Abstract
Voting systems aggregate preferences efficiently and are often used for deciding conservation priorities. Desirable characteristics of voting systems include transitivity, completeness, and Pareto optimality, among others. Voting systems that are common and potentially useful for environmental decision making include simple majority, approval, and preferential voting. Unfortunately, no voting system can guarantee an outcome, while also satisfying a range of very reasonable performance criteria. Furthermore, voting methods may be manipulated by decision makers and strategic voters if they have knowledge of the voting patterns and alliances of others in the voting populations. The difficult properties of voting systems arise in routine decision making when there are multiple criteria and management alternatives. Because each method has flaws, we do not endorse one method. Instead, we urge organizers to be transparent about the properties of proposed voting systems and to offer participants the opportunity to approve the voting system as part of the ground rules for operation of a group.
Sistemas de Votación para Decisiones Ambientales
Resumen
Los sistemas de votación agregan preferencias eficientemente y muy seguido se usan para decidir prioridades de conservación. Las características deseables de un sistema de votación incluyen la transitividad, lo completo que sean y la optimalidad de Pareto, entre otras. Los sistemas de votación que son comunes y potencialmente útiles para la toma de decisiones ambientales incluyen simple mayoría, aprobación y votación preferencial. Desafortunadamente, ningún sistema de votación puede garantizar un resultado y a la vez satisfacer un rango de criterios de desempeño muy razonable. Además, los métodos de votación pueden manipularse por los que toman las decisiones y votantes estratégicos si tienen el conocimiento de los patrones de votación y de las alianzas entre miembros dentro de las poblaciones votantes. Las propiedades difíciles de los sistemas de votación sobresalen en las tomas de decisiones rutinarias cuando hay criterios múltiples y alternativas de manejo. Ya que ambos métodos tienen fallas, no apoyamos a uno sobre el otro. En lugar de esto le pedimos urgentemente a los organizadores ser transparentes con respecto a las propiedades de los sistemas de votación y ofrecer a los participantes la oportunidad de aprobar el sistema de votación como parte de las reglas básicas para la operación de un grupo.
Keywords: Arrow’s theorem, decision theory, philosophy, preferences, Filosofía, preferencias, teorema de Arrow, teoría de decisión
Introduction
Environmental decisions lie at the interface of science and public policy. Scientists provide technical understanding, data, expert judgment, and predictions of the outcomes of alternative scenarios (Morgan & Henrion 1990; Cooke 1991; Burgman 2005; Patterson et al. 2007). Decisions also depend on the preferences of stakeholders: people interested in or affected by a decision. Stakeholders often have disparate values, interests, and prefer different tradeoffs among environmental, social, cultural, and economic criteria. Inevitably, differences of opinion arise (Slovic 1999; Maguire 2004). How should policy makers reconcile these divergent preferences to make decisions?
Voting is used widely to choose options, often because of its ease of application (e.g., Ghanbarpour et al. 2005). In conservation planning, it is used most often in informal settings to generate group preferences (e.g., Dicks et al. 2010). Despite its pervasiveness and practical appeal, there has been no systematic evaluation of voting for environmental applications. Importantly, different voting systems can generate different outcomes, even given the same underlying preferences. Yet, voting systems often are used unthinkingly and many people are unaware of the implications of choosing one voting system or another. The most familiar voting system allocates one vote per participant, and the alternative with the most votes is selected. However, this system has serious shortcomings, and there are many other voting systems with different and potentially more useful properties. We illustrate how different systems can generate different outcomes and describe the strengths and weaknesses of the alternatives, encouraging conservation biologists to think about desirable properties of different voting methods.
We examine how voting can be used to aggregate opinions about values and preferred strategies, rather than how voting can aggregate beliefs about facts. We assume that participants (voters) and the alternatives are known; group member selection and identification of stakeholders and feasible alternatives have been discussed elsewhere (e.g., Keeney 1992; Burgman 2005; Burgman et al. 2011). We also ignore the many psychological factors that influence group decisions (Slovic 1999; Kerr & Tindale 2004).
This review focuses on a subset of voting systems with the greatest potential utility for environmental decision making. We describe simple majority, approval voting, and preferential voting and outline 2 approaches with very long histories of application, the Borda count and Condorcet functions. We evaluate the mathematical and cognitive properties of these systems, identify circumstances in which voting system attributes are likely to be important, and describe how voters may manipulate systems. We conclude with recommendations for using voting systems for environmental decisions.
Methods
We searched the ISI Web of Science from 1990 to 2012 for papers describing voting methods using “voting,” “preference aggregation,” and “group decision.” We used terms discovered in this initial search (decision, environment, conservation, group, vote, and preference) to find applications of voting methods in ecology, conservation biology, and environmental science. References in these papers were used to identify additional studies that applied a voting method to aggregate individual preferences for environmental issues. In total we found 21 articles that used at least one of the voting methods focused on in this study or that used a variation of them that was relevant or that illustrated their use. We cite and discuss the applications in the relevant sections of the review.
Concepts and Notation
We devised a formal notation for the voting systems described below. Group decisions involve sets of individuals, I, alternatives, A, and preferences, P. We let I = {Ii : i = 1, 2, …, m} be the set of m individuals, A = {Aj : j = 1, 2, …, n} be the set of n alternatives, and P = {Pi : i = 1, 2, …, m} be the set of preferences of the individuals in I, where Pi is a set of preferences over A for individual Ii. Voting methods for group decisions involve evaluating the set of alternatives, A, on the basis of individual preferences, P.
A group evaluation takes the form of an ordering, R, of alternatives which indicates, for each pair of alternatives Aj, Ak, whether the group prefers Aj to Ak, prefers Ak to Aj, or is indifferent between the two. Group decision methods thus define a function, W, on P such that W(P) = R. Following Arrow (1951), W is described as a social welfare function. For the purposes of this review, a voting method combines a protocol for determining individual preferences with a social welfare function W to identify the set of alternatives the group prefers to all others, from the set of individual preferences, P. We ignore quantitative information and focus solely on the ordinal preference information of P to identify that set of alternatives. We assume initially that P includes enough information about preferences of individuals in I to define a preference relation, ≻i, on A for each individual Ii ∈ I, where the alternative Aj ≻i Ak if and only if individual Ii prefers Aj to Ak.
