separate article.

To summarize: Knowing a law makes cognitional causality assessment possible, even in single case situations. An example of law-based assessment in medicine is electrolyte substitution steered by formulas and by observable dose-effect relationship.

Knowing metacauses can also facilitate the understanding and assessment of causal complexities.

Such complexities, ie, sequences of linearly connected causal relations, and causal systems, ie, complexes of functionally interconnected causal relations and causal chains. An everyday example is a mechanic repairing a broken-down car. Due to his professional education and mental capacity, he has insight into multiple explanations: why the car's parts were functionally interconnected in their specific way; why the car is now not functioning; and why certain repair actions (A) would lead to a functional restoration (B). It is this insight into the system's working principles that allows an understanding of the A-B relation as a causal relation and thus also allows the prediction that A will be followed by B. Again, as in the gas example, if there is such an insight-based prediction of an A-B succession and if this A-B succession is then concretely observed in a single-case situation, it can be identified as a cause-effect relation.

The certainty comes not from comparing car repairs and non-repairs, not at all from randomization, and not from a gestalt correspondence between the repair actions and the restored function. It comes from knowing the working principles of the system, just as the certainty in the gas example came from knowing the law. Again, single-case causality assessment is possible.

Knowing the working principles of a system also can be relevant for medical therapeutic evaluation. The example in Box 5 is remarkable because it presents highly certain but also highly particular evidence. As in the car repair example, the evidence can only be realized when there is insight into the working principles (the metacause, the reason) of why the treatment eventually leads to the desired outcome. This insight is a necessary presupposition, and without it one would miss the most relevant part of the observation: the therapeutic causality. One is dealing here with cognitional causality assessment—which is not conceived in the evidence hierarchies of today's evidence-based medicine and is not reflected in its methodology.

Box 5: System Assessment in Therapy Evaluation

A 26-year-old man is admitted to a regional hospital with severe chest pain, localized frontal hematoma, raised troponin-T and creatine kinase, and a right bundle branch block.83 After receiving medical treatment, he recovers from the symptoms. Was the treatment effective?

If only the baseline symptoms and outcome are registered (as in conventional clinical trials), there can be no certainty about the therapeutic causality. The situation changes, however, when a full overview is given. The facts are as follows.

The young man has a high-speed snowboard crash. Echocardiography and magnetic resonance imaging show a rupture of the descending aorta, a false aneurysm of the aortic arch, and a contained rupture of the aortic isthmus with an intussusception of the intimal cylinder into the distal aortic segment. The patient develops arterial hypertension in his arms, which can be explained by a compression of the left carotid artery. As neither a median sternotomy nor a lateral thoracotomy alone would allow full exposure of both lesions simultaneously, a two-step therapeutic procedure is chosen. First, the abdominal rupture of the descending aorta is treated with an endovascular stent implantation. Second, 2 days later, a median sternotomy is conducted and the aortic arch is opened. A circumferential intimal tear is sutured, and the aorta is closed with a Vascutek patch. After the surgical procedure, the arterial hypertension in the arms promptly disappears; the patient recovers rapidly and is discharged 1 week after the operations.

With this information, and based on anatomical and physiological systems insight, the expert knows that:

  • The patient's life was highly endangered, and the 2-step intervention successfully saved his life, and

  • Each of the surgical measures (stent implantation, suture of the intimal tear of the aortic arch, and reclosure with a Vascutek patch) was causally effective, and each repaired a defect of the aorta and restored functionality.

The basis for the causality assessment is as follows. The surgeon is able to make an insight-based prediction that there is a good chance the interventions (A) will be followed by a coherent pattern of structural and functional improvements of the organism (B), and he makes achieves an insight-based observation of exactly this A-B succession. The conformance of this kind of prediction and observation allows certainty about the causal relation between A and B—even though the operation is a novelty and conducted only in a single case. System transparency is the key to this kind of therapeutic causality assessment.

Type 3 Vertical Causality: Trans-metacause Bridges Cause and Effect

There is a hierarchy among the different types of vertical causality: a type 1 metacause can itself have a metacause, which is a type 2 metacause; for example, the metacause of the rain process lies in the laws of gravitation, condensation, etc. Similarly, a type 2 meta-cause can have a metacause, which is a type 3 meta-cause. This type 3 metacause is rather different from types 1 and 2. While type 1 is plainly observable and type 2 is assessable with cognitive effort, they still belong to the same level of reality as the horizontal A-B causality. The type 3 metacause, however, comes from outside: from the hidden parts of reality, from deeper or from higher levels (Figure 3). It is a trans-metacause.

