Summary
In clinical practice, and in the medical literature, severe congenital malformations such as trisomy 18, anencephaly, and renal agenesis are frequently referred to as ‘lethal’ or as ‘incompatible with life’. However, there is no agreement about a definition of lethal malformations, nor which conditions should be included in this category. Review of outcomes for malformations commonly designated ‘lethal’ reveals that prolonged survival is possible, even if rare. This article analyses the concept of lethal malformations and compares it to the problematic concept of ‘futility’. We recommend avoiding the term ‘lethal’ and suggest that counseling should focus on salient prognostic features instead. For conditions with a high chance of early death or profound impairment in survivors despite treatment, perinatal and neonatal palliative care would be ethical. However, active obstetric and neonatal management, if desired, may also sometimes be appropriate.
Keywords: Infant, Newborn, Fatal outcome, Ethics, Medical futility, Trisomy, Fetal termination
1. Introduction
Antenatal screening, particularly the use of routine mid-trimester ultrasound screening, has altered the diagnosis of major congenital malformations. As a result, in many parts of the world it is now uncommon for major malformations to be discovered at birth [1]. Antenatal diagnosis potentially allows targeted diagnostic testing, planning of delivery, counseling and education of couples, and earlier postnatal intervention for newborns with congenital malformations [2]. However, antenatal diagnosis may identify severe abnormalities where treatment is unavailable, or unlikely to be successful, and where fetal or neonatal death is a likely outcome. Such cases are often referred to as ‘lethal malformation’ (LM) (Box 1).
Box 1. Malformations most frequently described as ‘lethal’ conditions [9].
Potter's syndrome/renal agenesis
Anencephaly/acrania
Thanatophoric dwarfism
Trisomy 13 or 18
Holoprosencephaly
The diagnosis of LM is often said to carry ethical and legal implications for management during pregnancy, delivery, and postnatally [3–6]. For example, it may permit obstetric management focused on maternal well-being rather than on fetal survival, termination of pregnancy (including late in pregnancy), or non-resuscitation at birth [7]. But what do we mean when we refer to a malformation as ‘lethal’? Which conditions fit into this category? What are the ethical implications of diagnosis of LM?
2. The concept of ‘lethal malformation’
The word ‘lethal’ is derived from the Latin ‘letalis’ (deadly), and related to a Greek word meaning ‘oblivion,’ referring to the myth that the souls of the dead forgot their lives on Earth after drinking the waters of the River Lethe. Conventionally, ‘lethal’ is used to describe something (e.g. an action or agent) that will cause death [8].
In theory, there are several different ways to interpret the description of a malformation as lethal (Box 2).
Box 2. Possible definitions of a ‘lethal congenital malformation’.
1. Fetal death: a condition that invariably leads to death in-utero
2. Fetal death/neonatal death: a condition that invariably leads to death either in utero or in the newborn period regardless of treatment
3. Usual fetal/neonatal death: a condition that leads to death in utero or in the newborn period in most cases
4. Associated with death: a condition that leads to fetal or neonatal death in some cases
A review of the published literature on LM revealed no consensus on which of these definitions should be applied [9]. The first definition does not apply to any of the commonly cited LMs, and is not one found in the literature. The second definition is probably the most plausible and the most frequently encountered [5,10–13]. Chervenak and McCullough endorse this definition: ‘a lethal condition, properly understood, invariably leads to death, i.e., there is no effective treatment that will prevent a condition, disease, or injury from causing death in the near future’ [14]. However, this definition does not apply to any of the malformations that are often described as lethal. Some papers have used the third definition [15–18]. This raises a question about how high a chance of death is sufficient to fit into a lethal category. The cited proportion ranges from 50% to ‘almost all’ [16,19]. There is neither agreement about the correct proportion, nor any obvious way to determine where the cut-off should lie. The fourth definition is used in some epidemiologic studies of neonatal mortality [20–22]. However, it appears far too broad to correspond to the way that LM is used by obstetricians and neonatologists.
3. Which malformations are lethal?
Although Box 1 lists the most frequently cited LMs, more than 25 conditions are included in different lists [9]. No condition was present on all lists, and there was considerable variation.
