Knocking out the Grb10 imprinted gene in a mother compensates for the loss of the same gene in her offspring. Is this evidence of a role for coadaptation in the evolution of imprinting?
Abstract
Mammalian development involves significant interactions between offspring and mother. But is this interaction a carefully coordinated effort by two individuals with a common goal—offspring survival? Or is it an evolutionary battleground (a central idea in our understanding of reproduction). The conflict between parents and offspring extends to an offspring's genes, where paternally inherited genes favor demanding more from the mother, while maternally inherited genes favor restraint. This “intragenomic conflict” (among genes within a genome) is the dominant evolutionary explanation for “genomic imprinting.” But a new study in PLOS Biology provides support for a different perspective: that imprinting might facilitate coordination between mother and offspring. According to this “coadaptation theory,” paternally inherited genes might be inactivated because maternally inherited genes are adapted to function harmoniously with the mother. As discussed in this article, the growth effects associated with the imprinted gene Grb10 are consistent with this idea, but it remains to be seen just how general the pattern is.
Genomic Imprinting
As diploid organisms, we humans inherit two copies of most of our genes, one from our mother and one from our father. Those two alleles might be the same or different, but in general, it does not matter which allele came from which parent. But, for a small fraction of our genes (∼1% in mammals), it does matter which allele came from which parent. These genes are subject to genomic imprinting, an epigenetic phenomenon in which the pattern of expression depends on an allele's parental origin. Genomic imprinting results from differential epigenetic modifications (such as DNA methylation and histone modifications) established separately in the maternal and paternal germ lines during oogenesis and spermatogenesis, respectively. After fertilization, the genome undergoes large-scale epigenetic reprogramming; the differences that survive can be propagated across cell divisions throughout development. The result is that the genome in each cell contains certain loci where the two alleles are in different epigenetic states, and therefore interact differently with the transcriptional and regulatory machinery.
In the simplest cases, one imprinted allele is expressed, while the other is silent, but many imprinted loci exhibit more complex expression patterns. Some, like the Gnas locus [1], encode multiple gene products, including splice variants transcribed from different promoters, each with a different pattern of imprinting. At others, silencing of a protein-coding transcript results in cis from the production of an anti-sense, non-coding RNA transcript, which may be processed into various small RNA products, such as microRNAs and snoRNAs (e.g., the Ube3a-ATS transcript, which regulates genes associated with Angelman and Prader-Willi Syndromes [2]). Some loci show tissue-specific imprinting, with monoallelic expression in some cell types, and biallelic expression in others. And, of course, some imprinted loci combine all of the above.
More, and More Varied, Imprinted Genes
Over the past two decades, more than 100 imprinted genes have been identified in mice, and over 50 in humans. Many imprinted genes affect early growth and development in ways that are consistent with the predictions of the Kinship Theory of Imprinting (see Box 1), but it is increasingly clear that imprinted genes have systematic effects on other phenotypes. For example, imprinted genes affect various aspects of metabolism [3], extending into adulthood, and many imprinted genes are expressed in the central nervous system (CNS), with major effects on cognition and behavior [4].
Box 1. The Kinship/Conflict Theory of Imprinting
The Kinship (or Conflict) Theory of Imprinting [26],[27] was first applied to fetal/placental genes that play an active role in soliciting resources from the mother during pregnancy [28]–[30]. In mammals, the optimal demand on maternal resources is different for maternally and paternally inherited alleles in an offspring: natural selection favors alleles that demand more maternal resources when paternally inherited, and fewer resources when maternally inherited. Maternally inherited alleles favor limited demand because each of the mother's other offspring has a 50% chance of carrying an identical copy of the allele. Paternally inherited alleles favor slightly greater demand, since some of the mother's other offspring could have different fathers, so their chance of carrying an identical copy of the paternally inherited allele is less than 50%.
At unimprinted loci, natural selection drives demand to a point between the optima for maternally and paternally inherited alleles. However, genomic imprinting allows alleles to evolve two separate expression patterns. For loci where the gene product acts as a fetal growth enhancer, the evolutionarily stable pattern is monoallelic expression from the paternally inherited allele. At a growth-suppressing locus, it is expression from the maternally inherited allele [31]–[34].
Some of these phenotypes, such as imprinted gene effects on suckling and weaning behaviors, can be understood through straightforward extensions of the Kinship Theory, with the intragenomic conflict over maternal resource demand continuing after birth (Figure 1A) [5],[6]. But what about other phenotypes, such as effects on adult behavior?