Type 3 meta-causes have been designed into molecularistic, atomistic, and sub-atomistic models. For example, the behavior of a gas (and the gas law itself) can be derived from the kinetic gas model. Thus the gas molecules can be considered the trans-metacause behind the macroscopic cause-effect relations in a gas. Even deeper-reaching models explain again the properties of the molecules, models that have been designed for the sub-molecular and sub-atomic level and that make these sub-entities appear to be the vertically underlying cause of molecule properties. Finally, quantum theory comes in, and the sub-models are enclouded in stochastics and indeterminism.84 All of these underlying particularistic meta-causes are of type 3a (Figure 3).

The most classical of all Western thoughts, Plato's concept of the idea is in contrast to the particularistic models.31 Plato considered the idea as that which forms the respective physical reality; not doing this particularistically (as molecular and atomic interactions) but holistically; not coming from a deeper, sub-physical part of reality (as particles do) but from a higher, supra-physical part of reality. This would be the type 3b meta-cause. Similar concepts are used in the diverse schools of vitalism that assume the existence and effectiveness of non-physical and non-chemical forces (entelechia, vis vitalis, nisus formativus, morphogenetic field, etheric force, formative forces, etc), and the more traditional forms of medicine are often conceptually outlined in this respect. The extent to which these concepts are valid is not a matter of concern here.

An important difference between the particularistic and the holistic concepts is the causative direction. Particularistic concepts imply upward causality, ie, the causation comes from the parts of the system. In contrast, holistic concepts imply downward causality; ie, the causation comes from the totality of the system. While the concept of upward causation is immanent in all reductionist thinking, the term downward causation was coined (though not with regard to Platonism and vitalism) in psychobiology by Roger Sperry and in the context of system theory by Donald Campell. It was elaborated by Popper and John Eccles regarding mind-body, and again by James Murphy, Peter Anderson, Anthony Dardis, and others.85-90

If taken radically, upward causality comes from below the macro-physical parts, from particles (molecules, atoms, etc), and downward causality comes from beyond the totality of the respective system, from its own construction process or morphogenesis. The radical concept of downward causality thus even considers the existence of non-physical and non-chemical causes.

Different questions arise: On the one hand, they arise about the status of diverse kinds of particles: whether they exist only under certain experimental or observational conditions or in how far they exist even only as mere model entities.91 On the other hand, questions arise about the existence of non-physical and non-chemical causative instances: whether they exist at all, and if so how they could possibly be assessed. Apart from these difficulties, the radical upward route of causation (from the subatomic level to the atomic, molecular, and cellular levels, to tissues, organs, and organisms) eventually disseminates in indeterminism, and the radical downward causation, currently at least, is not clearly understood. Neither one thus provides a broadly applicable contribution to the possibilities of cognitional causality assessment in single-case situations.

The System of Vertical causality and Its assessment

As with horizontal causality and its assessment, there are three major types of vertical causality. The metacause is increasingly externalized and is differently assessed (Figure 3):

  • the type 1 metacause is fully inherent in the respective A-B succession and can thus be plainly observed;

  • the type 2 metacause also belongs to the A-B succession level but cannot be plainly observed, and its assessment needs cognitional activity; and

  • the type 3 metacause is located at a deeper or higher level of reality, and its assessment requires an even greater surplus of cognitional achievement.

Several of the classic causality concepts can be characterized by how they relate to the system of vertical causality: Hume's concept contains no verticality at all. Aristotle's concept contains the interrelating vertical aspects of causa materialis and causa formalis. The atomist concept adds an extra upward causality. And the Platonist concept adds an extra downward causality.

GENERALIZATION

Inherent in the assessment methods is the potential for generalization, either based on repetition (the power of custom) or insight (the power of reasoning). The repetition of an A-B causality suggests that there will be similar causalities in the future; and insight into the reason for the causality makes it obvious why A will be causally followed by B. Insight thus provides a stronger basis. However, the topic of insight—of cognitional causality assessment—is neglected in the dominant Hume-Popper methodological tradition and has not been sufficiently clarified, neither for RCTs nor for case assessments.

