Abstract
How and when do children develop an understanding of extraordinary mental capacities? Fifty-six preschoolers (3-5 years old) were tested on false-belief and knowledge-ignorance tasks about the mental states of carefully contrasted agents – some agents were ordinary humans, some had exceptional perceptual capacities, and others possessed extraordinary mental capacities. Results indicated that, in contrast with younger and older peers, children within a specific age-range reliably attributed fallible, human-like capacities to ordinary humans and to several special agents (including God) for both tasks. These data lend critical support to an anthropomorphism hypothesis – which holds that children’s understanding of extraordinary minds is derived from their everyday intuitive psychology – and reconcile disparities between the findings of other studies on children’s understanding of extraordinary minds.
Children and adults worldwide come to understand persons as intentional agents who act in accordance with their perceptions, desires, and beliefs (Flavell & Miller, 1998; Wellman, 1990). Most people also come to entertain ideas about non-human or superhuman agents with extraordinary mental capacities (such as deities who are all-knowing) or agents with exceptional perceptual capacities (such as animals with specialized senses or superheroes with x-ray vision). How and when do such concepts of extraordinary or exceptional agents develop? Addressing this question promises to inform fundamental issues in cognitive development, such as the nature of intuitive and counterintuitive ideas, the enculturation of thought, and the cognitive foundations of religion.
Arguably, the ability to appreciate extraordinary or exceptional capacities originates in early childhood, and is intimately linked to the development of an understanding of ordinary, human capacities. Children’s understanding of persons and minds – their theory of mind – undergoes substantial development during the preschool years (Wellman & Liu, 2004), as children increasingly appreciate the subjective nature of perceptions and thoughts. Such development requires that children disambiguate how the world really is from how self and others perceive and think about the world. Very young children have difficulty understanding this distinction between appearance and reality. When asked about what other people know or believe, very young children tend to answer by simply assessing reality and using that information to infer others’ knowledge and beliefs (Wellman, Cross & Watson 2001). We will refer to this tendency as a reality bias.
One early-emerging manifestation of children overcoming this reality bias is their understanding of ignorance – an understanding that agents can be unaware of certain facts. By 3-years of age, children understand that ignorance may result from a variety of circumstances, including agents’ lack of perceptual access to certain information. For example, older 3-year-olds understand that only those individuals who have looked inside a container will know what the container holds (Pratt & Bryant, 1990; Pillow, 1989). Soon after children develop an appreciation for the distinction between knowledge and ignorance, they begin to appreciate the distinction between reality and belief; they start to understand that others, misled by inaccurate perceptual cues or outdated information, can hold false-beliefs (Wellman & Bartsch, 1988). In one standard false-belief task – an unexpected contents task (Perner, Leekam, & Wimmer, 1987) – children are shown that a familiar container (e.g., a cracker box) holds something atypical (e.g., rocks). The container is then closed and children are asked what another person, who has not seen in the container, will think is inside. When faced with this task, 3-year-olds typically report that the other person will think the cracker box contains rocks, demonstrating a reality bias. Older 4-year-olds, in contrast, report that others will think the box contains crackers, demonstrating their ability to distinguish how the world really is from one’s beliefs about the world.
Thus, in the preschool years, children evidence an emerging understanding of human knowledge and beliefs, including some appreciation of mechanisms that yield knowledge and beliefs (e.g., that seeing leads to knowing). But how does an understanding of the mental capacities of non-human or superhuman agents emerge? Studying children’s developing understanding of extraordinary minds is interesting in its own right and also promises to shed light more generally on children’s understanding of ordinary minds. One possibility, stemming from Piaget’s (1979) notion that preoperational children anthropomorphize all agents, has been termed the anthropomorphism hypothesis. According to this hypothesis (Boyer 1996), when children first come to attribute constrained knowledge and fallible beliefs to ordinary humans, they attribute similar limitations to all agents. Only later, building on this initial platform, do children differentiate between the limited capacities of ordinary humans and extraordinary agents’ less limited capacities.
An anthropomorphism hypothesis is intuitively appealing; even adults tend to think of non-human beings, such as God, as human-like (Barrett & Keil, 1996; Gray, Gray, & Wegner, 2007). Indeed, although formal religious doctrine may attribute radically non-human, counterintuitive capacities to deities (e.g., total omniscience), in everyday judgments adults tend to think of deities in terms that are more human-like and limited, and thus only moderately counterintuitive (Barrett, 2000; Boyer, 1996; Boyer, 1998). For example, Barrett and Keil (1996) found that even religious believers well-versed in God’s omniscience conceptualized God as attending to people’s prayers sequentially, rather than attending to all prayers simultaneously, suggesting that they thought of God as subject to some of the same spatiotemporal constraints as humans. If such anthropomorphic tendencies are true of adults, they seem all the more plausible for children.
However, seminal studies by Barrett, Richert, and Driesenga (2001) challenged this anthropomorphism perspective. These researchers asked children (who attended Christian preschools) to reason about the knowledge and beliefs of humans, God, animals, and inanimate objects. In two studies, using unexpected-contents false-belief tasks, 3- to 7-year-olds reported what their mother, a tree, non-human animals, and God would think is inside a cracker box that contained rocks. Regardless of age or level of false-belief understanding, children typically reported that God would know the actual contents of the box. In another study, these researchers asked 3- to 8-year-olds whether a human, a monkey, God, or a cat that could see in the dark would know the contents of a box that had only a small slit to peer inside, and no internal illumination. Children consistently reported that God and the cat would know the contents of the box, both before and after they gained an understanding (at about age 5 years) that humans and monkeys would not know the contents of the box.
Based upon these findings, Barrett and colleagues (Barrett et al., 2001; Barrett & Richert, 2003) have endorsed an alternate preparedness hypothesis, which states that, “early-developing conceptual structures in children used to reason about God are not specifically for representing humans, and, in fact, actually facilitate the acquisition and use of many features of God concepts of the Abrahamic monotheisms” (Barrett & Richert, 2003, p. 300). Further, Barrett and colleagues (2001) proposed that, “children can have a more accurate understanding of God’s agency than that of humans” (p. 54). That is, very young children’s tendency to not attribute false-beliefs or ignorance to any agent reflects an early supposition of infallible mental capacities; children treat all agents (human and non-human) as omniscient. This hypothesis thus advances the intriguing idea that early cognitive biases facilitate rapid awareness of certain counterintuitive ideas, including ideas about the extraordinary qualities of God.