Let ≻i represent “strict preference” and define ≥i as the “weak preference” of Ii for Aj over Ak (i.e., where Aj ≥i Ak means individual Ii prefers or is indifferent to Aj over Ak) and ∼i as “indifference” (i.e., where Aj ∼i Ak means individual Ii is indifferent between them).
Ordinal preferences refer to ranks of preferences. A preference relation ≻i defines an ordinal value function Oi: A → R on A where Oi(Aj) > Oi(Ak) if and only if Aj ≻i Ak. The O therefore indicates the results of pairwise comparisons of alternatives, that is, whether Aj ≻i Ak, Ak ≻i Ai, or Ai ∼i Ak.
Properties of an ideal system
Different ways of considering preferences can lead to different decisions. For example, consider 7 stakeholders who must decide which of 3 environmental strategies is best. The alternatives are A1 maximize harvest, A2 protect threatened species, and A3 maximize public amenity. Three stakeholders prefer A1 to A2 and A2 to A3 (i.e., A1 > A2 > A3). Two stakeholders prefer A2 to A1 and A1 to A3 (i.e., A2 > A1 > A3). Two prefer A3 to A2 and A2 to A1 (i.e., A3 > A2 > A1). Alternative A1 gets 3 first place votes, and each of the other alternatives only gets 2. But a clear majority (4 of 7) prefers A2 to A1. Which alternative should the policy maker select?
Three appealing properties of any voting system are transitivity, completeness, and the Pareto principle.
Transitivity requires that if an individual or the group prefers A1 over A2 (O(A1) ≻ O(A2)) and A2 over A3 (O(A1) ≻ O(A3)), then they prefer A1 over A3 (O(A1) ≻ O(A3)). Consider a group that prefers to maximize harvest to protect threatened species and prefers to protect threatened species over maximizing public amenity. If the group is given the choice to maximize harvest or public amenity, transitivity means they would prefer to maximize harvest.
The Pareto principle states that if A1 is preferred to A2 by all individuals, then the group should also prefer A1 over A2. More generally, Pareto efficiency (or Pareto optimality) means that if the group preference is A1 ≻ A2, it implies A1 is better than A2 from the perspective of at least one person and no one regards it as worse. Thus, if protecting public amenity in the example above is the least preferred of the 3 alternatives for all individuals, then the voting system should not select it.
Completeness requires the voting system give a group preference for all of the alternatives in A.
There are other appealing properties of voting systems. For example, we may wish to select the alternative that would defeat every other alternative in one-on-one (pairwise) comparisons. Other desirable properties may be social or psychological. For example, it may be important that all members of the group understand how the voting system works (Elkind et al. 2011). Others writing about desirable properties of voting systems (Armbruster & Boge 1983; Fishburn & Brams 1983; Hwang & Lin 1987; Saari 2001; Hodge & Klima 2005; Poundstone 2008; Elkind et al. 2011) have proposed the following:
Homogeneity: The result of a vote depends on the proportions of the total number of votes assigned to each alternative, and not on their absolute counts.
Monotonicity: Increasing the number of votes for a winning alternative cannot make it a loser, and a losing alternative cannot become a winner when its number of votes decreases.
Anonymity: Voters are treated the same in the sense that if any 2 individuals trade their votes, the outcome would be the same.
Decisiveness: The voting system delivers an unambiguous winner or a winning set, if more than one alternative is desired.
Consistency: If a group is divided into subgroups and each subgroup selects the same alternative, then the entire group also selects that alternative.
Invulnerability to the no-show paradox: It is not possible for a group of voters to obtain their first-ranked choice by abstaining if voting would lead to the selection of some other option.
Although each of these properties seems intuitively desirable, some have several interpretations, some are inconsequential in many situations, some are mutually exclusive and others have undesirable implications in some circumstances.
Arrow (1951) proved that when 3 or more alternatives exist, no voting system can convert voter preferences into a Pareto efficient, complete, and transitive rank while satisfying these very reasonable criteria:
If every individual prefers A1 to A2, then the group should prefer A1 to A2.
There should be no individual in the group who can determine the group’s preferences (no dictatorship). More formally, there is no individual i such that A1 ≻ A2 implies the social choice of A1 over A2 regardless of the preferences of all other individuals.
The solution should be independent of irrelevant alternatives. That is, the ranking of A1 relative to A2 should not depend upon the introduction of another alternative, A3.
The importance of these and other intuitively desirable properties depends on the context in which a voting system is applied. For example, when choosing one alternative, completeness may not be important. Votes may be used to choose a subset of acceptable alternatives, unranked, in which case resolving all ties is not essential. Anonymity may not be desired when votes are deliberately weighted unequally, reflecting, for example, the number of shares individuals hold in a public company. Some voting systems may not guarantee a clear winner, but if there are many more individuals than alternatives, an indecisive outcome may be very unlikely.
Voting Systems
Return to the hypothetical example outlined above in which a group of stakeholders is asked for their preferences for 3 mutually exclusive environmental strategies, each of which has a different focus: A1 maximize harvest, A2 protect threatened species, and A3 maximize public amenity. The preferences expressed by 2 groups of 3 individuals (I) are arranged in Table1.
Table 1.
Removing Dominated Alternatives
The simplest defensible action a decision maker can make is removing “dominated” alternatives. In general, dominated alternatives are not the favorite of any individual. Therefore, in Table1a, the alternative set is reduced to A1 and A2. However, this does not provide a complete ranking of the remaining alternatives, A1 and A2, which are Pareto efficient alternatives (i.e., they are preferred by at least one individual).