Regarding RCTs, two points must be stated. First, an RCT result does not provide the reason for the causality it assesses. Second, a single RCT is only one causality assessment and does not differ in this respect from a single case assessment. Even with a large number of participants, one RCT represents only one causality assessment. Hence, an RCT result offers no basis for the prediction that such a result will be generated from a similar sample in the future. Generalizability, on the statistical level, would require that the study sample (treatment plus control sample) and the future sample both be randomly selected from the total present and future population of subjects, which can never be realized.92 Still, most RCTs have the potential for generalization, yet it comes not through the RCT itself but through other background research that provides some, though insecure, insight into the reason for the therapeutic causality, ie, into the intervention's working principle. If this insight is then supplied with a claim of general validity, the RCT is an exemplary test. Hence, both are needed: the (insecure) insight into the working principle that is per se general and thus the basis for the generalization, and the confirmative RCT that is per se a singular test and thus an exemplary validation of that basis. Further support for the generalizability of an RCT result can come through its replications.

Take-home messages

  1. Case causality: It is possible to assess therapeutic causality in single-case situations. There exist criteria for case causality.

  2. Case reports: Case reports should explicitly reflect on the case causality.

  3. Causality system: Different types of causality require different assessment methods: cognitional, observational, and experimental; for cohorts and for cases. The system of causality puts the different types and methods into order.

Regarding case assessments, the insight into the working principle is the most relevant. If such insight is present and transparent, it is, by its nature, always a general insight. Hence, it has a tripartite potential: for generalization, for individualization, and for causality identification in the single-case situation. Our example is the snowboard case in Box 5. The surgeons were able to achieve that triple task: Their insight into the patient's injury and into the possibilities of surgical intervention allowed them to generalize how any such patient could be treated, individualize this general perspective to the concrete incoming patient, and identify in this particular patient the concrete succession of treatment and recovery as a causal relation. All three achievements were based on the same capacity for cognitional insight.

An important aspect of insight-based generalization is that it does not imply a machine-like necessity. Confounders may well disrupt the A-B succession, but often those confounders can be cognitively understood. Reflection in action93 can often be realized, and the causative actions can be adapted accordingly; this applies also to medicine.

The possibilities of insight into the working principle and the resulting generalizability depends on the type of horizontal causality involved. In the causal gestalt process, the working principle is openly assessable and generalization is thus easy. In causal gestalt correspondence, insight into the working principle is often easily achieved, and if not, generalizability can be supported by case repetitions. In the causal probabilistic correlation, the insight in the working principle is mostly weak and validation by statistical methods is necessary.

CONCLUSION: THE NEED TO EXPAND THE CONCEPT OF CLINICAL EVIDENCE

The system of causality and its assessment is particularly important for clinical case research because it identifies a variety of methods and criteria for the assessment of case causality. Accordingly, the system suggests expansions of the current concept of medical evidence in regard to the possibilities of assessing causality in individual therapeutic situations. The criteria of causal case assessment can be used in clinical research, upgrading case reports.

Clinical case research will have to be fostered in the future in the same way that clinical trial research is currently promoted. With this goal ahead, more sub-types of causality assessment may need to be differentiated; the methods of assessment further elaborated; semi-standardizations for case research determined; the generalization topic further analyzed; guidelines for the conduct and publication of case studies and case series improved and professionalized; and cross-design syntheses of cohort evidence and case evidence developed. In all of this, the theme of causality will need thorough and critical attention. Case reports may easily induce bias and illusion if the methods and criteria for the assessment of causality are not handled with sufficient care.

The conventional ideal in therapeutic evaluation is to identify the best therapy available—“best” in the sense of comparative cohort studies. RCTs often are optimal for achieving this goal because they simultaneously assess causality and comparative superiority. However, the individual patient does not always need the proven best cohort therapy. Often, the challenge is to find and apply just the right and individually appropriate treatment for the concrete personal situation. This is the task of individualized, personalized medicine. Yet it can hardly be mastered without a methodology that truly supports the assessment of therapeutic causality in the individual case.

The causality system presented here embraces both cohort assessment (eg, RCT) and case assessment and opens a perspective on case causality as an asset complementary to conventional clinical research. This approach has been called cognition-based medicine 94; it can also be considered as expanded evidence. If medicine is to become individualistic, this expansion is a highly urgent undertaking—conceptually, methodologically, and practically.