While intriguing, these findings and the preparedness hypothesis raise several questions, both empirical and conceptual. First, when very young children apparently attribute infallible knowledge and beliefs to persons (or Gods), their answers may simply reflect an early reality bias – they answer by reporting the reality of the situation without considering agents’ mental abilities (Evans & Wellman, 2006; Wellman & Bartsch, 1988). The critical question then is what children attribute to God when they first start to distinguish between the actual state of reality and people’s (often inaccurate) mental representations of that reality; in particular, at the point when they begin to attribute false-beliefs or ignorance to humans. At that point, do they attribute fallible knowledge and beliefs to God as well, as proposed by the anthropomorphism hypothesis, or infallible knowledge and beliefs, as implied by the preparedness hypothesis? At a later age, when children have developed a more robust understanding of fallible mental capacities, around 5- to 6-years-of-age, both preparedness and anthropomorphism hypotheses might predict that children attribute more infallible mental capacities to God, provided they have been exposed to such information about God. The preparedness hypothesis predicts that such an understanding at age 6 would reflect a continuation of children’s early default understanding of extraordinary minds. The anthropomorphism hypothesis, in contrast, posits that such an understanding at age 6 indicates that children are beginning to loosen their earlier tendencies to anthropomorphize all agents. To best test these two hypotheses, it is necessary to densely sample children within the proper age range. Further, the data should be analyzed in a sensitive age-related fashion in order to find and assess the critical window when children first correctly attribute fallible mental capacities to humans. Barrett and colleagues (2001) simply grouped 3-, 4- and 5-year-olds in year-long age blocks that might have masked the critical developmental window during which children first begin to ascribe human-like limitations to non-human agents for these social-cognitive tasks.
A second empirical issue concerns the replicability of Barrett and colleagues’ (2001) findings. This may well be related to the first issue of fine-grained age sampling and analyses, because different samples or different age-groupings may differentially capture the critical developmental window. On the one hand Barrett and colleagues (Knight, Sousa, Barrett, & Atran, 2004) have replicated their findings with a sample of Yukatek Mayan children whose culture has adopted the Catholic God. As well, Richert and Barrett (2005) reported data conforming to a preparedness trajectory for children’s performance on a diverse set of knowledge-ignorance tasks. But other researchers offer findings that conflict with those of Barrett and colleagues, and which would be better explained by the anthropomorphism hypothesis (e.g., Giménez-Dasí, Guerrero, & Harris, 2005; Makris & Pnevmaticos, 2007). For example, using a less challenging knowledge-ignorance task, Makris and Pnevmaticos (2007) found that 3- and 4-year-olds reliably attributed ignorance both to a human and to God. These latter findings suggest that, at least for certain mental properties, there may be a developmental period during which young children concurrently understand human and non-human mental capacities to be constrained.
Alongside these empirical issues is an important conceptual one. When children attribute accurate knowledge to God in a false-belief or knowledge-ignorance task, how are they reasoning about such knowledge and beliefs? One interpretation, following from the preparedness hypothesis, is that they are attributing (and prepared to attribute) to God something like omniscience – the capacity to know all things without perceptual access. But the tasks used tell us little about children’s appreciation for the mechanisms through which agents acquire their knowledge or beliefs. In past studies, it is unclear whether young children (even 5-year-olds) attributed to extraordinary agents privileged knowledge directly or via certain (ordinary or exceptional) mechanisms. For example, children may have assumed that God had special visual capacities (a moderate extension of human capacities) and thus actually saw the contents of the containers. Indeed, Richert and Barrett (2005) found that children as young as 4-years understood that agents with specialized senses (e.g., exceptional hearing or vision) can gain knowledge about certain stimuli that would be elusive to normal humans. Thus, one unaddressed issue concerns when exactly children are able to understand that an agent can possess certain (privileged) knowledge or beliefs without the use of perceptual mechanisms. And, this is related to whether and when they might attribute anything like omniscience to God.
We addressed these empirical and conceptual issues in several ways. We employed fine-grained age sampling and analyses (on the order of months rather than years) in an effort to reveal, more precisely, the ontogenetic unfolding of concepts of extraordinary minds. We tested children on both a false-belief task and knowledge-ignorance task and, because children develop an appreciation for human agents’ ignorance and false-beliefs on different timetables, we analyzed the age-related trajectories for these two tasks separately with appropriately different age groupings. Further, and crucially, we addressed the conceptual issue about children’s understanding of mechanisms mediating ordinary and apparently extraordinary knowledge and beliefs. Our primary method was to present 3-, 4-, and 5-year-olds with carefully contrasting agents. Specifically, we asked children to report on the mental capacities of ordinary humans (their mother and a young girl), and various non-human and superhuman beings, including God. In some cases we carefully specified, for the child, the capacities and mechanisms possessed by the agent. Two agents were specified as having special perceptual mechanisms for acquiring knowledge: a cat that can see in the dark, and a superhero (Heroman) who possesses x-ray vision. One other agent (Mr. Smart) was described as being able to “know everything,” even without seeing; so Mr. Smart’s knowledge or beliefs did not depend on perceptual mechanisms at all.
Each of these “special” agents was described in a brief but detailed way (see Appendix). Mr. Smart’s and Heroman’s special powers were also elaborated through brief demonstrations. Note that Mr. Smart was of interest in his own right and also served as a control in relation to God. It is impossible to know the precise information each child had already received about God and surely children did not have equal exposure to tutelage about a sentient God or God’s extraordinary attributes. Therefore, in contrast to God, about whom we provided no information, for Mr. Smart we gave all children exactly the same background information regarding his attributes. If, as predicted by the preparedness hypothesis, children are prepared to pick up on such information, given prior tendencies to think of agents as infallible and all-knowing, then Mr. Smart should be especially easy to appreciate. This set of contrasting agents allowed us to assess the extent to which children appreciated different mental and perceptual capacities as well as the specific mechanisms agents may use to gather information. As a second method for generating information about children’s reasoning about mechanisms, we asked children to explain their judgments. For example, if they judged that an agent knew the contents of a completely darkened container, we asked them how that agent knew that information.