In principle, the logic of the Kinship Theory applies to any trait that affects the fitness of other, related individuals. In fact, in its general form, the theory is simply an extension of standard inclusive-fitness theory [7],[8], where inclusive fitness effects are calculated separately for maternally and paternally inherited alleles [9]. This generalization of the Kinship Theory makes sense once we recognize that most relatives (excepting full siblings and descendants) are related either matrilineally or patrilineally—for example, a cousin on my mother's side is a pretty close relative to my maternally inherited alleles, but a complete stranger to my paternally inherited alleles.
In practice, however, the application of the Kinship Theory to non-growth-related traits is challenging. The models quickly become complicated, and it is not always obvious how to connect them to empirical data. Specific biological predictions can vary, depending on factors such as sex-biased dispersal in structured populations and the scale of (geographically or socially) local competition for resources [10]–[13]. For example, imagine a species where males disperse over long distances every generation. At the local scale, we would find that individuals were more closely related through their maternally inherited alleles than their paternally inherited ones (Figure 1B). We would expect the elaboration of traits involved in cooperation and resource sharing to be preferentially favored by those maternally inherited alleles. Of course, real systems will typically be more complicated, and will not lead to this sort of robust, qualitative prediction. Even seemingly benign factors—such as whether the population has overlapping or non-overlapping generations—can substantially alter conclusions of the models [14]. The testing of these models' predictions requires quantitative measurements of relatedness, social interaction, reproduction, and resource allocation, which will be challenging in most natural populations [15].
Thus, in addition to continuing to examine the implications of the Kinship Theory, it is important to explore alternative hypotheses that might complement, or even supersede, the Kinship Theory within specific contexts. So far, most of the alternative hypotheses proposed have not proven to have predictive or explanatory power that would justify replacing or augmenting the Kinship Theory [16]. However, one notable exception is the Coadaptation Theory [17], which in their recent PLOS Biology article, Cowley and colleagues set out to test [18].
Mother-Offspring Coadaptation
The basic idea behind the Coadaptation Theory is that the mother-offspring system, when taken as a whole, functions better when the components of the system are aligned with each other. In terms of imprinting, this means “allele matching,” driven by the close interaction between mother and offspring during early development. For example, imagine a gene expressed in both mother and offspring, where the gene products interact (perhaps only indirectly, through effects on a shared phenotype). If there is substantial functional variation among alleles in the population, we might expect certain combinations of alleles to be more compatible than others. We might also expect the functions of the same allele, expressed in mother and offspring, to be more compatible, since their compatibility is constantly subjected to selection. Different alleles, which co-occur less frequently, might accumulate incompatibilities. Silencing the paternally inherited copy in the offspring would avoid interaction between that allele and a potentially incompatible allele in the mother (Figure 1C). It is like avoiding conflict at holiday gatherings by letting your spouse do most of the talking when you visit the in-laws.
Theoretical models have shown that this type of system can, indeed, favor imprinted gene expression, at least under certain conditions [17]. The question then becomes, how often do those conditions hold? Are there imprinted genes for which natural selection for coadaptation was likely a more significant factor than differential inclusive fitness effects on maternally and paternally inherited alleles?
Compensatory Pleiotropy
The work by Cowley and colleagues [18] examines the effect of a loss-of-function mutation of the imprinted Grb10 gene in mice. Grb10 is pleiotropic, with at least three distinct phenotypic effects. It is expressed exclusively from the maternally inherited allele in fetal and extra-embryonic tissues during pregnancy, where it restricts growth, consistent with predictions from the Kinship Theory [19],[20]. It is also maternally expressed in the peripheral tissues of adults, where it plays a role in glucose homeostasis and insulin signaling [21]. Of particular interest here is the expression of Grb10 in the mammary epithelium of lactating females [18]. Adult mice also express Grb10 in their CNS, specifically from the paternally inherited allele [22], where it affects adult behavior [23].
This study focuses on the growth effects of the maternally expressed transcripts in mother and offspring, using a well-characterized genetic construct to knock out Grb10. The authors implemented various cross-fostering arrangements to separate two major effects of the gene product: (1) expression of Grb10 in offspring suppresses demand for maternal resources; and (2) expression of Grb10 in the mother's mammary epithelium enhances the maternal nutrient supply during lactation.
As expected, knocking out Grb10 in offspring results in mice that are larger than wild type. Knocking it out in the mother (but not the offspring) produces small mice. The exciting result is that when you combine the two knockouts—eliminating maternally inherited Grb10 in both mother and offspring—the two effects cancel each other out, and the offspring recover their wild-type body size. These equal-and-opposite effects of the two knockouts suggest the type of compensatory pleiotropy described by the Coadaptation Theory, but it is still an open question whether such compensation is typical of natural allelic variation at the locus.