Contributor Information

Helmut Kiene, Helmut Kiene, Dr med, is director of Institute for Applied Epistemology and Medical Methodology at the University of Witten/Herdecke, Germany..

Harald J. Hamre, Harald J. Hamre, Dr med, is research scientist at the Institute for Applied Epistemology and Medical Methodology at the University of Witten/Herdecke, Germany..

Gunver S. Kienle, Gunver S. Kienle, Dr med, is research scientist at the Institute for Applied Epistemology and Medical Methodology at the University of Witten/Herdecke, Germany..

REFERENCES

  • 1.Léauté-Labrèze C, Dumas de la Roque E, Hubiche T, Boralevi F, Thambo JB, Taïeb A. Propranolol for severe hemangiomas of infancy. N Engl J Med. 2008;358(24):2649–51 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Hardin WD, Jr, Stylianos S, Lally KP. Evidence-based practice in pediatric surgery. J Pediatr Surg. 1999;34(5):908–12 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Vandenbroucke JP. In defense of case reports and case series. Ann Intern Med. 2001;134:330–4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Grimes DA, Schulz KF. Descriptive studies: What they can and cannot do. Lancet. 2002;359(9301):145–9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Oxford Centre for Evidence-based Medicine Levels of evidence. http://www.cebm.net/?o=1025 Accessed October 9, 2012.
  • 6.Ivánka E. Die Polemik gegen Platon im Aufbau der aristotelischen Metaphysik. Scholastik. 1934;9:520–42 [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Hume D. An enquiry concerning human understanding. London; 1758 [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Kant I. Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Riga: Johann Friedrich Hartknoch; 1787 [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Reichenbach H. The philosophical significance of the theory of relativity. In: Albert Einstein: philosopher-scientist. Schilpp PA, editor. Evanston, IL: The Library of Living Philosophers; 1949 [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Russell B. On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series. The Aristotelian Society. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing; 1912:1–26 [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Wittgenstein L. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. New York; London: Harcourt, Brace & Company, Inc; Kegan Paul, Trench, Hubner & Co, Ltd; 1922 [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Sosa E, Tooley M. Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1993 [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Pearl J. 2000. Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2000 [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Cartwright N. Hunting causes and using them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2007 [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Anscombe GEM. Causality and determination. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1971 [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Eells E. Probabilistic causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1991 [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Mackie JL. Causes and conditions. Am Phil Q. 1965;(2/4):245-55–261-64 [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Collins J, Hall N, Paul LA, eds. Causation and counterfactuals. Cambridge, London: MIT Press; 2004 [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Fair D. Causation and universals. London: Routledge Press; 1990 [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Menzies P. Causation in context. In: Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality. Russell's republic revisited. Price H, Corry R, eds. Oxford: Clarendon Press; 2009 [Google Scholar]
  • 21.von Wright GH. On the logic and epistemology of the causal relation. In causation. Sosa E, Tooley M, editors. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2007 [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Cartwright N. Causation: one word, many things. Philosophy of Science. 2004;71(5):805–19 [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Cartwright N. Plurality in causality. In: Hunting causes and using them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2007 [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Price H, Corry R, eds. Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell's republic revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2009 [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Pearl J. Causal inference in statistics: an overview. Stat Surveys. 2009;3:96–146 [Google Scholar]
  • 26.von Ehrenfels C. Über Gestaltqualitäten. Leipzig: Reisland, 1890 [Google Scholar]
  • 27.Wertheimer M. Untersuchungen zur Lehre der Gestalt. Teil 1. Psychologische Forschung 1; 1922 [Google Scholar]
  • 28.Köhler W. Die Aufgabe der Gestaltpsychologie. Berlin, New York: Walter de Gruyter; 1971 [Google Scholar]