What is the outcome for these malformations? Table 1 presents an attempt to estimate outcome; however, the values cited are necessarily imprecise. High proportions of affected pregnancies are terminated [47]. Since these conditions are associated with high fetal death rate, survival rate also varies with the gestational age at the time of diagnosis. Postnatal survival is also difficult to estimate because of selection bias in published cohorts, and because of the problem of self-fulfilling prophecies [48,49]. Where a large proportion of infants receive palliative care after birth, a high mortality rate is inevitable [9].
Table 1.
Severe congenital anomalies | Prevalence | Probability of live birth (in absence of termination) | Median postnatal survival | Proportion surviving >1 week/>1 year | Longest reported survivals |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Renal agenesis | 1.7/10,000 [23] | Not reported | <24 h [23] | <5% | 13 months [97,98] |
Anencephaly | 10/10,000 pregnancies 2.6/10,000 births [24] |
62–72% [25,26] |
<24 h [26,27] 55 min [28] |
0–14%>1 week/7% >1 year [18,29] | 10 months [30] 2.5 years [31] |
Thanatophoric dysplasia | 0.4/10,000 [32] | Not reported | Not reported | Not reported | 5 years [33] 9 years [34] |
Trisomy 18 | 2.6/10,000 [24] | 48–51% [35,36] | 14 days [37] | 35–65%>1 week/14–19% >1 year [18,29] | 27 years [38] 30 years [39] 50 years [40] |
Trisomy 13 | 1.2/10,000 [24] | 28–46% [35,36] | 10 days [37] | 45–57%>1 week/14–21% >1 year [18,29] | 19 year [41] 27 year [42] |
Holoprosencephaly | 0.5/10,000 [43] | Not reported | 4–5 months [44] | 71%>1 week/ 47% >1 year [29] | 6 years [45] 11 years [44] 13 years [43] 19 years [46] |
Using recent population cohort studies where available.
What is clear from Table 1 is that survival of at least six months has been described in all of the conditions frequently cited as lethal. Most strikingly, this includes both anencephaly and bilateral renal agenesis. There has been a very recently published case report of an infant in the USA with Potter syndrome who was treated with antenatal amnio-infusion and neonatal renal dialysis and who survived to be listed for renal transplantation at one year of age.
4. The significance of a ‘lethal diagnosis’: the examples of trisomy 18 and 13
The severe autosomal trisomies, 18 (Edwards syndrome; T18) and 13 (Patau syndrome; T13), are frequently described as lethal [18,50–53]. Yet, recent population cohort studies show that more than half of affected live-born infants survive for more than a week, and up to 20% survive for more than a year [18,29]. In a large US series including 52,262 very low birth weight infants, 11% of infants with T13 and 9% of infants with T18 survived to discharge [54]. It is possible that even these values represent an underestimate of potential survival rates, since in parts of the world where cardiac surgery is offered to infants with T13 or T18, one-year survival rates as high as 50% have been reported [55].
Why does it matter if these conditions are described as lethal? The first reason to be concerned about this terminology is its potential for misunderstanding and miscommunication. We surveyed more than 1000 obstetricians from the UK, Australia, and New Zealand about the perinatal management of T18 [56]. The overwhelming majority (85%) of obstetricians regarded T18 as a lethal malformation. More than 50% regarded T18 as ‘incompatible with life’. We did not ask obstetricians whether they would use these terms in counseling, but a survey of parents from T13/T18 support groups found that 93% had been told by health professionals that their child's condition was ‘lethal or incompatible with life’ [57]. This contrasts with the evidence summarized above, and with obstetricians' own understanding about survival. Three-quarters of respondents estimated that at least 5% of affected infants would survive for more than one year if treatment were provided [56].