This approach (removing dominated alternatives) is used in multicriteria decision analysis to simplify problems (e.g., Gregory & Keeney 2002). Hämäläinen et al. (2001) used it to analyze 5 water level management plans for a lake-river system in Finland involving 10 groups of stakeholders, including power producers, farmers, environmentalists, recreational users, and fishers and 10 ecological, economic, and sociological criteria.
Simple Majority (Plurality) Voting
Under simple majority voting, each voter has one vote, which may be cast for a single alternative. Thus, stakeholders cannot express their preferences for all of the alternatives; they merely identify their best option. Under simple majority voting, the aggregation rule is to sum the votes for each alternative. The alternative with the most votes is selected. There is no requirement that an alternative acquire a majority (>50%) of votes.
In antiplurality voting, individuals apply a single veto. The alternative with the largest number of vetoes is removed. The set of alternatives may be reduced to a desired size through successive vetoes (Armbruster & Boge 1983).
Consider the preferences of 9 individuals for 3 alternatives (Table2). Under simple majority voting, A1 would be selected, even though 5 of the 9 individuals prefer either A2 or A3 to A1. Thus, the preference ordering suggested by the count of votes in Table1 may not capture the full set of individual preferences and may result in unsatisfactory choices from the perspective of the majority. Below, we discuss how this property may be exploited to deliver outcomes at odds with the preferences of the majority of voters.
Table 2.
A1 | A2 | A3 | |
---|---|---|---|
I1 | 1 | 2 | 3 |
I2 | 1 | 2 | 3 |
I3 | 1 | 2 | 3 |
I4 | 1 | 3 | 2 |
I5 | 3 | 2 | 1 |
I6 | 3 | 2 | 1 |
I7 | 3 | 2 | 1 |
I8 | 3 | 1 | 2 |
I9 | 3 | 1 | 2 |
Votes | 4 | 2 | 3 |
Above we noted that transitivity is a desirable property of a voting system. Unfortunately, if more than 2 alternatives exist, simple majority voting may not be transitive (Arrow 1951; Dodgson 1876; Gehrlein 1983). For example, consider the case in Table1b, where 3 individuals specify their preferences for the 3 alternatives.
For A1 and A2, Oi(A1) > Oi(A2) holds for 2 individuals and Oi(A2) > Oi(A1) holds for one individual. Thus, R = (A1 > A2).
For A2 and A3, Oi(A2) > Oi(A3) holds for 2 individuals and Oi(A3) > Oi(A2) holds for one individual. Thus, R = (A2 > A3).
For A1 and A3, Oi(A1) > Oi(A3) holds for one individual and Oi(A3) > Oi(A1) holds for 2 individuals. Thus, R = (A3 > A1).
Thus, for this set, R is not transitive.
Another drawback of simple majority voting is that the preference of the group for one of 2 alternatives can be influenced by the inclusion or exclusion of other alternatives. For example, if we were to remove A3 from Table2 and reassign the preferences, then A1 would have 4 votes and A2 would have 5. The votes for A2 have been effectively split between A2 and A3. If every choice involved only 2 alternatives, then the outcome could be determined equitably and consistently through simple majority voting. If there are many alternatives, the winner may attract only a small percentage of total votes cast, which may be unsatisfying even if it does not violate any of the other desirable qualities listed above.
Given the potential frailties of simple majority voting, it is perhaps surprising how widely it is used to make environmental management decisions. Examples include nomenclatural decisions in taxonomy (e.g., McNeill & Turland 2010). (Although, interestingly, for the naming of Acacia, a 60% majority threshold was required.) In environmental management it has been used to identify a preferred management strategy for threatened species (Marcot et al. 2006) and to identify preferred forest management options (Kangas et al. 2006; Hiltunen et al. 2008). Tisdell et al. (2006) used it to assess preferences for conservation objectives for Australian vertebrates. In Chile, members of the National Fisheries Council vote on proposals for total allowable catch by a simple majority vote (Leal et al. 2010).
Approval Voting
In approval voting (Brams 2004) individuals select all alternatives of which they approve. The alternative(s) with the most votes is (are) selected. Generally, the option with the greatest overall support attracts the largest number of votes (Brams 2004). To illustrate its properties, we use Table2 and specify that the 9 individuals who expressed preferences would approve of their first and second choices but not their third. Other configurations of approvals would lead to different results. Their approval votes would be as in Table3.
Table 3.
A1 | A2 | A3 | |
---|---|---|---|
I1 | 1 | 1 | |
I2 | 1 | 1 | |
I3 | 1 | 1 | |
I4 | 1 | 1 | |
I5 | 1 | 1 | |
I6 | 1 | 1 | |
I7 | 1 | 1 | |
I8 | 1 | 1 | |
I9 | 1 | 1 | |
Votes | 4 | 8 | 6 |
In this example, A2 would be selected. Approval voting has the advantage over simple majority voting in that its results are transitive and it captures more information about the preference set P. However, it can generate counter-intuitive outcomes from the perspective of the choice of a single, most-preferred alternative. In this example, A2 was selected even though the fewest voters preferred it (Table2). If a second alternative were selected based on the approval vote, it would be A3, even though most voters preferred A1. Nevertheless, most voters considered A2 to be good enough. Approval voting tends to promote moderate alternatives that may be satisfactory but not ideal from any one perspective (Kangas & Kangas 2002).
Approval voting is used widely to identify group preferences in ecology and conservation biology. Sutherland et al. (2009) (see also Morton et al. 2009) used Approval voting to reduce a long list of global conservation questions to a more manageable list. In Brown et al. (2010), each participant allocated 10 votes among 94 water research questions, and the questions with the most votes were selected, creating a priority list of 15 questions. Vignola et al. (2012) used it to identify acceptable alternatives for the management of a catchment, reconciling the priorities of upstream farmers with downstream hydropower producers. Kangas et al. (2006) reviewed its application to choices in forest management.