  • 29.Duncker K. Zur Pschologie des produktiven Denkens, 1st ed Berlin: Verlag Julius Springer; 1935 [Google Scholar]
  • 30.Michotte A. La perception de la causalité. Institut Supérieure de Philosophie ed. Paris: Louvain; 1946 [Google Scholar]
  • 31.Ross D. Plato's theory of ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1951 [Google Scholar]
  • 32.Aristotle The metaphysics. Lawson-Tancred H, translator. New York: Penguin; 1998 [Google Scholar]
  • 33.Falcon A. Aristotle on causality. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford; 2008 [Google Scholar]
  • 34.Mill JS. A System of logic: ratiocinative and inductive. London; 1843 [Google Scholar]
  • 35.Fisher RA. The design of experiments. Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd; 1935 [Google Scholar]
  • 36.Kant I. Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können [Erste Ausgabe 1783]. Vorländer K, editor. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag; 1976 [Google Scholar]
  • 37.Locke J. An essay concerning human understanding. London; 1690 [Google Scholar]
  • 38.Albrecht M. Ursache/Wirkung III. Neuzeit. In: Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Band 11: U-V. Ritter J, Gründer K, Gabriel G, editors. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft; 2001 [Google Scholar]
  • 39.Walch JG. Philosophisches lexikon. Leipzig: Johann Friedrich Gleditschens seel. Sohn; 1726 [Google Scholar]
  • 40.d'Alembert J. Traité de dynamique. Paris: 1743 [Google Scholar]
  • 41.Gatterer JC. Vom historischen Plan. Halle: Verlag Gebauer; 1767 [Google Scholar]
  • 42.Hobbes T. Elementorum philosophiae sectio prima: De corpore. London; 1655 [Google Scholar]
  • 43.Rothman K, Greenland S. Causation and causal inference in epidemiology. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(Suppl 1):144–50 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 44.Salmon WC. Causality: production and propagation. Proceedings of the 1980 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Irvine, CA: Philosophy of Science Association; 1981 [Google Scholar]
  • 45.Mach E. Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit. Prag: J.G.Calve'sche K.u.K. Univ.-Buchhandl; 1872 [Google Scholar]
  • 46.Lurie S, Appleman Z, Katz Z. Subendometrial vasopressin to control intractable placental bleeding. Lancet 1997;349(9053):698. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47.Gilson I, Busalacchi M. Marijuana for intractable hiccups. Lancet. 1998;351(9098):267. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48.Guyatt G, Sackett D, Taylor DW, Chong J, Roberts R, Pugsley S. Determining optimal therapy—randomized trials in individual patients. N Engl J Med. 1986;314(14):889–92 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 49.Kazdin AE. Single-case research designs: methods for clinical and applied settings. New York: Oxford University Press; 1982 [Google Scholar]
  • 50.Naumann M, Flachenecker P, Bröcker EB, Toyka KV, Reiners K. Botulinum toxin for palmar hyperhidrosis. Lancet. 1997;349(9047):252. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51.Larsen R. Anästhesie. 6 ed.München, Wien, Baltimore: Urban & Schwarzenberg; 1999 [Google Scholar]
  • 52.Thomas P, Rascle C, Mastain B, Maron M, Vaiva G. Test for catatonia with zolpidem. Lancet. 1997;349(9053):702. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53.Nordoff P, Robbins C. Creative music therapy: a guide to fostering clinical musicianship. 2nd ed.Gilsum, NH: Barcelona Publishers; 2007 [Google Scholar]
  • 54.Ebrey RJ, Hayek LJ. Antibiotic prophylaxis after swan bite. Lancet. 1997;350(9074):340. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55.Farouk R, Duthie GS, MacGregor AB, Bartolo DC. Sustained internal sphincter hypertonia in patients with chronic anal fissure. Dis Colon Rectum. 1994;37(5):424–9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56.Schouten WR, Briel JW, Auwerda JJ. Relationship between anal pressure and anodermal blood flow. The vascular pathogenesis of anal fissures. Dis Colon Rectum. 1994;37(7):664–9 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 57.Soybel DI. What causes anal fissure? Gastroenterology. 1996;111(4):1154–5 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 58.Schouten WR, Briel JW, Boerma MO, Auwerda JJ, Wilms EB, Graatsma BH. Pathophysiological aspects and clinical outcome of intra-anal application of isosorbide dinitrate in patients with chronic anal fissure. Gut. 1996;39(3):465–9 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59.Suppes P. Probalistic theory of causality. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company; 1970 [Google Scholar]
  • 60.Miettinen O. Confounding and effect-modification. Am J Epidemiol. 1974;100(5):350–3 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61.Sackett DL, Haynes RB, Guyatt GH. Clinical epidemiology: a basic science for clinical medicine. London: Little, Brown and Co; 1991 [Google Scholar]