Qualitative studies and narratives from parents of infants with T13 or T18 describe feelings of anger and disillusionment and a sense of being misled by health professionals as well as by the language used [58–61]. Many parents reported that health care providers were unable to look beyond adverse statistics [57]. Furthermore, the Internet has provided families with the ability to do their own research and encounter alternate perspectives on their child's condition. Within seconds of searching for ‘trisomy 18’ a parent may see pictures of many older children with trisomy 18, smiling and happy, strong evidence against ‘incompatibility with life’. If they have been told by their doctor that trisomy 18 is always lethal, there may be repercussions for the family's ongoing capacity to trust health professionals [44].
Another reason to be concerned about denoting a condition such as T18 as ‘lethal’ is because of a worry that this language contains concealed value judgments about the quality of life of surviving infants [31,49]. Eighty percent of obstetricians in our survey believed that T18 was not compatible with a ‘meaningful life’ [56]. Labeling a condition as ‘lethal’ may also risk taking decision-making from the parents [31,49]. In our survey, 23% of obstetricians would never discuss or offer fetal monitoring in labour for women after an antenatal diagnosis of T18, and 28% would never offer caesarean section for fetal distress [56]. In the parent-support group study, two-thirds of parents reported feeling pressure to terminate their pregnancy [57].
There is a concept in medical ethics that shares some features with that of LM: the concept of ‘medical futility’ [9,19]. Medical futility emerged in the 1990s as a potential way to resolve disputes between patients and doctors about life-sustaining treatment [62]. It reflected a perceived need by medical professionals to limit patient autonomy and to justify a decision not to provide treatment that had been requested [62]. The basic idea was that although it was important to respect patients' views about treatment, health professionals were not obligated to provide futile treatment [63]. However, the concept of futility has fallen out of favour because of a number of serious problems in parallel with the concept of LM [64,65].
First, there is a problem with defining futility. There have been at least five different definitions proposed, and no agreement on which should be used [64]. Some authors distinguish quantitative from qualitative futility [63]. Treatment is quantitatively futile if it has a very low chance of success. However, just as for the third definition of LM, there is a problem with determining where the statistical threshold should lie. Is a 90% chance of death high enough, or should it be 95% or 99%? Trisomy 13/18 might appear lethal on some definitions, but not others.
Second, even if a particular statistical threshold is used, there is a problem with determining whether treatment would actually be futile in an individual case. Even if treatment has not succeeded in the past, there may have been technological changes that could potentially improve survival. There may be specific features for an individual patient that distinguish him from aggregated cohorts. (For example, a fetus with T18 might have a structurally normal heart and appear to have better prognosis, or might have hypoplastic left heart and have a much worse prognosis than average [66].) Often there are limited data on which to base a prognosis. The problem of self-fulfilling prophecies means that available data may not be representative of actual chances of survival if treatment were provided [48].
Third, the clearest and strictest available definition appears to exclude almost all actual cases. Treatment is said to be ‘physiologically futile’ if there is no way for it to achieve its physiologic aim [62]. For example, cardio-pulmonary resuscitation would be physiologically futile if there were literally no ability for it to restore circulation and breathing. Analogously, a condition might be denoted lethal (using the second definition) if survival is impossible regardless of treatment. However, either of these definitions appears to render the concept relevant only in extremely rare cases, and certainly not in T13 or T18.
Fourth, there is a concern that the term ‘futile’, particularly when it is used qualitatively, amounts to ‘giving opinion disguised as data’ [67]. Treatments are described as being ‘qualitatively futile’ when treatment might be able to sustain life but is not perceived to amount to a benefit for the patient. For example, providing intensive care to a patient in a persistent vegetative state has been described as being qualitatively futile [63]. Similarly, some definitions of LM include conditions associated with a persistent vegetative state or absent cognitive development [6,10,68,69]. In our survey of obstetricians, 20% indicated that the best developmental outcome in T18 is a vegetative state [56]. Yet, available data suggest that children with T18 and T13, although usually profoundly impaired, are not vegetative. Surviving children are reported to be aware of those around them, to hear and respond to sound, and to learn and remember [39]. Most are unable to speak, yet are able to communicate non-verbally at a basic level [70]. Whether this level of function is sufficient to outweigh the burdens of treatment constitutes an important ethical question. It may or may not be in the best interests of a child to provide particular treatment given this prognosis [52,68,71]. However, it is clear that this involves a judgment about the value of life in a severely impaired cognitive state. Professional guidelines strongly endorse the idea that counseling following prenatal diagnosis should be non-directive and value neutral [72–74]. Whereas some authors have questioned whether complete neutrality in counseling is possible or desirable [72,75–77], there are good reasons for doctors to aspire to neutrality in most circumstances. One important way to do this is to avoid language that contains implicit value judgments [78].