Method
Participants
Fifty-seven children (32 males), ranging in age from 40 to 73 months (M age = 54 months), participated. Primarily, children were of European-American descent and lived in a middle- to upper-middle-class Midwestern university community. We densely sampled children in a critical age range (50 to 56 months) on the hypothesis (established during pilot testing) that during this period children would be likely to first understand ordinary humans’ limited mental and perceptual capacities. One child was excluded from the sample because she could not remember the actual contents of the box for the knowledge-ignorance task. Following the interview, when asked what they knew about God, more than half of these children (59%) provided specific details about God (e.g., “He’s very smart”, “He’s magical and powerful”). Thirty-nine parents agreed to briefly report on their child’s exposure to religious concepts. Almost half of these parents reported that they take their child to a place of worship; most on a weekly or monthly basis.
Procedure
Children were interviewed individually in a quiet location. They were asked about the beliefs and knowledge of various agents (see Appendix) using two tasks: one a contents false-belief task (Perner, Leekam, & Wimmer, 1987), the other a knowledge-ignorance task (similar to that used by Barrett and colleagues, 2001). Half of the children received the false-belief task first, the others received the knowledge-ignorance task first. Each of the agents was displayed on a five-by-seven-inch laminated card. Importantly, prior studies have shown that children perform equally well on these tasks whether the protagonists are drawings, puppets, or live performers (Wellman et al., 2001). Children were introduced to each agent (see precise language in Appendix) upon their first exposure to that agent. For each task, children were presented either mom or the girl first. The presentation of the remaining agents was randomized (the girl or mom was presented as the second agent for two children only).
Because prior research suggests that adults who are exposed to anthropomorphic images of God are more prone to make anthropomorphic judgments about God (Barrett & VanOrman, 1996), we assessed whether the presentation of an image representing God would influence children’s judgments about God’s mental capacities. Thus, half of the sample was tested using a blurry nondescript image to represent God (see Appendix), and the other half received no image and no language alluding to a bodily presence for God.
Measures
False-belief understanding
Children were shown a crayon box and a brown paper bag. The experimenter asked children what they thought was inside the crayon box, and then showed them that the box actually held marbles, and that the paper bag held crayons. Both containers were closed and, as a memory check, children were asked which container had marbles and which container had crayons inside (all children answered correctly). Children were then asked the following for each agent with regard to the box: “__ has never been in the room with these things before. If we show __ this box, all closed up, [picture of agent approaches the crayon box] what will __ think is inside here?” To minimize anthropomorphic cues, half of the children were not shown a picture representing God nor told that God had “never been in the room;” they were simply asked “What will God think is inside here?” To deemphasize Mr. Smart’s visual abilities and emphasize his all-knowing capacity, children were asked what Mr. Smart would think is in the box if he stayed across the room, facing away from the box. Following each judgment, the interviewer prompted children to justify their answer by asking, “Why will __ think __ are inside?”
Knowledge-ignorance understanding
To assess children’s ability to distinguish knowledgeable versus ignorant agents, children were shown two boxes, each with a slit at the top allowing children to look inside. A lamp was positioned above each box. One of the lamps was turned on, illuminating the interior of the corresponding box and revealing a red plastic frog inside. The other lamp was off, and the corresponding box appeared completely empty. Children were first asked to look inside the lit box, and to report what they saw. After children reported that the lit box contained a red frog, they were asked to look inside the unlit box. After children reported that they could not see anything inside the unlit box, the experimenter turned on the corresponding lamp, revealing an identical red frog inside. The latter light was then turned off, and the experimenter reminded children, “So, both boxes have a frog inside but you can’t see the frog when this one is dark [pointing at the unlit box].” As a memory check, children were asked whether each box, in turn, contained a frog or was empty (corrective feedback was provided for a few children as necessary). Children were then asked the following for each agent with regard to the unlit box: “__ has never been in this room with these boxes before. If __ comes very close to the top of the dark box, what will __ think is inside here; a frog or nothing?” For this focal question, the experimenter held the agent’s picture above the unlit box, facing the contents of the box. To minimize anthropomorphic cues for half of the sample, no picture representing God was presented and children were not told that God had “never been in this room;” they were simply asked “What will God think is inside here; a frog or nothing?” while the interviewer pointed at the box. To deemphasize Mr. Smart’s visual abilities, children were asked what Mr. Smart would think is in the box if he stayed across the room, facing away from the box. Following each judgment, the interviewer prompted children to justify their choice by asking, “Why will __ think a frog is inside?” or “Why will __ think nothing is inside?”
Results
Before conducting our focal analyses, we determined whether the presentation of an image representing God (along with language alluding to God’s physical presence) was related to children’s attribution of human-like (i.e., fallible or constrained) mental capacities to God. For the false-belief task, 43% of those children presented the image and language, and 36% of those who neither saw the image nor heard the language, reported that God will think crayons are in the crayon box, χ2(1, 56) = 0.30, ns. For the knowledge-ignorance task, 61% of children presented the image and language, and 64% of those not presented the image or language, reported that God will think nothing is inside the unlit box, χ2(1, 56) = 0.08, ns. Because children who were presented the ‘anthropomorphic’ image and language and those not presented the image and language were equally likely to ascribe fallible capacities to God, they were combined in the focal analyses.
False-Belief Understanding
To be clear in what follows, a “correct belief” refers to the judgment that an agent knows what is actually in the box (its real albeit hidden contents – marbles). “False-beliefs” refer to judgments that an agent is mistaken (i.e., will think crayons are inside the crayon box). Preliminary analyses assessed whether some children concurrently attributed human-like, false-beliefs to normal humans and to extraordinary beings, as expected under an anthropomorphism hypothesis. Many children indeed attributed false-beliefs not only to normal humans (i.e., the girl and mom), but also to each of our special agents – Heroman, Mr. Smart, and God – at levels significantly different from chance (for details, see Table 1). Of primary interest was whether a pattern of attributing human-like limitations to all agents would be most common when children first began to understand that humans may hold false-beliefs. Based upon exploratory data analyses of children’s false-belief judgments, we divided children into three age-groups: 24 in the young group (40.4 – 52.4 months; M = 47.7), 17 in the middle group (52.5 – 58.9 months; M = 54.7), and 15 in the oldest group (59.0 – 73.4 months; M = 63.3). Figure 1 depicts the primary data: the percentage of children who attributed a false-belief to each agent, by age group. Three trends are apparent in this graph: (1) with increasing age, children more often attributed false-beliefs to mom and the girl, (2) children in all three age-groups ascribed correct beliefs to Heroman, and (3) the youngest and oldest children attributed correct beliefs to God and Mr. Smart, whereas children in the middle age-group typically attributed false-beliefs to God and Mr. Smart.