For example, interpolating between the wild-type and knockout results, we might assume that the growth enhancement resulting from a 25% reduction in Grb10 expression in the offspring would be offset by the growth restriction resulting from a 25% reduction in Grb10 expression in the mother. The question then becomes, what is the relationship between the regulatory elements responsible for dosage in these two conditions? Will a given mutation typically have similar effects on expression or activity in the two tissues? If so, the case for coadaptation is compelling. On the other hand, if the two activities are largely independent (e.g., if expression of Grb10 in mother and offspring is controlled by two completely different sets of cis-acting enhancer elements), then the phenotype of the double knockout will seem more like an interesting coincidence.
Two Types of “Evolution of Imprinting”
The striking data presented by Cowley and colleagues are consistent with a role for coadaptation in the evolution of imprinting, and their results will hopefully prompt more research in this area. So what future results would lead us to conclude that coadaptation has played a major role in the evolution of imprinting at the Grb10 locus or was a major factor in the evolution of imprinting in general?
The “evolution of imprinting” actually refers to two distinct processes. The first is the acquisition of imprinted gene expression at a locus—the evolutionary transition from being unimprinted to imprinted. The second is the evolution at a locus after it has become imprinted. Coadaptation could potentially play an important role in either of these processes.
If coadaptation drove the acquisition of imprinting at Grb10, this implies that the complementary phenotypic effects of Grb10 expression in mother and offspring predated the evolution of imprinted gene expression. In this scenario, genomic imprinting evolves because, by increasing the allelic match between mother and offspring, it enhances this complementarity. Because Grb10 would already have its growth-suppressing effect in the offspring, it would be reasonable to say that Kinship and Coadaptation both contributed to the selective pressure favoring paternal silencing at the locus.
An alternative scenario follows the “Growth First” theory of imprinting [24], where paternal silencing of Grb10 is driven by its growth-suppressing function in the offspring. Maternal expression in the peripheral tissues of adults is, at first, an epiphenomenon not requiring an adaptive (selective) explanation. Then, variation among Grb10 alleles creates selection to canalize, or buffer, the resulting variation in growth rates. This selects for Grb10 to acquire its novel, pleiotropic function in the mother, where it enhances resource provisioning.
Distinguishing between these scenarios requires determining the order in which Grb10 acquired these two features—imprinting and coadaptation. One possibility involves a comparative, taxonomic approach. Under the first scenario, we might find species where Grb10 exhibits complementary growth effects in mothers and offspring, but where the locus is not imprinted. Under the second, we might find species where Grb10 is imprinted, but not expressed in mammary tissues. A recent study found that Grb10 is widely expressed in the tissues of the Tammar wallaby, a marsupial, where its expression appears not to be imprinted [25], but its function in this species remains unknown.
It is important to keep in mind that evolutionary explanations are rarely mutually exclusive. Evolutionary Biology is a historical science, and identifying “the cause” of a unique evolutionary event, such as the acquisition of imprinting at Grb10, is analogous to trying to identify “the cause” of the French Revolution. Each unique event involves multiple selective factors, as well as a healthy dose of chance.
The power of the Kinship Theory is that it makes at least some sense of many of the large-scale patterns associated with imprinting, across disparate genes and species, including analogous phenomena in plants and insects. The work by Cowley and colleagues in PLOS Biology [5] represents the first real attempt at testing the Coadaptation Theory. As this perspective is brought to bear on other cases, we will see if it is able to bring additional order to the zoo of imprinted genes and their phenotypes.
Funding Statement
This work was not supported by outside funding.
