In a series of three human neuroimaging studies we recently identified prefrontal and parietal brain signals that predict a person's upcoming “free” choice up to several seconds before a person believes to be making up their mind (Soon et al., 2008, 2013; Bode et al., 2011). These findings were based on a combination of functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) with multivariate pattern classification (e.g., Haynes and Rees, 2006) and extended similar previous work using electroencephalography measures where choice-predictive signals were also found, albeit across shorter time scales (e.g., Libet et al., 1983; Haggard and Eimer, 1999).
We took care to perform a number of sanity checks in order to rule out potential alternative explanations for our data (Soon et al., 2008), and more research will be needed to establish the nature and potential function of choice-predictive signals (Haynes, 2011). One of the questions we already originally addressed was whether our choice-predictive signals might reflect a spill-over from the previous trial, rather than being related to a process involved in shaping the upcoming choice. There were several aspects of our data that spoke against such an account. First, the classification accuracy increased with distance from the previous trial. Second, the classification of the time period of the next trial was not above chance, meaning that the regions we identified presumably did not carry predictive signals into the next trial. Third, we also used a simple assessment of randomness to check for dependencies between successive trials. We found that in our data sequence length roughly followed the shape of an exponential distribution, as would be expected for random data.
Lages et al. (2013) now raise the question whether this latter analysis, our assessment of randomness might not have been sufficient. We fully agree that the original approach was only an approximate assessment of randomness that can be improved in many ways. However, it was only one among a number of points that spoke against sequential dependencies. The proper assessment of randomness in the data from our choice experiments is tricky because the experimental data were acquired in separate runs, each of which only contained only around 10 choices. We recently published a reanalysis of the behavioral data from these studies (Allefeld et al., 2013) using more sensitive analyses based on single-subject data. A stochastic process analysis revealed that subjects' data was close to random with an entropy rate of around 0.95 bit/trial (where 1 bit/trial reflects perfectly random behavior). The redictability of a choice on trial N from the choice in the previous trial N − 1 was approximately 62–64%, based on a classifier that also exploited small base-rate differences between choices. This is in a similar range as between-trial predictability in other studies (e.g., Lopes, 1982), including those found by these authors (Lages and Jaworska, 2012).
Because the brain-based classification accuracies were on a similar scale to the trial-by-trial behavioral predictions one might be led to believe that the brain-based prediction reflects nothing other than the carry-over of information between trials (Lages et al., 2013). In the following we will explain why this inference is misguided and present data to show that our classification does not directly reflect signals from the previous trial. The “spillover model” postulates that the choice on the previous trial (CN − 1) has some form of temporal persistence in the brain that leads it to spill over into the next trial (CN), creating the false impression of a choice-predictive signal in trial N several seconds before the choice (Figure 1A). In this model the classifier simply picks up the spillover signal and is only predictive of the next trial because of the weak behavioral correlation. Please note, however, that because the predictive link between CN − 1 and CN is weak (albeit existent), the brain-based classifier would need to be able to decode the brain signal related to CN − 1 with incredible precision in order to then be sufficiently predictable for CN, because the two are only weakly correlated.
The key issue here is that the sole numbers of the trial-by-trial contingencies and the brain-based decoding accuracies alone do not allow us to tell whether the spillover model is true. The only way to decide this issue is to directly test whether the spillover model provides a better account of our data. This can be done by applying the same classification analysis as in the original study, but shifted by one trial, i.e., to determine whether neural activity predicting the current trial still encodes the previous decision. If the spillover model is true, the classification accuracy should increase when shifting the labels by one trial. We performed this analysis (see Figure 1B) for both original studies. We found no decodable choice information using the shifted model. In contrast the information from our original model was significant in the seconds leading up to the decision and it was significantly higher than that of the shifted model. Thus, our original model provides the better account of the data and suggests that the choice-predictive signals are not based on a spill-over between trials.
Finally, we would like to point out that we obviously believe that there has to be some form of relationship between the brain signals of the two neighboring trials. It would be untenable to assume that choices come out of the blue by some break in the causal flow of events in the brain, rather than by a causal dynamical process that links the previous trial to the current trial. The issue is whether the choice-predictive signals we find are some emergent property of the brain dynamics in the inter-trial period, or whether they reflect a direct and explicit representation of the previous trial, for which we find no evidence in our data.
Conflict of interest statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
References
- Allefeld C., Soon C. S., Bogler C., Heinzle J., Haynes J. D. (2013). Sequential dependencies between trials in free choice tasks. arXiv:1311.0753 [q-bio.NC]. [Google Scholar]
- Bode S., He A. H., Soon C. S., Trampel R., Turner R., Haynes J. D. (2011). Tracking the unconscious generation of free decisions using ultra-high field fMRI. PLoS ONE 6:e21612 10.1371/journal.pone.0021612 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haggard P., Eimer M. (1999). On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Exp Brain Res. 126, 128–133 10.1007/s002210050722 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haynes J. D. (2011). Decoding and predicting intentions. Ann. N Y Acad. Sci. 1224, 9–21 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.05994.x [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haynes J. D., Rees G. (2006). Decoding mental states from brain activity in humans. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 7, 523–534 10.1038/nrn1931 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lages M., Boyle S. C., Jaworska K. (2013). Flipping a coin in your head without monitoring outcomes? Comments on predicting free choices and a demo program. Front. Psychol. 4:925 10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00925 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lages M., Jaworska K. (2012). How Predictable are “Spontaneous Decisions” and “Hidden Intentions”? comparing classification results based on previous responses with multivariate pattern analysis of fMRI BOLD signals. Front. Psychol. 3:56 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00056 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Libet B., Gleason C. A., Wright E. W., Pearl D. K. (1983). Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106(Pt 3), 623–642 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lopes L. L. (1982). Doing the impossible: a note on induction and the experience of randomness. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 8, 626–636 [Google Scholar]
- Soon C. S., Brass M., Heinze H. J., Haynes J. D. (2008). Unconscious determinants of free decisions in the human brain. Nat. Neurosci. 11, 543–545 10.1038/nn.2112 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Soon C. S., He A. H., Bode S., Haynes J. D. (2013). Predicting free choices for abstract intentions. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 110, 6217–6222 10.1073/pnas.1212218110 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]