Table 1.
Agent | Heroman | Mr. Smart | God |
---|---|---|---|
Mother | χ2(1, 18) = 8.00** | χ2(1, 21) = 10.71** | χ2(1, 22) = 14.73*** |
Girl | χ2(1, 18) = 5.56* | χ2(1, 21) = 8.05** | χ2(1, 22) = 11.64*** |
Note. Eighteen children attributed a false-belief to Heroman, 21 to Mr. Smart, and 22 to God.
p < .05,
p < .01,
p<.001.
Judgments
An initial repeated-measures ANOVA for children’s attributions of false-beliefs with Age as a between-subjects factor (3: young, middle, old), and Agent as a within-subjects factor (5: mom, girl, Mr. Smart, Heroman, God), revealed a significant effect for age, F(2, 53) = 6.98, p < .01, and agent F(4, 212) = 10.50, p < .001, and a significant interaction between age and agent, F(8, 212) = 5.13, p < .001. For the youngest group, there were no differences between the agents in children’s attributions of false beliefs, F(4, 92) = .57, ns; children reported that all agents would think the crayon box contains marbles. Children in the middle group attributed false-beliefs to each agent (except Heroman) more often than did the youngest children, ts(39) > 2.70, ps < .05. Children in this group (along with the oldest children) affirmed correct beliefs for Heroman (tending to report that Heroman will know the crayon box actually contains marbles) in contrast to the false-beliefs of mom (t(16) > 2.06, p < .06) and the girl, t(16) > 2.40, p < .05. Notably, children in the middle group generally did not grant God or Mr. Smart correct beliefs – judgments for these agents were indistinguishable from the judgments for mom and the girl. Only the oldest children (those 59 months and older) consistently reported that Mr. Smart and God would possess correct beliefs whereas the beliefs of mom and the girl would be false, ts(14) > 3.50, p < .01.
Justifications
Children’s justifications help clarify the reasoning behind their judgments. Children’s justifications were coded into seven categories, as outlined in Table 2, and a residual uncodable category ("don’t know"). Twenty-percent of the justifications were coded by two separate coders (one blind to all hypotheses and aims of the study) to assess inter-rater reliability (all κs ≥ .96). We focus on three contrasting agents: Heroman (whose special vision was described), Mr. Smart (who was described as having an extraordinary mind, but no specific exceptional perceptual mechanism), and God (about whom we told children nothing). Table 3 presents data on the primary forms of reasoning that children used to justify these three agents’ correct beliefs. Justifications for correct beliefs are particularly revealing because they address which (if any) extraordinary capacities children attributed to these agents.
Table 3.
Age group | Agent | Correct Belief Reasoning
|
Correct Knowledge Reasoning
|
||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Reality- based |
Exceptional Perceptual Capacities |
Extraordin. Mental Capacities |
Uninformative | Reality- based |
Exceptional Perceptual Capacities |
Extraordin. Mental Capacities |
Uninformative | ||
Young | Heroman | 24% | 29% | 6% | 35% | 29% | 14% | 14% | 43% |
Mr. Smart | 17% | 6% | 28% | 33% | 13% | --- | 13% | 50% | |
God | 32% | 5% | 5% | 37% | 17% | --- | 17% | 50% | |
Middle | Heroman | 10% | 60% | 10% | --- | 18% | 73% | --- | --- |
Mr. Smart | 17% | --- | 67% | 17% | 33% | --- | 67% | --- | |
God | 50% | 17% | 17% | --- | 67% | --- | --- | 33% | |
Oldest | Heroman | --- | 100% | --- | --- | 33% | 67% | --- | --- |
Mr. Smart | --- | --- | 100% | --- | 35% | 5% | 60% | --- | |
God | --- | 22% | 56% | --- | 42% | 25% | 17% | 17% |
Note. Age ranges for the false-belief task are: Young (40.4 – 52.4 months), Middle (52.5 – 58.9 months), and Oldest (59.0 – 73.4 months). Age ranges for the knowledge-ignorance task are: Young (40.4 – 49.4 months), Middle (49.5 – 54.5 months), and Oldest (54.6 – 73.4 months). Extraordin. Mental Capacities = Extraordinary Mental Capacities.
The youngest children generally did not appreciate these agents’ mental capacities or knowledge-collecting mechanisms; rather, they evidenced a reality bias (or said something uninformative). Most of the youngest children said that Heroman would know that the box contains marbles, but fewer than a third referred to his exceptional vision (e.g., “He has super eyes”). In contrast, most of these children justified Heroman’s correct beliefs by citing reality (e.g., “There is crayons inside”), confabulating a reason (e.g., “He guessed”), or provided an uninformative response (e.g., “Because”, or “I don’t know”). In this young group, of the children who said that Mr. Smart or God would think that the crayon box contains marbles (correct belief) only a few provided justifications indicating an appreciation for Mr. Smart’s or God’s extraordinary mental capacities (e.g., “He’s super smart”). Of the remaining children who attributed correct beliefs to Mr. Smart and God, most justified these agents’ correct beliefs by citing reality or provided an uninformative response. In sum, when attributing correct beliefs to these special agents (as was typical for these young children, who generally attributed correct beliefs to all agents), only 22% of children’s responses mentioned anything like exceptional perception or extraordinary mental capacities, although such special capacities were described to children at several points in our protocol.
In the middle group, most children attributed a correct belief to Heroman, and more than half justified their answers by specifically referring to Heroman’s extraordinary vision (e.g., “He can look through things”). However, most children attributed to all other agents a false-belief. Of the 11 children who attributed a false-belief to Mr. Smart, 10 (91%) cited the appearance of the box (e.g., “There’s a picture of crayons on the box”) or type of box (e.g., “It’s a crayon box”). Similarly, of the 11 children who attributed a false-belief to God, nine (82%) cited the appearance of the box or type of box. When attributing correct beliefs to these special agents, children in this middle group cited exceptional perception or extraordinary mental capacities in 55% of their responses.