References
- 1. Peters J, Williamson C (2008) Control of imprinting at the Gnas cluster. Adv Exp Med Biol 626: 16–26. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2. Runte M, Färber C, Lich C, Zeschnigk M, Buchholz T, et al. (2001) Comprehensive methylation analysis in typical and atypical PWS and AS patients with normal biparental chromosomes 15. Eur J Hum Genet 9: 519–526. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3. Smith FM, Garfield AS, Ward A (2006) Regulation of growth and metabolism by imprinted genes. Cytogenet Genome Res 113: 279–291. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4. Wilkinson LS, Davies W, Isles AR (2007) Genomic imprinting effects on brain development and function. Nat Rev Neurosci 8: 832–843. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5. Haig D, Wharton R (2003) Prader-Willi syndrome and the evolution of human childhood. Am J Hum Biol 15: 320–329. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6. Úbeda F (2008) Evolution of genomic imprinting with biparental care: implications for Prader-Willi and Angelman syndromes. PLoS Biol 6: e208. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7. Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. J Theor Biol 7: 1–16. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour. II. J Theor Biol 7: 17–52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9. Haig D (1997) Parental antagonism, relatedness asymmetries, and genomic imprinting. Proc Biol Sci 264: 1657–1662. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10. Wilkins J, Haig D (2003) Inbreeding, maternal care and genomic imprinting. J Theor Biol 221: 559–564. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11. Úbeda F, Gardner A (2010) A model for genomic imprinting in the social brain: juveniles. Evolution 64: 2587–2600. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12. Úbeda F, Gardner A (2010) A model for genomic imprinting in the social brain: adults. Evolution 65: 462–475. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13. Wild G, West SA (2009) Genomic imprinting and sex allocation. Am Nat 173: E1–14. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14. Van Cleve J, Feldman MW, Lehmann L (2010) How demography, life history, and kinship shape the evolution of genomic imprinting. Am Nat 176: 440–455. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15. Brandvain Y, Van Cleve J, Úbeda F, Wilkins JF (2011) Demography, kinship, and the evolving theory of genomic imprinting. Trends Genet 27: 251–257. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16. Moore T, Mills W (2008) Evolutionary theories of imprinting–enough already!. Adv Exp Med Biol 626: 116–122. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17. Wolf JB, Hager R (2006) A maternal-offspring coadaptation theory for the evolution of genomic imprinting. PLoS Biol 4: e380. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18. Cowley M, Garfield AS, Madon-Simon M, Charalambous M, Clarkson RW, et al. (2014) Developmental programming mediated by coadapted roles of imprinted Grb10 in mother and pup. PLoS Biol 12: e1001799. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19. Charalambous M, Smith FM, Bennett WR, Crew TE, Mackenzie F, et al. (2003) Disruption of the imprinted Grb10 gene leads to disproportionate overgrowth by an Igf2-independent mechanism. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 100: 8292–8297. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20. Charalambous M, Cowley M, Geoghegan F, Smith FM, Radford EJ, et al. (2010) Maternally-inherited Grb10 reduces placental size and efficiency. Dev Biol 337: 1–8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21. Smith FM, Holt LJ, Garfield AS, Charalambous M, Koumanov F, et al. (2007) Mice with a disruption of the imprinted Grb10 gene exhibit altered body composition, glocose homeostasis, and insulin signaling during postnatal life. Mol Cell Biol 27: 5871–5886. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22. Garfield AS, Cowley M, Smith FM, Moorwood K, Stewart-Cox JE, et al. (2011) Distinct physiological and behavioural functions for parental alleles of imprinted Grb10. Nature 469: 534–538. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23. Dent CL, Isles AR (2013) Brain-expressed imprinted genes and adult behaviour: the example of Nesp and Grb10 . Mamm Genome In press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Wilkins JF (2013) Phenotypic plasticity, pleiotropy, and the growth-first theory of imprinting. Jirtle RL, Tyson FL, editors. Environmental epigenomics in health and disease: epigenetics and human health. New York: Springer. pp. 57–72. [Google Scholar]
- 25. Stringer JM, S S, Pask AJ, Shaw G, Renfree MB (2012) GRB10 imprinting is eutherian mammal specific. Mol Biol Evol 29: 3711–3719. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26. Haig D (2000) The kinship theory of genomic imprinting. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 31: 9–32. [Google Scholar]
- 27. Wilkins J, Haig D (2003) What good is genomic imprinting: the function of parent-specific gene expression. Nat Rev Genet 4: 359–368. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28. Haig D, Westoby M (1989) Parent-specific gene expression and the triploid endosperm. Am Nat 147–155. [Google Scholar]
- 29. Haig D, Graham C (1991) Genomic imprinting and the strange case of the insulin-like growth factor II receptor. Cell 64: 1045–1046. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30. Moore T, Haig D (1991) Genomic imprinting in mammalian development: a parental tug-of-war. Trends Genet 7: 45–49. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31. Haig D (1996) Placental hormones, genomic imprinting, and maternal-fetal communication. J Evol Biol 9: 357–380. [Google Scholar]
- 32. Wilkins JF, Haig D (2001) Genomic imprinting of two antagonistic loci. Proc Biol Sci 268: 1861–1867. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33. Mochizuki A, Takeda Y, Iwasa Y (1996) The evolution of genomic imprinting. Genetics 144: 1283–1295. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34. Spencer HG, Feldman MW, Clark AG (1998) Genetic conflicts, multiple paternity and the evolution of genomic imprinting. Genetics 148: 893–904. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]