Preferential Voting
Preferential voting and the Borda count (following) use the entire preference order to determine R. Preferential voting (also called alternative vote or instant run-off) is designed to give equitable consideration to the full range of each voter’s preferences. Under this system, if an alternative receives sufficient first preferences to achieve a quota (i.e., a minimum number of votes), it is selected. If no alternative achieves sufficient votes, the votes allocated to the least popular alternative are redistributed (transferred) to the remaining alternatives with the following procedure. Remove the alternative with the fewest primary votes. If there is a tie, remove the alternative with the fewest second preferences among those that tie. If there is a second tie, remove the alternative with the fewest third preferences among those that tie, and so on.
When there are m voters and more than one alternative is to be selected, transfers are made sequentially until n alternatives attain the quota needed for election. The quota, Q, is usually defined as (Fishburn & Brams 1983),
1 |
where the brackets indicate the integer part of the argument.
In Table4, all 3 alternatives are scored first once, but A3 is never scored second, so it is removed. Of the remaining alternatives, A1 and A2, A2 has the fewest first preferences so it is removed. Thus, R = (A1 > A2 > A3).
Table 4.
First round | Second round | ||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
A1 | A2 | A3 | A1 | A2 | |
I1 | 1 | 2 | 3 | 1 | 2 |
I2 | 2 | 3 | 1 | 1 | 2 |
I3 | 2 | 1 | 3 | 2 | 1 |
In preferential voting, an alternative that would attract the most votes in simple majority voting or an alternative that can defeat every other alternative in direct-comparison (one-on-one) voting (i.e., the Condorcet winner; see below) might not be selected (Fishburn & Brams 1983). Preferential voting may violate the monotonicity criterion, such that an increase in support for an alternative may turn it from a winner into a loser. In Table5 decision 1, the fewest people prefer option A2. It so happens that all of the voters who prefer A2 also prefer A3 over A1. Their votes in round 2 transfer to option A3, which is selected.
Table 5.
A1 | A2 | A1 | |
---|---|---|---|
Decision 1 | |||
Round 1 | 11 | 8 | 10 |
Round 2 | 11 | 18 | |
Decision 2 | |||
Round 1 | 7 | 8 | 14 |
Round 2 | 15 | 14 |
The only change between decision 1 and decision 2 is that in Decision 2, support for A3 increases in the form of 4 votes moving from A1 to A3.
In decision 2, the only change is that support for A3 increases, with 4 votes being transferred from A1 to A3. As a result, A1 is removed first. It so happens that all of the voters who prefer A1 also prefer A2 over A3. The preferences associated with A1 transfer to A2, which is selected over A3. The outcome is that A3 is no longer selected even though support for it increased. Although this counter-intuitive outcome is possible, it required quite an unusual distribution of preferences (namely, all voters who prefer A2 also prefer A3 over A1 and all voters who prefer A1 also prefer A2 over A3). This raises the question of whether such arrangements of preferences are likely to arise in practice. We explore this question below.
Despite the appeal of systems that incorporate each individual’s full set of preferences, we could find no examples of preferential voting in environmental science or conservation decision making. It is implemented in many jurisdictions in Australia to choose political representatives and has affected the development of public environmental policy there (Williams 2006).
The Borda Count
Like preferential voting, the Borda count uses the entire preference order of participants, but instead of reallocating the votes as is done under preferential voting, the preferences are tallied. When there are n alternatives, the best alternative gets n – 1 points, the second n – 2 points, the third n – 3 points, and so on. The least preferred option scores zero. The Borda counts for preferences shown in Table4 are given in Table6. The Borda tally aggregates individual preferences to generate the group’s preferences. The tallies in Table6 suggest the ranks R = (A1 > A2 > A3).
Table 6.
A1 | A2 | A3 | |
---|---|---|---|
I1 | 2 | 1 | 0 |
I2 | 1 | 0 | 2 |
I3 | 1 | 2 | 0 |
Tally | 4 | 3 | 2 |
The Borda count has been used to aggregate preferences in many contexts (Black 1958; Hwang & Lin 1987). Kijazi and Kant (2010) used a Borda count to establish group preferences for alternatives for forest use on Mount Kilimanjaro. Laukkanen et al. (2005) and Hiltunen et al. (2008) evaluated group preferences for forest management plans in Finland, applying several voting methods including the Borda count. Laukkanen et al. (2005) asked individuals to provide an ordering of forest plans on each of several criteria with approval voting and then used the Borda count to combine individual preferences into a group ordering.
Condorcet Functions
A Condorcet winner has the appealing property that it is preferred to any other alternative by a majority of the voters (see Elkind et al. 2011). Condorcet functions find the preferred alternative by examining all pairwise comparisons of alternatives for each individual (a total of n × (n – 1)/2 comparisons for n alternatives). Each individual votes on each comparison. The score for an alternative is given by the number of times it is ranked higher than another. That is, Oi(Aj, Ak) = 1 if and only if Aj ≻i Ak and O(Aj) is summed over n alternatives and m individuals:
2 |
For example, Table7 gives the preferences of 4 individuals for 3 alternatives. The resulting table of ordinal preferences, O, and resulting Condorcet scores are given in Table8. The O(A1) is the sum of columns O(A1, A2), and O(A1, A3) = 6, O(A2) = 2, and O(A3) = 3 so that R = (A1 > A3 > A2).
Table 7.
A1 | A2 | A3 | |
---|---|---|---|
I1 | 1 | 3 | 2 |
I2 | 1 | 3 | 2 |
I3 | 3 | 1 | 3 |
I4 | 1 | 3 | 2 |
Table 8.