5. Beyond the concept of ‘lethal malformations’
We have criticized the concept of LM, but what does that mean for counseling or for decision-making?
It might be possible to find an alternative term to describe all of the congenital conditions that are usually referred to as lethal. They appear to share a high chance of death and profound impairment regardless of attempted treatment. We could refer to ‘life-limiting’ conditions [79], ‘poor prognosis’ malformations, or ‘potentially lethal’ [79] malformations. However, any new term will have the same problems of defining the probability and severity of poor outcome that would justify its application. Unless it is a term that parents easily and reliably understand, it will need to be explained. Instead, we have previously suggested that it would be better for counseling to openly and honestly address the key prognostic questions that parents are likely to ask after diagnosis of a severe congenital malformation [9].
-
1.
Diagnosis: what is the diagnosis, and how certain can practitioners be?
-
2.
Neonatal survival: what is the chance of survival past the newborn period if treatments (including intensive life-prolonging therapies) are provided?
-
3.
Long-term survival: how long is the child likely to survive if life-sustaining treatment is provided?
-
4.
Long-term impairment and illness: if the newborn survives, what long-term health problems and impairments are they likely to experience? What is the range of possible outcomes?
-
5.
Burden of treatment: what treatments would be required to keep the newborn infant alive, and how burdensome would these be for the child and the family?
The most important ethical question is what treatment should be offered or provided to women and to fetuses and babies in the setting of severe congenital malformations with a very high chance of death or profound disability despite treatment. We have argued that such malformations should not be called ‘lethal’. However, the label should not change the treatment that is provided. The label that we give to conditions is not ethically relevant to the options that are appropriate. One additional advantage of avoiding the ‘lethal’ designation may be that these conditions are not identical. If we treat each condition (and indeed each child) on its merits, options may be appropriate in some circumstances and not in others.
Which options, then, should be provided to severe malformations such as those in Box 1? For all, the option of palliative care at birth should be given to parents. The high chance of death or profound impairment means that it is questionable whether providing resuscitation and life-prolonging treatment is in the child's best interests [80]. It is critical that high quality palliative care is available to the infant and family [4,81]. It is important, though, to ensure that parents and future parents are aware about variable duration of survival. Provision of palliative care does not necessarily mean that the child will die quickly [82]. Palliative support does not need to be confined to the postnatal period, and there may be considerable benefit to the family by offering a palliative approach from the time of diagnosis, through to delivery, and beyond [3,83,84]. There are perinatal palliative care programs available in an increasing number of centres. A palliative (maternal-focused) approach to obstetric care may mean that it is appropriate to avoid monitoring in labour and to aim for vaginal delivery, if that is consistent with a woman's wishes [6,85–87].
If palliative care is an option, what about the opposite? Should resuscitation and intensive care be an option? Should fetal-oriented obstetric management be available? Here a nuanced answer is needed that takes into account the specifics of each case. Nevertheless, we support the recommendation that an active approach to obstetric management, including fetal monitoring, cesarean section, and resuscitation, may be appropriate even in the face of a high death rate [14,85,88,89]. Such treatment is not contrary to the interests of the child [89]. For some parents, the opportunity to experience some time with their child while s/he is still alive may be extremely important [88]. On the other hand, this does not mean that unlimited treatment should be made available if requested by parents [90]. Invasive and intensive treatment, particularly if prolonged, may not be in the interests of the child in the face of very low chance of benefit. Such treatment may also be unreasonable in the setting of limited public health resources [62]. Health professionals may be justified in declining treatment in such circumstances. However, such decisions must be made on the basis of the child's specific circumstances, and on consistently and transparently applied ethical principles rather than on the basis of a label of ‘lethality’.