  • 62.Scheler M. Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft. Leipzig: Der Neue-Geist Verlag; 1926 [Google Scholar]
  • 63.Dingler H. Die Methode der Physik. München: Verlag Ernst Reinhardt; 1938 [Google Scholar]
  • 64.von Wright GH. Explanation and understanding. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; 1971 [Google Scholar]
  • 65.Ducasse CJ. 1968. Truth, knowledge and causation. Honderich T, ed. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul; 1968 [Google Scholar]
  • 66.Bacon F. Instauratio magna. London: Apud Joannem Billium Typographum Regium; 1620 [Google Scholar]
  • 67.Howson C. Hume's problem: the justification of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2000 [Google Scholar]
  • 68.de Malebranche N. Da la recherche de la vérité. Paris; 1674 [Google Scholar]
  • 69.Petitti DB. Associations are not effects. [Editorial]. Am J Epidemiol. 1991;133(2):101–2 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 70.Susser M. Causal thinking in the health sciences. Concepts and strategies of epidemiology. New York: Oxford University Press; 1973 [Google Scholar]
  • 71.Susser M. Judgment and causal inference: criteria in epidemiologic studies. Am J Epidemiol. 1977;105(1):1–15 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 72.Holland PW. Statistics and causal inference. J Am Stat Assoc. 1986;81(396):945–60 [Google Scholar]
  • 73.Rosenbaum PR, Rubin DB. The central role of the propensity score in observational studies for causal effects. Biometrika. 1983;70(1):41–55 [Google Scholar]
  • 74.Reiter J. Using statistics to determine causal relationship. Am Math Mon. 2000;107(1):24–32 [Google Scholar]
  • 75.Pearl J. Causal inference in the health sciences: a conceptual introduction. Health Services & Outcomes Research Methodology. 2001;2:189–220 [Google Scholar]
  • 76.Greenland S. An overview of methods for causal inference from observational studies. In: Applied Bayesian modeling and causal inference from incomplete-data perspectives. Gelman A, Meng XL, editors. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons; 2004 [Google Scholar]
  • 77.D'Agostino R, Jr, D'Agostino R., Sr Estimating treatment effects using observational data. JAMA. 2012;297(3):314–16 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 78.Hill AB. The environment and disease: Association or causation? Proc R Soc Med. 1965May;58:295–300 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 79.Spinoza B. Ethica: ordine geometrico demonstrate. 1677 [Google Scholar]
  • 80.Popper K. Logik der Forschung. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck; 1934 [Google Scholar]
  • 81.Popper K. Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. New York: Basic Books; 1963 [Google Scholar]
  • 82.Popper K. objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1972 [Google Scholar]
  • 83.Carrel T, Do DD, Müller M, Triller J, Mahler F, Althaus U. Combined endovascular and surgical treatment of complex traumatic lesions of thoracic aorta. Lancet. 1997;350(9085):1146. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 84.Bunge M. Causality: the place of the causal principle in modern science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1958 [Google Scholar]
  • 85.Sperry R. Problems outstanding in the evolution of brain function. New York: American Museum of Natural History; 1964 [Google Scholar]
  • 86.Campbell DT. “Downward causation” in hierarchically organised biological systems. In: Studies in the philosophy of biology: Reduction and related problems. Ayala FJ, Dobzhansky T, editors. London/Bastingstoke: Macmillan; 1974 [Google Scholar]
  • 87.Popper K, Eccles J. The self and its brain: an argument for interactionism. Berlin: Springer; 1985 [Google Scholar]
  • 88.Murphy JB. The kinds of order in society. In: natural images in economic thought: markets read in tooth and claw. Mirowski P, editor. New York: Cambridge University Press; 1994 [Google Scholar]
  • 89.Andersen EA, Christiansen PV, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO. Downward causation: minds, bodies and matter. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press; 2001 [Google Scholar]
  • 90.Dardis A. Mental causation: the mind-body problem. New York: Columbia University Press; 2008 [Google Scholar]
  • 91.Agazzi E, editor. The problem of reductionism in science. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers; 1991 [Google Scholar]
  • 92.Feinstein AR. Clinical biostatistics. St Louis: Mosby; 1977 [Google Scholar]
  • 93.Schön DA. The reflective practitioner. How professionals think in action. New York: Basic Books; 1983 [Google Scholar]
  • 94.Kiene H. Komplementäre Methodenlehre der klinischen Forschung. New York: Springer; 2001 [Google Scholar]

Articles from Global Advances in Health and Medicine are provided here courtesy of SAGE Publications

RESOURCES