O | O | O | O | O | O | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
(A1, A2) | (A1, A3) | (A2, A1) | (A2, A3) | (A3, A1) | (A3, A2) | |
I1 | 1 | 1 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 1 |
I2 | 1 | 1 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 1 |
I3 | 0 | 0 | 1 | 1 | 0 | 0 |
I4 | 1 | 1 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 1 |
Tallies | 3 | 3 | 1 | 1 | 0 | 3 |
Ghanbarpour et al. (2005) and Zendehdel et al. (2010) used a Condorcet function to aggregate group opinions about management alternatives for a watershed in Iran. Pairwise procedures such as the Condorcet function ignore portions of the information that are used by other procedures such as the Borda count and preferential voting. Of course, simple majority voting ignores even more.
Other Functions
Many other voting systems have been developed. They have not been used widely for environmental decision making, but we document them so that readers may pursue them if they require a particular feature for a specific context.
Variants of the Condorcet function, including Copeland’s function (Hwang & Lin 1987), select alternatives based on pairwise comparisons, their differences depending on the form of the comparisons (e.g., Craven 1992; Risse 2001). Dodgson’s (1876) function orders alternatives according to the number of pairwise comparisons that would require alteration for an alternative to be preferred to all others (Hwang & Lin 1987; Elkind et al. 2011).
In the Hare system, sometimes called 2-stage plurality, individuals cast one vote for one alternative. These are tabulated and the alternative with the smallest tally is removed from A. This process is repeated until one alternative remains. Hare voting requires that votes be tallied and results disseminated before another round of voting can take place, significantly increasing the complexity of the voting process.
Nanson’s (1883) function identifies preferences through iterative application of the Borda count (Hwang & Lin 1987). Alternatives with the lowest Borda count are sequentially eliminated until a set of alternatives with the same Borda count remains. Group preferences derived from Nanson’s function may differ from those derived from simple Borda counts.
Fishburn’s (1977) function gives a group preference A1 > A2 if and only if A1 outscores or ties A2 by simple majority and A1 outscores or ties at least one other alternative that outscores A2. Kemeny’s (1959) function scores alternatives by the number of times each is ranked higher than another. Its goal is to maximize the agreement between final group preferences and individual voters’ preferences; matrix algebra is used to find a solution (Fishburn 1977; Hwang & Lin 1987). It is considered far too complex for many voters to understand.
Some systems allocate multiple votes to each individual. If individuals may allocate multiple votes to a single alternative if they strongly prefer it (e.g., Mendoza & Prabhu 2009), the method is equivalent to assigning weights rather than voting. This is sometimes called cumulative voting. New voting systems continue to be developed. The examples outlined here illustrate the richness of potential approaches.
Individual preferences can be expressed by the strength of preferences among alternatives (sometimes called cardinal data). Data on preference strengths can be collected via focus groups, deliberative multicriteria analysis, or remotely via surveys of stated preferences or willingness to pay (e.g., Saaty 1980; Gregory & Keeney 2002; Chee 2004). These methods often require travel and face-to-face workshops, extensive sampling protocols, or complex question formats. Cost and fatigue can make these systems impractical.
Do the Differences Matter?
As illustrated above, counter-intuitive and even unintended outcomes are possible when voting methods are applied unthinkingly. Riker (1982), Poundstone (2008), and others argue that because all voting procedures have at least one serious flaw and opportunities for strategic manipulation are ubiquitous, voting results cannot express collective opinion. The list of important properties of voting systems in Table9 is incomplete, but even so, no method satisfies them all.
Table 9.
Voting system | |||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Simple | |||||
Criteria | Majority | Approval | Preference | Borda | Condorcet |
Condorcet winner is chosen | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 1 |
Monotonicity | 1 | 1 | 0 | 1 | 1 |
Pareto optimality | 1 | 0 | 1 | 1 | 1 |
Consistentency | 1 | 1 | 0 | 1 | 0 |
Independence | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 | 0 |
Invulnerability | 1 | 1 | 0 | 1 | 0 |
Majority winner | 1 | 0 | 1 | 0 | 1 |
Numbers: 1, system satisfies the criterion; 0, system violates criterion.
Independence of irrelevant alternatives.
Invulnerability to no-show paradox.
Arrow’s theorem applies to open and secret ballots, even when voters are unaware they are voting, such as when they reveal preferences through their purchases (French 1986). Saari (2001) notes that the same problems arise when individuals make choices based on a number of independent and incommensurate criteria, as is commonplace in conservation management. Consider an example in which a manager is required to select a conservation reserve from among 4 areas that contain 4 threatened species, 3 threatened communities, and 4 important ecosystem services. A field survey results in the data in Table10.
Table 10.
Measure | Area A | Area B | Area C | Area D |
---|---|---|---|---|
Populations of threatened species 1 | 0 | 20 | 10 | 80 |
Populations of threatened species 2 | 4 | 0 | 3 | 2 |
Populations of threatened species 3 | 30 | 20 | 18 | 12 |
Populations of threatened species 4 | 2 | 9 | 8 | 15 |
Extent of threatened ecosystem 1 | 400 | 50 | 80 | 100 |
Extent of threatened ecosystem 2 | 7 | 0 | 2 | 3 |
Extent of threatened ecosystem 3 | 0 | 25 | 30 | 10 |
Index of water quality | 3 | 7 | 8 | 5 |
Index of cultural value | 4 | 8 | 6 | 10 |
Index of pollination services | 44 | 80 | 60 | 100 |
Tourism revenue | 8 | 5 | 2 | 1 |
Units of measure: threatened species, number of adults; ecosystem extent, hectares; ecosystem services, constructed scales; tourism revenue, millions of dollars per annum. The units are omitted on the table to emphasize interest only in rank of each option for each criterion.
The scores for the 11 criteria generate a rank order for the manager’s preference for each reserve. There is no clear winner over all criteria, and no clear loser, so the manager cannot eliminate any dominated alternatives. A natural approach is to select the ‘best of the best’ (Saari, 2001), where the manager finds the top-ranked alternative for each criterion and selects the option ranked best most often. This is equivalent to plurality voting.