What about termination of pregnancy? The diagnosis of LM would make no difference to decisions about termination in jurisdictions that either do not permit termination on fetal grounds, or alternatively that allow access to termination for a broad range of fetal abnormalities. However, in some jurisdictions the diagnosis of a ‘lethal’ malformation may permit termination of pregnancy, even at a gestational age when this would otherwise be prohibited [91]. For example, the Texas Health and Safety Code [92] makes an exception to the prohibition of pregnancy termination after 20 weeks if ‘the fetus has a severe and irreversible abnormality’, defined as ‘a life threatening physical condition that … regardless of the provision of life saving medical treatment, is incompatible with life outside the womb’ [93]. Similarly, the Columbian Penal Code permits termination “when there are serious malformations of the fetus that make the fetus not viable, as certified by a medical doctor’ [94]. The terms ‘not viable’ and ‘incompatible with life’ appear to relate to LM, and might have been intended to refer to conditions listed in Box 1. Yet, the analysis indicates that anencephaly and even bilateral renal agenesis are potentially compatible with long-term survival and are ‘viable’ on strict definitions. If so, women carrying fetuses with LM may be unable to access termination.
It is beyond the scope of this paper to provide a detailed discussion of the legal or ethical approach to abortion law. Nevertheless, it is not our intention to limit women's options. For jurisdictions that regard LM as a special case and wish to allow abortion in such cases, there are perhaps three possibilities. One possibility would be for lawmakers to create specific exceptions for conditions such as those listed above. For example, the Brazilian Supreme Court ruled that termination is permissible after diagnosis of anencephaly (though not in other situations) [95]. Other conditions could be added to this list, although in practice there may be significant hurdles in achieving such a law change. A second possibility would be to leave it to medical professionals to decide which conditions are sufficiently severe to be regarded in law as ‘lethal’ or non-viable. The Columbian constitutional court has ruled that ‘determinations are to be made by medical practitioners acting within the ethical standards of their profession’ [94]. However, the lack of medical consensus about which conditions can and should be considered ‘lethal’ would potentially lead to inconsistent determinations and decision-making [85,96]. A third possibility would be to draft legislation that sets out the specific ethical pre-conditions for permitting termination of pregnancy. For example, Chervenak and McCullough have argued that termination of pregnancy should be permitted in the third trimester for conditions with a high degree of certainty of diagnosis, and ‘a very high probability of either death or survival with severe and irreversible deficit of cognitive developmental capacity’ [7,14]. This would appear to include all of the conditions in Box 1.
6. Conclusions
In this review, we have analysed and criticized the concept of ‘lethal’ congenital malformations. The term is misleading, and potentially leads to miscommunication with families and inconsistent decision-making. None of the malformations frequently described as ‘lethal’ fits with strict definitions of this term. However, even if they are not lethal, the severity of conditions such as anencephaly, renal agenesis, and T13/T18 means that perinatal palliative care, maternal-focused obstetric care, and potentially termination of pregnancy are justified. It may also be appropriate to provide fetal-oriented obstetric care and some life-sustaining treatments for these conditions where this is consistent with a woman's wishes and the child's best interests.
Practice points.
-
•
Survival beyond the newborn period has been described in all of the congenital malformations that are often described as being ‘lethal’.
-
•
The terms ‘lethal malformation’ or ‘incompatible with life’ should be avoided in counseling.
-
•
A palliative approach to management during pregnancy, delivery, and postnatally may be ethically appropriate for fetuses with a very poor prognosis.
-
•
An active approach to obstetric and neonatal care may also be appropriate in these conditions to enable parents to experience some time with their child while alive.
Research directions.
-
•
Research is needed on parental response to language and counseling approaches following diagnosis of severe congenital malformations.
-
•
There are few data on how frequently parents would choose active or palliative approaches to care following diagnosis of severe congenital malformations.
-
•
There is a need to evaluate the impact of antenatal and postnatal decisions on parents' long-term well-being.
Conflict of interest statement
None declared.