Just as in their judgments, the oldest children’s justifications suggested an appreciation for Heroman’s perceptual prowess and for Mr. Smart’s and God’s extraordinary minds. All of the children in the oldest group who attributed a correct belief to Heroman cited his extraordinary vision, and every child who attributed a correct belief to Mr. Smart cited his mental capacities (e.g., “He’s so smart”). Interestingly, of the children who attributed a correct belief to God, about half cited extraordinary mental capacities (e.g., “He knows everything”), but several attributed to God exceptional visual capacities (e.g., “He can see through anything”). Overall, when attributing correct beliefs to these special agents (the typical response for the oldest children), older children appealed to exceptional perception or extraordinary mental capacities 94% of the time. In sum, when attributing correct (“infallible”) beliefs to these agents, young children rarely referred to agents’ extraordinary perceptual or mental capacities; however, this sort of reasoning was provided often by the middle age-group and especially by the oldest children.
Knowledge-Ignorance Understanding
With regard to children’s understanding of agents’ ignorance, we again first determined whether some children concurrently attributed human-like, constrained capacities to most agents. For clarification, we use the phrase “correct knowledge” when referring to children’s judgments that the agent knows what is actually in the box (its real but hidden contents – a frog). “Ignorance” refers to children’s judgments that the agent is mistaken (i.e., will think the box is empty). A significant number of children reported that ordinary humans (i.e., the girl and mom) as well as each of the special agents – Heroman, the cat, Mr. Smart, and God – would be ignorant, at levels significantly different from chance (see Table 4 for details). Again, of primary interest was whether this pattern would be most common among children who were just beginning to understand that ordinary humans’ knowledge can be limited by perceptual access. Based on preliminary exploratory analyses, we divided children into three age-groups. Because children evidenced an understanding of ignorance at an average age four months younger than an understanding of false-beliefs, for knowledge-ignorance analyses there were 12 in the young group (40.4 – 49.4 months; M = 44.2), 20 in the middle group (49.5 – 54.5 months; M = 52.2), and 24 in the oldest group (54.6 – 73.4 months; M = 60.5). Figure 2 depicts the focal data: the percentage of children who attributed ignorance to each agent, per age group. Three trends are noticeable in this graph: (1) with increasing age, children more often attributed ignorance to mom and the girl, with a later leveling-off, (2) children in all three age-groups attributed correct knowledge to Heroman and the cat, a tendency that was particularly pronounced in the oldest age-group, and (3) children in the young and old age-groups attributed correct knowledge to God and Mr. Smart, whereas children in the middle age-group attributed ignorance to God and Mr. Smart.
Table 4.
Agent | Cat | Heroman | Mr. Smart | God |
---|---|---|---|---|
Mother | χ2(1, 14) = 4.57* | χ2(1, 20) = 7.20** | χ2(1, 22) = 6.55* | χ2 (1, 35) = 17.86*** |
Girl | χ2(1, 14) = 7.14** | χ2(1, 20) = 12.80*** | χ2(1, 22) = 18.18*** | χ2 (1, 35) = 27.46*** |
Note. Fourteen children attributed ignorance to the cat, 20 to Heroman, 22 to Mr. Smart, and 35 to God.
p < .05,
p < .01,
p<.001.
Judgments
A repeated-measures ANOVA for children’s attributions of ignorance with Age as a between-subjects factor (3: young, middle, old), and Agent as a within-subjects factor (6: mom, girl, Mr. Smart, Heroman, God, cat), revealed a significant effect for age, F(2, 53) = 4.73, p < .05; agent, F(5, 265) = 11.16, p < .001; and an interaction between age and agent, F(10, 265) = 3.58, p < .001. For the youngest children, there were no differences in children’s attribution of ignorance between the agents, F(5, 55) = .61, ns, they reported that each agent will know that the dark box contains a frog. Children in the middle group attributed ignorance to agents (except Heroman and the cat) more often than did the youngest children (ts(30) > 2.09, ps < .05), but they (along with the oldest children) distinguished between the correct knowledge of Heroman and the cat and the ignorance of mom and the girl, ts(19) > 2.99, ps < .01. Notably, in the middle age-group, only the two agents who were specified as possessing exceptional vision were judged to know the correct contents of the dark box; God and Mr. Smart were judged to be ignorant. Only the oldest group of children (54 months and older) consistently reported that, whereas mom and the girl would think the unlit box is empty, Mr. Smart and God would have correct knowledge that the unlit box contains a frog (all ts(23) > 2.77, ps ≤ .01, except the difference between mom and God, which was significant at p < .06).
Justifications
Children’s justifications shed light on the reasoning behind their judgments. Justifications were coded into the same seven focal categories as before (see Table 2). Twenty-percent of the justifications were coded by two coders (one unaware of the hypotheses and aims of the study) to assess inter-rater reliability (all κs ≥ .88). We focus on four contrasting agents: Heroman and the cat (whose exceptional visual abilities were described), Mr. Smart (whose extraordinary mind was described, but who was not given a special perceptual mechanism), and God (about whom we told children nothing). Table 3 presents data on the most common forms of reasoning that children used to justify Heroman’s, Mr. Smart’s, and God’s correct knowledge.
Table 2.
Category | Description | Examples
|
|
---|---|---|---|
False-Belief Task | Knowledge-Ignorance Task | ||
Reality-based | Child cites actual contents of the containers. Child does not mention agent’s mental or perceptual capacities | “There are marbles inside the box” | “There is a frog inside” |
“The crayons are in the bag” | “I saw it in there” | ||
“I saw it in there” | |||
Appearance-based | Child cites the appearance of the box | “There are crayons on the box” | “It’s dark” |
“It looks like a crayon box” | “It looks like its empty” | ||
“It says ‘crayons’ ” | |||
Typicality-based | Child cites the type of container or mentions what that the type of box typically holds | “It’s a crayon box” | “It’s supposed to be in there” |
“There’s usually crayons in a crayon box” | “Frogs live in boxes” | ||
Exceptional Perceptual Capacities | Child cites agent’s exceptional senses (vision, hearing) when justifying why the agent will think the true contents are inside | “He has special/x-ray/lit-up eyes” | “He can see in the dark” |
“He can see in the dark” | “Because he saw it” | ||
“He heard us talking about the marbles” | “Heard us talking about the frog” | ||
Inadequate Perceptual Capacities | Child cites agent’s inadequate, senses (e.g., inadequate vision) | “He can’t see through things” | “It’s too dark to see inside” |
“He can’t see” | “He can’t see” | ||
“Can’t see in closed things” | “Light isn’t on” [implies agent cannot see] | ||
Extraordinary Mental Capacities | Child cites agent’s mental capacities without referring to perceptual capacities | “He’s super smart” | “He’s very smart” |
“He knows everything” | “He thinks very good” | ||
Inadequate Mental Capacities | Child cites agent’s inadequate mental capacities without referring to perceptual capacities | “He doesn’t know crayons are in there” | “He’s not as smart as Smarty” |
“He doesn’t know” | “She won’t know there’s a frog inside’ |
For the youngest children, most judged that Heroman and the cat would know that the box contains a frog, but only one of these children for each agent referred to special vision (“He can use his light sensy” and “He can see in the dark”). In contrast, most of these children justified these agents’ correct knowledge by citing reality (e.g., “I saw a frog”) or provided an uninformative response (e.g., “Because,” or “I don’t know”). In this young group, of the many children who reported that Mr. Smart would know that the unlit box contains a frog, only one provided a justification that suggested he appreciated Mr. Smart’s extraordinary mind (“He knows everything”), and only one of the children who reported that God would know that the box contains a frog cited God’s mental capacities (“He knows everything at church”). The remaining children justified Mr. Smart’s and God’s correct knowledge by citing the real nature of the box, or provided uninformative responses. In summary, when attributing correct knowledge to these special agents (the typical response for the young children, who generally attributed correct knowledge to all agents), in only 21% of their responses did the youngest children appeal to exceptional perception or extraordinary mental capacities.