The manager’s objective may be to avoid making a bad choice on any of the criteria. One way of doing so awards votes to an option if it is either first or second on each criterion. This is equivalent to approval voting. Alternatively, the manager may wish to account for all attributes in a balanced fashion, awarding 3 votes to the best option, 2 to the second best option, and 1 to the third best option for each criterion. This is equivalent to Borda count. In this hypothetical but quite realistic example, area A is chosen under a plurality vote, area B is chosen under an approval vote, and area D is chosen under a Borda count or preferential vote.
There are several problems with Table9 as a basis for choosing a voting system. First, it is not comprehensive about what is good in a system. Some of these other attributes have been outlined in the preceding discussion. Second, the criteria are not equally important or independent. For example, the Condorcet winner criterion is strictly incompatible with the consistency criterion (Young 1974 in Nurmi 2012). Perhaps most importantly, the potential for violations of the criteria says nothing about how likely these violations are to arise in particular circumstances in which the system is used.
Assessing the likelihood of violations can be difficult because it relies on assumptions about the distributions and independence of preferences (see Nurmi 2012). In general, though, given strong preferences (full ordering of preferences), a small numbers of voters (less than about 10) or many alternatives (more than about 10), as might happen in a small committee, it is likely the Condorcet system will not produce a preferred alternative. The probabilities of intransitive outcomes are even greater than failing to find a Condorcet winner (Klahr 1966; Jones et al. 1995). In contrast, such problems are unlikely to arise if there are many voters with weak preferences (such that individuals may be indifferent to some alternatives), few alternatives (Jones et al. 1995), a few relatively strong candidates (Tangian 2000), or coalitions of voters with similar preferences (Nurmi 2012).
All voting rules are susceptible to strategic manipulation to greater or lesser degrees (Satterthwaite 1975). People designing voting systems may manipulate outcomes by including alternatives so that votes for a preferred alternative are split among 2 or more similar alternatives (Gibbard 1973). It may be in the best interests of a voter to vote for an alternative other than the one they prefer most, or not to vote at all, to secure their desired result (Kangas & Kangas 2002). A major drawback of simple majority voting, for example, is that it is relatively easy to manipulate by introducing irrelevant alternatives (Lehtinen 2008). Consider the preferences in Table11 (derived from Table2). Under simple majority voting, A2 is selected (decision 1). A person who controls the design of the voting system may have a personal preference for A1. If they know the likely distribution of votes among the alternatives, they may add another alternative with attributes similar to A2, in which case A1 would be selected if votes were now distributed evenly across A2 and the new alternative (decision 2).
Table 11.
A1 | A2 | A3 | |
---|---|---|---|
Decision 1 | 4 | 5 | |
Decision 2 | 4 | 2 | 3 |
Strategic voting and coalitions have been explored at length in political science (see Taylor 1995; Hodge & Klima 2005). Generally, manipulation requires the system designer or the voter to know about other voters’ preferences. Voters with more information have more power. For instance, approval voting is more difficult to manipulate than simple majority voting because it requires additional information about the distribution of approvals (Lepelley & Valognes 2003). Thomas et al. (2010) showed how strategic voting behavior may evolve over time into special interest-driven voting blocks that “capture” state agencies, leading to decisions about the environment by public regulatory agencies that accord with commercial or recreational interests.
Discussion
Many decisions in conservation biology and environmental science involve reconciling disparate, competing objectives and thus may be viewed as attempts to maximize net social welfare. We described the characteristics of some common voting systems and outlined examples from environmental science and conservation biology. Most of the application papers that we reviewed merely described the voting system used, without justifying its selection.
As noted above, characteristics of voting systems that may be crucial weaknesses in one situation may be irrelevant in another. Although comprehensive analysis of the strengths and weaknesses of different voting systems is complex (Elkind et al. 2011; Nurmi 2012), it is possible to compare the behavior of candidate systems in particular circumstances using simulations (Gavish & Gerdes 1997). People designing or choosing voting systems might use simulations to anticipate potential manipulations and implement measures to mitigate them, if such manipulative voting strategies are judged unfair.
Voting systems embody different philosophies. For example, winners under Condorcet voting can defeat every other alternative in pairwise contests. They almost always win under approval voting. However, under preferential voting, they often lose because they split the vote with one or more moderate alternatives. A Condorcet winner may be defeated through manipulation by individual voters or coalitions of voters. Approval voting, however, ensures the election of a Condorcet winner, encouraging sincere voting (Brams & Sanver 2006).
Preferential voting encourages honest support for alternatives that are unlikely to succeed. In simple majority voting, in contrast, voters may decide against voting for their preferred candidate if they are unlikely to win, believing their vote would be effectively wasted. Instead, they may vote for a generally more favored alternative, rather than risk a much less preferred alternative being selected. That is, people may use knowledge about the preferences of other voters to make strategic voting decisions. Preferential voting takes the full order of preferences into account. If a person’s first preference is eliminated early, their vote is reallocated to their second preference. People do not have to anticipate the favored alternatives to be sure their preferences will count in determining the final outcome (Brams 2004).
The myriad properties and sensitivities of alternative voting systems raise the important question, what are the qualities of a desirable outcome? Do we prefer to come away with everyone moderately pleased, or some people very pleased and others disgruntled? As previously noted, every voting system has at least one flaw. Many people, including those engaged in environmental decision making, trust voting systems to aggregate preferences fairly. Yet, most people are unaware that the outcome of voting may be determined by interactions between properties of the system and strategic behavior of other voters. Every voting system may seem unfair, at least in some circumstances. The people responsible for designing voting systems should be explicit about their choice, the possibilities of counterintuitive outcomes, and its susceptibility to strategic manipulation.