In the middle group, most judged Heroman and the cat to have correct knowledge. Almost all of these children provided justifications that specifically referred to these agents’ exceptional vision (e.g., “He can see through anything” and “He can see in the dark”, respectively). Most children attributed to all other agents ignorance. Of the 14 children who attributed ignorance to Mr. Smart, four (29%) justified their responses by citing the appearance of the box (e.g., “It’s dark”), and seven (50%) referred to Mr. Smart’s inadequate visual capacities (e.g., “It’s hard to see”). Similarly, of the 17 children who attributed ignorance to God, three (18%) referred to the appearance of the box (e.g., “It’s dark”), and 10 (59%) justified their responses by referring to God’s inadequate visual capacities (e.g., “He can’t see in the dark”). When attributing correct beliefs to these four special agents, children referred to exceptional visual capacities or extraordinary mental abilities in 73% of their responses.
The oldest children’s justifications suggested a greater appreciation for Mr. Smart’s and God’s extraordinary mental capacities, in addition to an appreciation for Heroman’s and the cat’s exceptional vision. Most of the oldest children judged Heroman and the cat to have correct knowledge, and a majority of these children justified their judgments by explicitly referring to these agents’ exceptional visual capacities. Of the children in this group who attributed correct knowledge to Mr. Smart, more than half cited his extraordinary mental capacities (e.g., “He knows everything”), one referred to exceptional visual capacities (“He can see anything”), and a third cited reality. Of the children who attributed correct knowledge to God, almost half cited reality, while others cited extraordinary mental capacities (e.g., “He knows everything”) or exceptional visual capacities. In short, when attributing correct knowledge to these four agents (the typical response for the oldest children), the oldest children cited exceptional perception and extraordinary minds in 63% of their responses.
Discussion
Not only do children everywhere come to understand the basic mental and perceptual capacities of ordinary human agents, they come to entertain ideas about agents with extraordinary capacities, including religious deities. Recent research on children’s understanding of extraordinary, non-human minds has been aimed at comparing and contrasting two opposing positions: the anthropomorphism hypothesis and the preparedness hypothesis. From the anthropomorphism perspective, very young children initially understand all intentional agents as possessing human-like capacities. Three-year-olds fall prey to a reality bias – they do not consider agents’ mental abilities and thus fail to distinguish between the state of reality and people’s (often inaccurate) mental states. As children begin to appreciate that humans’ capacities are limited and fallible, they initially attribute similar limitations to all agents. After developing an understanding of ordinary, human capacities children can appreciate that certain agents may conceivably have exceptional or extraordinary powers. Thus, to understand extraordinary agents’ special capacities children must overcome or modify their intuitive conceptions of agents, and increasingly think in counterintuitive, non-anthropomorphic terms. The alternative preparedness perspective proposes that very young children begin life well-equipped to understand that certain agents possess non-human capacities (e.g., infallible beliefs) because they have an initial “default assumption” that “many superhuman properties are the norm” (Richert & Barrett, 2005, p. 284). Because initially all beliefs are true and all agents infallible, for special agents (God or others when they are explicitly told the agent has superhuman capacities or states) children need merely and easily continue to see them as superhuman.
A crucial developmental difference exists for these two positions. According to the anthropomorphism hypothesis, there should exist a developmental point, once children begin to attribute fallible capacities and states to humans, when they attribute these states to all agents, even agents adults contend are infallible (e.g., God) and children have heard are infallible (perhaps God, but in our tasks explicitly Mr. Smart). For the preparedness hypothesis, on the other hand, because superhuman properties are the default “norm,” children need not struggle to reason counterintuitively about such agents and, as a consequence, there should be no developmental point when these agents are attributed fallible, limited capacities or states. For both positions, an intriguing contrast case concerns agents with more limited extension of ordinary capacities, such as night vision or x-ray vision.
In accordance with the anthropomorphism hypothesis, we found that children reliably attributed ordinary, human-like capacities to special agents for both a false-belief task and a knowledge-ignorance task. Children did this for God, but also did so for agents whose extraordinary mental capacities and exceptional perceptual mechanisms were explicitly described and demonstrated to them. Normatively, children come to understand knowledge-ignorance before understanding false-beliefs; this is true in precise scaling comparisons (e.g., Wellman & Liu, 2004) and is apparent in our own data as well. Accordingly, we found that the age-related developmental period during which children were especially likely to consider most agents’ capacities to be human-like differed between these two forms of mental understanding, a sequential pattern that seems to accord more with an anthropomorphism position. A prepared, early understanding of infallibility should generally apply to knowledge and belief; overcoming an early reality bias could more sensibly apply first to developmentally “easier” mental states (knowledge), then later more complicated mental states (false beliefs). Thus it is of note that our data show that these children came to understand the ordinary limits of one and then another mental capacity, and subsequently entertained the counterintuitive suspension of those limits in sequence.
In apparently contradicting the results and conclusions of Barrett and colleagues, the current findings join two other recent studies. Using a different type of knowledge-ignorance task with Greek Orthodox children, Makris and Pnevmaticos (2007) found that 3- and 4-year-olds held that God and a little girl would both not know the contents of a closed box. Only at age 5 did participants differentiate between the girl’s ignorance and God’s correct knowledge of the box’s true contents. Similarly, using modified knowledge-ignorance and false-belief tasks with a sample of Spanish children, Giménez-Dasí and colleagues (2005) found that, compared with 3- and 5-year-olds, their 4-year-olds more often attributed ignorance and false-beliefs to God, and this was the case for children who were attending religious as well as those attending non-religious preschools.
Our data go beyond other results, however, in clarifying how the overall pattern of apparently contradictory findings could arise depending on the way in which children were sampled and grouped. That is, our finding of specific “anthropomorphic” developmental periods (using tasks similar to those used by Barrett and colleagues, 2001) was a product of careful age sampling and precise age-related analyses of the data. Suppose instead we reexamine our data after removing participants to correct for our dense sampling in the middle age-range, and simply divide our remaining children into three arbitrary age-groups. Then two age-graded linear trends emerge: (1) an increasing tendency to attribute fallible capacities to the girl and mom, and (2) a constant trend to attribute “infallible” capacities to God, Mr. Smart and Heroman. That is, with less precise sampling and age-grouping, our data would mimic the trend lines shown in Barrett’s work (e.g., Barrett et al., 2001; Knight et al., 2004). But as is clear in Figures 1 and 2, such analyses would actually mask three different trends: (1) an increasing linear trend to attribute fallible mental states to the girl and mom, (2) an apparently constant trend to attribute correct mental states to the cat and Heroman, and (3) a curvilinear trend where, with age, children first increasingly attribute fallible mental states to Mr. Smart and God, and only later attribute extraordinary, correct mental states to those superhuman agents. The latter trend thus parallels the findings of Makris and Pnevmaticos (2007), and also of Giménez-Dasí and colleagues (2005), and suggest that their data, too, may have emerged from samples and groupings that were able, like our own, to reveal more precise and detailed developmental trends.
Crucially, earlier studies provide limited information on what specific capacities children are attributing to extraordinary agents. The exception is Giménez-Dasí and colleagues’ (2005) finding that, when asked, 4- and 5-year-olds often justified their answers that God’s knowledge was limited by referencing God’s limited perceptual capacities. In our more comprehensive assessment of children’s reasoning, we distinguished children’s appreciation for mental capacities (e.g., infallible beliefs) from their appreciation for perceptual capacities (e.g., night vision). We used two techniques to provide this additional, needed, information: (1) asking children about the knowledge and beliefs of agents with contrasting mental and perceptual capacities, and (2) asking children to explain their responses. These techniques jointly revealed that children in the middle groups appreciated that most humans (such as the girl, mom, and Mr. Smart) as well as God have constrained access to certain information. However, they also reasoned that other agents who possess specific perceptual mechanisms to access information (such as the exceptional visual capacities of the cat and Heroman) may gain knowledge that would be elusive to most humans. It is conceivable that children attributed accurate knowledge and beliefs to Heroman merely because he held “superhero” status, and thus they understood him as being all-capable within a pretend world. However, on the knowledge-ignorance task, children treated Heroman just as they treated the cat – an agent who was not presented as a “super” agent. Moreover, for both tasks, children who attributed accurate knowledge and beliefs to Heroman justified their judgments by specifically referring to his visual abilities and not to his other exceptional abilities, such as his ability to fly fast.
Only the oldest children appreciated Mr. Smart’s and God’s extraordinary mental capacities, in the absence of exceptional perceptual mechanisms through which knowledge or beliefs could be acquired – Mr. Smart was described as being very smart and knowing everything, but we did not tell children how he acquired information other than saying that it was not based on vision. These data thus provide converging evidence that contradict the preparedness hypothesis, which specifically describes superhuman capacities, such as infallible beliefs, as the default. According to the preparedness hypothesis, children should have simply continued with this default position when taught about Mr. Smart, but they did not. Similarly, only the oldest children understood the extraordinary mind of God, about whom we provided no background information. Perhaps, in comparison with religiously trained children, the children in our sample lacked knowledge of God’s powers, and this is the reason why children in the middle age-group tended to anthropomorphize God – they simply had not learned about God’s powers. Following the interview, we did ask children what they know about God. Exploratory analyses did not indicate that there were differences in the responses of children based upon their knowledge of God. The children who could provide details about God, for example, were evenly distributed between the three age groups for the knowledge-ignorance task – about a third (35%) were in the middle ‘anthropomorphic’ age-group – and these children comprised about half (45%) of the children in the middle age-group. Moreover we found the same trends for God and Mr. Smart, an agent about whom children definitely had relevant background information. However, our measures did not sensitively capture details of children’s prior religious instruction, and our parental-reports of children’s religious exposure were available for only 39 of 56 children. It is important that future research be conducted using similar methods to assess these developing concepts in children who are exposed heavily to theistic ideas.
While the current results go a long way toward clarifying children’s developing ideas about extraordinary minds and exceptional perceptual capacities, they also raise several questions that could be addressed with future research. First, although we found that a substantial portion of children attributed fallible capacities to the two agents described as having exceptional perceptual capacities – Heroman and the cat – we did not find a specific developmental period during which children anthropomorphized these agents. It is possible that an even finer-grained age sampling and analysis might uncover earlier anthropomorphic windows for children’s understanding of exceptional perceptual capacities. Second, our findings do not indicate that our oldest children were attributing omniscience to Mr. Smart and God, although some researchers have used that term when interpreting their data (e.g., Giménez-Dasí et al., 2005; Knight et al., 2004). Understanding omniscience requires that one appreciates that an agent not only knows the contents of closed containers but that an agent truly knows everything – the nature of all past and future events, all scientific facts, everyone’s unspoken intentions and dreams, and so on. Rather, our oldest children likely understood God’s and Mr. Smart’s powers in a much less counterintuitive manner – Mr. Smart and God think like humans, but they know more (about certain tangible things in the here-and-now) than normal humans. It would certainly be interesting in future studies to address how children come to entertain increasingly counterintuitive concepts of extraordinary mental capacities and how this might eventually lead to a sophisticated understanding of omniscience.