If one were to abandon voting, the only realistic option would be to ask for more information, that is, cardinal, rather than ordinal, preferences, expressing how much one alternative is preferred over another. Measures of individual benefit, equity, or efficiency of social welfare avoid many of the difficulties that arise in voting systems (Sen 1999). For example, Chakravarty and Kaplan (2010) outline circumstances in which it may be preferable to allow people to express how much they care about an alternative and to have the strength of the preference contribute to the outcome. One may elicit cardinal preferences and combine them in a number of ways. However, it is unclear to what extent such systems satisfy a range of relevant, desirable criteria equivalent to those that apply to voting systems (Nurmi 2012). And as noted above, they may be costly and time consuming. In a rare example, Phillips et al. (2010) considered a case like that outlined in Table10 and evaluated a suite of quantitative systems against a set of desirable properties. Many more such studies are required.
For environmental decisions involving multiple stakeholders, voting systems can be effective tools for policy makers to generate group decisions from individual preferences. It is clear from this review that the choice of voting system involves social judgments about what sort of voting system is most fair. Participants in environmental decision making groups should have the opportunity to scrutinize alternative voting systems before one is chosen.
Acknowledgments
We wish to thank A. Moffat for comments on the manuscript and his substantial efforts in compiling and summarizing relevant papers in the early part of this project, and J. Dyer for his comments and discussion. We are grateful to C. Thompson for his comments on drafts of the manuscript and to W. Sutherland for his discussion of the implications of the voting systems. This work was conducted as part of the Decision Making for Complex Environmental Problems Working Group supported by the National Center for Ecological Analysis and Synthesis (NCEAS), a center funded by the NSF (grant DEB-0553768), the University of California Santa Barbara, and the State of California.
Literature Cited
- Armbruster W. Boge W. Efficient, anonymous, and neutral group decisions. Econimetrica. 1983;51:1389–1405. [Google Scholar]
- Arrow K. Social choice and individual values. New York: Wiley; 1951. [Google Scholar]
- Black D. The theory of committees and elections. London, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press; 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Brams SJ. Approval voting. In: Rowley C, Schneider F, editors. The encyclopedia of public choice. Dordrecht: Kluwer; 2004. pp. 344–346. DOI: 10.1007/978-0-306-47828-4_34. [Google Scholar]
- Brams SJ. Sanver MR. Critical strategies under approval voting: who gets ruled in and ruled out. Electoral Studies. 2006;25:287–305. [Google Scholar]
- Brown LE, et al. Priority water research questions as determined by UK practitioners and policy makers. Science of the Total Environment. 2010;409:256–266. doi: 10.1016/j.scitotenv.2010.09.040. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Burgman MA. Risks and decisions for conservation and environmental management. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Burgman MA, Carr A, Godden L, Gregory R, McBride M, Flander L. Maguire LA. Redefining expertise and improving ecological judgment. Conservation Letters. 2011;4:81–87. [Google Scholar]
- Chakravarty S. Kaplan TR. Vote or shout. The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics. 2010;10(1) Article 42. Available from www.bepress.com/bejte/vol10/iss1/art42. [Google Scholar]
- Chee YE. An ecological perspective on the valuation of ecosystem services. Biological Conservation. 2004;120:549–565. [Google Scholar]
- Cooke RM. Experts in uncertainty: opinion and subjective probability in science. New York: Oxford University Press; 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Craven J. Social choice: a framework for collective decision and individual judgments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Dicks LV, Showler DA. Sutherland WJ. Bee conservation: evidence for the effects of interventions. Pelagic Publications, Exeter; 2010. [Google Scholar]
- Dodgson CL. The theory of committees and elections. London, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press; 1876. A method of taking votes on more than two issues. Reprinted in Black, D. 1958. [Google Scholar]
- Elkind E, Faliszewski P. Slinko A. In: Homogeneity and monotonicity of distance-rationalizable voting rules. Tumer K, Yolum P, Sonenberg L, Stone P, editors; Taiwan: Taipei; 2011. pp. 821–828. Proceedings of the 10th International Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems. [Google Scholar]
- Fishburn PC. Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics. 1977;33:469–489. [Google Scholar]
- Fishburn PC. Brams SJ. Paradoxes of preferential voting. Mathematics Magazine. 1983;56:207–214. [Google Scholar]
- French S. Decision theory: an introduction to the mathematics of rationality. Chichester, United Kingdom: Ellis Horwood; 1986. [Google Scholar]
- Gehrlein WV. Condorcet’s paradox. Theory and Decision. 1983;15:161–197. [Google Scholar]
- Ghanbarpour MR, Hipel KW. Abbaspour KC. Prioritizing long-term watershed management strategies using group decision analysis. International Journal of Water Resources Development. 2005;21:297–309. [Google Scholar]
- Gibbard A. Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica. 1973;41:587–601. [Google Scholar]
- Gavish B. Gerdes JH. Voting mechanisms and their implications in a GDSS environment. Annals of Operations Research. 1997;71:41–74. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory RS. Keeney RL. Making smarter environmental management decisions. Journal of the American Water Resources Association. 2002;38:1601–1612. [Google Scholar]
- Hämäläinen R, Kettunen E, Marttunun M. Ehtamo H. Evaluating a framework for multi-stakeholder decision support in water resources management. Group Decisions and Negotiation. 2001;10:331–353. [Google Scholar]
- Hiltunen V, Kangas J. Pykalainen J. Voting methods in strategic forest planning—experiences from Metsahallitus. Forest Policy and Economics. 2008;10:117–127. [Google Scholar]
- Hodge JK. Klima RE. The mathematics of voting and elections: a hands-on approach. Providence, RI: American Mathematical Society; 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Hwang CL. Lin M. Group decision-making: mathematical models. Berlin: Springer-Verlag; 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Jones B, Radcliff B, Taber C. Timpone R. Condorcet winners and the paradox of voting: probability calculations for weak preference orders. American Political Science Review. 1995;89:137–144. [Google Scholar]