In summary, our data lend critical support to the anthropomorphism hypothesis while also suggesting ways in which this hypothesis might be modified. When these children first began to overcome their initial reality bias and started to understand the limits of human mental capacities (e.g., that ordinary humans possess ignorance and false-beliefs) they applied this same understanding to God and to an agent who was described as possessing extraordinary mental capacities. Meanwhile, during this “anthropomorphic” period, children appreciated that knowledge and beliefs may be acquired via highly specialized, non-human perceptual capacities – such as eyes that see in the dark. This initial grasp of exceptional perceptual capacities may well act as a bridge to a later understanding of even more counterintuitive, superhuman capacities. By age five, children understood that agents with special mental capacities, such as the ability to know everything, may possess knowledge and beliefs without necessarily relying on specialized perceptual mechanisms for acquiring that information. Such early ability to understand extraordinary capacities is indeed impressive. These abilities allow children to begin to grasp important religious teachings that are seemingly counterintuitive, such as God’s omniscience. But, importantly, this early understanding of the extraordinary is built upon an earlier and more fundamental understanding of the ordinary.
Acknowledgments
Funding for this research was provided by National Institute of Child Health & Human Development Grant 22149 to Henry M. Wellman. We are very grateful to the children and parents who participated in this study and to the staff of the University of Michigan Children’s Centers.
Appendix
Girl | |
Let’s talk about Mary. [Show picture of Mary] | |
Mom | |
Let’s talk about your mom [show picture of mom]. It’s not really a picture of your mom, but let’s say it is. | |
Cat | |
This is a kitty cat [show picture of cat]. This kitty cat has special eyes that let him see in the dark. | |
Heroman | |
[Show picture of Heroman and say:] | |
This is Heroman. Heroman has super powers. He can fly very fast so that he can help lots of people all over the world. He also has eyes that let him see the insides of things, he can even see through walls. | |
[Show child a pen] Can you see this pen? [Place pen out-of-sight, behind paper] | |
Now can you see the pen? [Place picture of Heroman on child’s side of the paper] | |
Well, Heroman can still see the pen. He can see through the paper and see the pen on the other side. | |
Remember, Heroman can fly very fast and can see right through things | |
Mr. Smart | |
[Show picture of Mr. Smart, facing the child (away from the box) and say: ] | |
This is Mr. Smart. Mr. Smart has special powers. He knows everything. | |
[Show child closed opaque container that has a ball inside]. | |
Do you know what’s inside here? [Child responds: “No”]. | |
Well, this is the first time that I’ve played with this, so I don’t know what’s inside either. Mr. Smart also hasn’t played with this before. But because he’s so smart he still knows what’s inside. We would have to look inside, but he wouldn’t even need to look. | |
Mr. Smart, what do you think is in here? [Lean next to Mr. Smart] | |
Mr. Smart thinks that there is a ball inside. Let’s see. [Open container and show child the ball] | |
Mr. Smart was right! Wow, he knows everything! | |
Remember, Mr. Smart is very smart. He knows everything. | |
[Place Mr. Smart face-down, away from box] | |
God | |
Let’s talk about God [show picture]. It’s not really a picture of God, but let’s say it is. | |
Note. Picture representing God (and language alluding to God’s physical presence) was only presented to half of the sample. |
References
- Barrett JL. Exploring the natural foundations of religion. Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 2000;4:29–34. doi: 10.1016/s1364-6613(99)01419-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barrett JL, Keil FC. Conceptualizing a nonnatural entity: Anthropomorphism in God concepts. Cognitive Psychology. 1996;31:219–247. doi: 10.1006/cogp.1996.0017. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barrett JL, Richert RA. Anthropomorphism or preparedness? Exploring children’s god concepts. Review of Religious Research. 2003;44:300–312. [Google Scholar]
- Barrett JL, Richert RA, Driesenga A. God’s beliefs versus mother’s: The development of nonhuman agent concepts. Child Development. 2001;72:50–65. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00265. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Barrett JL, VanOrman B. The effects of image-use in worship on God concepts. Journal of Psychology and Christianity. 1996;15:38–45. [Google Scholar]
- Boyer P. What makes anthropomorphism natural: Intuitive ontology and cultural representations. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute. 1996;2:83–97. [Google Scholar]
- Boyer P. Cognitive tracks of cultural inheritance: How evolved intuitive ontology governs cultural transmission. American Anthropologist. 1998;100:876–889. [Google Scholar]
- Evans EM, Wellman HM. A case of stunted development? Existential reasoning is contingent on a developing theory of mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2006;29:471–472. [Google Scholar]
- Flavell JH, Miller PH. Social cognition. In: Damon W, editor. Handbook of child psychology: Cognition, perception, and language. Vol. 2. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons; 1998. pp. 851–898. [Google Scholar]
- Giménez-Dasí M, Guerrero S, Harris PL. Intimations of immortality and omniscience in early childhood. European Journal of Developmental Psychology. 2005;2:285–297. [Google Scholar]
- Gray HM, Gray K, Wegner DM. Dimensions of mind perception. Science. 2007;315:619. doi: 10.1126/science.1134475. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Knight N, Sousa P, Barrett JL, Atran S. Children’s attribution of beliefs to humans and God: Cross-cultural evidence. Cognitive Science. 2004;28:117–126. [Google Scholar]
- Makris N, Pnevmatikos D. Children’s understanding of human and super-natural minds. Cognitive Development. 2007;22:365–375. [Google Scholar]
- Perner J, Leekam SR, Wimmer H. Three-year olds’ difficulty understanding false-belief: Representational limitation, lack of knowledge or pragmatic understanding? British Journal of Developmental Psychology. 1987;5:125–137. [Google Scholar]
- Piaget J. The child’s conception of the world. Totowa, NJ: Littlefield, Adams; 1979. Original work published 1929. [Google Scholar]
- Pillow BH. Early understanding of perception as a source of knowledge. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology. 1989;47:116–129. doi: 10.1016/0022-0965(89)90066-0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Pratt C, Bryant P. Young children understand that looking leads to knowing (so long as they are looking into a single barrel) Child Development. 1990;61:973–982. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Richert RA, Barrett JL. Do you see what I see? Young children’s assumptions about God’s perceptual abilities. International Journal for the Psychology of Religion. 2005;15:283–295. [Google Scholar]
- Wellman HM. The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT; 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Wellman HM, Bartsch K. Young children’s reasoning about beliefs. Cognition. 1988;30:239–277. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(88)90021-2. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Wellman HM, Cross D, Watson J. Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false-belief. Child Development. 2001;72:655–684. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00304. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Wellman HM, Liu D. Scaling of theory-of-mind tasks. Child Development. 2004;75:523–541. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2004.00691.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]