- Kangas J. Kangas A. Multiple criteria decision support methods in forest management. In: Pukkala T, editor; Multi-objective forest management, chapter 3. Netherlands: Kluwer; 2002. pp. 37–70. [Google Scholar]
- Kangas A, Laukkanen S. Kangas J. Social choice theory and its applications in sustainable forest management—a review. Forest Policy and Economics. 2006;9:77–92. [Google Scholar]
- Keeney R. Value-focused thinking: a path to creative decision making. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Kemeny J. Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus. 1959;88:577–591. [Google Scholar]
- Kerr NL. Tindale RS. Small group decision making and performance. Annual Review of Psychology. 2004;55:623–656. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kijazi MH. Kant S. Forest stakeholders’ value preferences in Mount Kilimanjaro, Tanzania. Forest Policy and Economics. 2010;12:357–369. [Google Scholar]
- Klahr D. A computer simulation of the paradox of voting. American Political Science Review. 1966;60:384–390. [Google Scholar]
- Laukkanen S, Palander T, Kangas J. Kangas A. Evaluation of the multicriteria approval method for timber-harvesting group decision support. Silva Fenn. 2005;39:249–264. [Google Scholar]
- Leal CP, Quinones RA. Chavez C. What factors affect the decision making process when setting TACs?: The case of Chilean fisheries. Marine Policy. 2010;34:1183–1195. [Google Scholar]
- Lehtinen A. The welfare consequences of strategic behaviour under approval and plurality voting. European Journal of Political Economy. 2008;24:688–704. [Google Scholar]
- Lepelley D. Valognes F. Voting rules, manipulability and social homogeneity. Public Choice. 2003;116:165–184. [Google Scholar]
- McNeill J. Turland NJ. The conservation of Acacia with Acacia penninervis as conserved type. Taxon. 2010;59:613–616. [Google Scholar]
- Maguire LA. What can decision analysis do for invasive species management? Risk Analysis. 2004;24:859–868. doi: 10.1111/j.0272-4332.2004.00484.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Marcot BG, Hohenlohe PA, Morey S, Holmes R, Molina R, Turley MC, Huff MH. Laurence JA. Characterizing species at risk II: Using Bayesian Belief Networks as decision support tools to determine species conservation categories under the Northwest Forest Plan. Ecology and Society. 2006;11:12. Available from http://www.ecologyandsociety.org/vol11/iss2/art12/ [Google Scholar]
- Mendoza GA. Prabhu R. Evaluating multi-stakeholder perceptions of project impacts: a participatory value based multi-criteria approach. International Journal of Sustainable Development and World Ecology. 2009;16:177–190. [Google Scholar]
- Morgan MG. Henrion M. Uncertainty: a guide to dealing with uncertainty in quantitative risk and policy analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Morton SR, et al. The big ecological questions inhibiting effective environmental management in Australia. Austral Ecology. 2009;34:1–9. [Google Scholar]
- Nanson EJ. Methods of election. Transactions and Proceedings of the Royal Society of Victoria. 1883;19:197–240. [Google Scholar]
- Nurmi H. On the relevance of theoretical results to voting system choice. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M, editors. Electoral systems. Berlin: Springer; 2012. pp. 255–274. Studies in choice and welfare, chapter 10. [Google Scholar]
- Patterson J, Meek ME, Strawson JE. Liteplo RG. Engaging expert peers in the development of risk assessments. Risk Analysis. 2007;27:1609–1621. doi: 10.1111/j.1539-6924.2007.00992.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Phillips SJ, Archer A, Pressey RL, Torkornoo D, Applegate D, Johnson D. Watts MW. Voting power and target-based site prioritization. Biological Conservation. 2010;143:1989–1997. [Google Scholar]
- Poundstone W. Gaming the vote: why elections aren't fair (and what we can do about it) New York: Hill and Wang; 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Richelson JT. A comparative analysis of social choice functions IV. Behavioral Science. 1981;26:346–353. [Google Scholar]
- Riker W. Liberalism against Populism: a confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman; 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Risse M. Arrow’s theorem, indeterminacy, and multiplicity reconsidered. Ethics. 2001;111:706–734. [Google Scholar]
- Saari DG. Decisions and elections: explaining the unexpected. Cambridge, United Kingdom: University of Cambridge Press; 2001. [Google Scholar]
- Saaty TL. The analytic hierarchy process. New York: McGraw Hill; 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Satterthwaite M. Strategy proofness and Arrow’s conditions. Journal of Economic Theory. 1975;10:187–217. [Google Scholar]
- Sen A. The possibility of social choice. American Economic Review. 1999;89:349–378. [Google Scholar]
- Slovic P. Trust, emotion, sex, politics, and science: surveying the risk-assessment battlefield. Risk Analysis. 1999;19:689–701. doi: 10.1023/a:1007041821623. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Sutherland WJ, et al. One hundred questions of importance to the conservation of global biological diversity. Conservation Biology. 2009;23:557–567. doi: 10.1111/j.1523-1739.2009.01212.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tangian AS. Unlikelihood of Condorcet’s paradox in a large society. Social Welfare and Choice. 2000;17:337–365. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor AD. Mathematics and politics: strategy, voting, power and proof. New York: Springer-Verlag; 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas CW, Soule AB. Davis TB. Special interest capture of regulatory agencies: a ten-year analysis of voting behavior on regional fishery management councils. Policy Studies Journal. 2010;38:447–464. [Google Scholar]
- Tisdell C, Wilson C. Nantha HS. Public choice of species for the ‘Ark’: Phylogenetic similarity and preferred wildlife species for survival. Journal for Nature Conservation. 2006;14:97–105. [Google Scholar]
- Vignola R, McDaniels TL. Scholz RW. Negotiation analysis for mechanisms to deliver ecosystem services: The case of soil conservation in Costa Rica. Ecological Economics. 2012;75:22–31. [Google Scholar]
- Williams PD. The greening of the Queensland electorate? Australian Journal of Political Science. 2006;41:325–337. [Google Scholar]
- Zendehdel K, Rademaker M, De Baets B. Van Huylenbroeck G. Environmental decision making with conflicting social groups: a case study of the Lar rangeland in Iran. Journal of Arid Environments. 2010;74:394–402. [Google Scholar]