Funding sources
This work was supported by a grant from the Wellcome Trust [086041/Z/08/Z]. D.W. was also supported for this work by an early career fellowship from the Australian National Health and Medical Research Council [1016641].
Acknowledgments
We would like to acknowledge Dr Andrew Watkins and Ms Pauline Thiele for their contributions to previous work related to this paper.
References
- 1.Richards D.S. Prenatal ultrasound to detect fetal anomalies. NeoReviews. 2012;13:c9–19. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Lakhoo K. Fetal counselling for surgical conditions. Early Hum Dev. 2012;88:9–13. doi: 10.1016/j.earlhumdev.2011.11.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Bhatia J. Palliative care in the fetus and newborn. J Perinatol. 2006;26(Suppl. 1):S24–S26. doi: 10.1038/sj.jp.7211468. discussion S31–3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Breeze A.C.G., Lees C.C., Kumar A., Missfelder-Lobos H.H., Murdoch E.M. Palliative care for prenatally diagnosed lethal fetal abnormality. Archs Dis Childh Fetal Neonatal Ed. 2007;92:F56–F58. doi: 10.1136/adc.2005.092122. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Catlin A., Carter B. Creation of a neonatal end-of-life palliative care protocol. J Perinatol. 2002;22:184–195. doi: 10.1038/sj.jp.7210687. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Chervenak F.A., McCullough L.B. An ethically justified, clinically comprehensive management strategy for third-trimester pregnancies complicated by fetal anomalies. Obstet Gynecol. 1990;75(3 Pt 1):311–316. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Chervenak F.A., Farley M.A., Walters L., Hobbins J.C., Mahoney M.J. When is termination of pregnancy during the third trimester morally justifiable? N Engl J Med. 1984;310:501–504. doi: 10.1056/NEJM198402233100806. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Oxford English Dictionary online. Oxford University Press; 1989. http://www.oed.com/ [Google Scholar]
- 9.Wilkinson D.J.C., Thiele P., Watkins A., De Crespigny L. Fatally flawed? A review and ethical analysis of lethal congenital malformations. Br J Obstet Gynaecol. 2012;119:1302–1307. doi: 10.1111/j.1471-0528.2012.03450.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.World Health Organization. Basic newborn resuscitation: a practical guide. WHO reference number: WQ 450 98BA 1998 [available at: http://www.who.int/maternal_child_adolescent/documents/who_rht_msm_981/en/].
- 11.Hunfeld J.A.M., Wladimiroff J.W., Passchier J., Uniken Venema-Van Uden M., Frets P.G., Verhage F. Emotional reactions in women in late pregnancy (24 weeks or longer) following the ultrasound diagnosis of a severe or lethal fetal malformation. Prenat Diagn. 1993;13:603–612. doi: 10.1002/pd.1970130711. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Schechtman K.B., Gray D.L., Baty J.D., Rothman S.M. Decision-making for termination of pregnancies with fetal anomalies: analysis of 53,000 pregnancies. Obstet Gynecol. 2002;99:216–222. doi: 10.1016/s0029-7844(01)01673-8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Munson D., Leuthner S.R. Palliative care for the family carrying a fetus with a life-limiting diagnosis. Pediatric Clin North Am. 2007;54:787–798. doi: 10.1016/j.pcl.2007.06.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Chervenak F., McCullough L.B. Responsibly counselling women about the clinical management of pregnancies complicated by severe fetal anomalies. J Med Ethics. 2012;38:397–398. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100491. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Courtwright A.M., Laughon M.M., Doron M.W. Length of life and treatment intensity in infants diagnosed prenatally or postnatally with congenital anomalies considered to be lethal. J Perinatol. 2011;31:387–391. doi: 10.1038/jp.2010.124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Czeizel A.E. First 25 years of the Hungarian congenital abnormality registry. Teratology. 1997;55:299–305. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1096-9926(199705)55:5<299::AID-TERA1>3.0.CO;2-V. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Dommergues M., Mandelbrot L., Mahieu-Caputo D., Boudjema N., Durand-Zaleski I. Termination of pregnancy following prenatal diagnosis in France: how severe are the foetal anomalies? Prenat Diagn. 2010;30:531–539. doi: 10.1002/pd.2510. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Wang Y., Hu J., Druschel C.M., Kirby R.S. Twenty-five-year survival of children with birth defects in New York State: a population-based study. Birth Defects Res A Clin Mol Teratol. 2011;91:995–1003. doi: 10.1002/bdra.22858. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Courtwright A. Who is “too sick to benefit”? Hastings Cent Rep. 2012;42:41–47. doi: 10.1002/hast.51. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Goldenberg R.L., Humphrey J.L., Hale C.B. Lethal congenital anomalies as a cause of birth-weight-specific neonatal mortality. JAMA. 1983;250:513–515. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Milunsky A. Lethal congenital anomalies. JAMA. 1983;250:517–518. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Young I.D., Clarke M. Lethal malformations and perinatal mortality: a 10 year review with comparison of ethnic differences. BMJ. 1987;295:89–91. doi: 10.1136/bmj.295.6590.89. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Cunniff C., Kirby R.S., Senner J.W., Canino C., Brewster M.A., Butler B. Deaths associated with renal agenesis: a population-based study of birth prevalence, case ascertainment, and etiologic heterogeneity. Teratology. 1994;50:200–204. doi: 10.1002/tera.1420500305. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Parker S.E., Mai C.T., Canfield M.A., Rickard R., Wang Y., Meyer R.E. Updated national birth prevalence estimates for selected birth defects in the United States, 2004–2006. Birth Defects Res A Clin Mol Teratol. 2010;88:1008–1016. doi: 10.1002/bdra.20735. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Machado I.N., Martinez S.D., Barini R. Anencephaly: do the pregnancy and maternal characteristics impact the pregnancy outcome? ISRN Obstet Gynecol. 2012;2012:127490. doi: 10.5402/2012/127490. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Jaquier M., Klein A., Boltshauser E. Spontaneous pregnancy outcome after prenatal diagnosis of anencephaly. Br J Obstet Gynaecol. 2006;113:951–953. doi: 10.1111/j.1471-0528.2006.01014.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Kalucy M., Bower C., Stanley F., Burton P. Survival of infants with neural tube defects in Western Australia 1966–1990. Paediatr Perinat Epidemiol. 1994;8:334–351. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-3016.1994.tb00467.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Obeidi N., Russell N., Higgins J.R., O'Donoghue K. The natural history of anencephaly. Prenat Diagn. 2010;30:357–360. doi: 10.1002/pd.2490. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Tennant P.W., Pearce M.S., Bythell M., Rankin J. 20-year survival of children born with congenital anomalies: a population-based study. Lancet. 2010;375:649–656. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61922-X. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.McAbee G., Sherman J., Canas J.A., Boxer H. Prolonged survival of two anencephalic infants. Am J Perinatol. 1993;10:175–177. doi: 10.1055/s-2007-994655. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Koogler T.K., Wilfond B.S., Ross L.F. Lethal language, lethal decisions. Hastings Cent Rep. 2003;33:37–41. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Stevenson D.A., Carey J.C., Byrne J.L.B., Srisukhumbowornchai S., Feldkamp M.L. Analysis of skeletal dysplasias in the Utah population. Am J Med Genet A. 2012;158:1046–1054. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.35327. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.MacDonald I.M., Hunter A.G.W., MacLeod P.M., MacMurray S.B. Growth and development in thanatophoric dysplasia. Am J Med Genet. 1989;33:508–512. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.1320330420. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Baker K.M., Olson D.S., Harding C.O., Pauli R.M. Long-term survival in typical thanatophoric dysplasia type 1. Am J Med Genet. 1997;70:427–436. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Houlihan O.A., O'Donoghue K. The natural history of pregnancies with a diagnosis of trisomy 18 or trisomy 13; a retrospective case series. BMC Pregn Childbirth. 2013;13:209. doi: 10.1186/1471-2393-13-209. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Morris J.K., Sawa G.M. The risk of fetal loss following a prenatal diagnosis of trisomy 13 or trisomy 18. Am J Med Genet. 2008;146A:827–832. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.32220. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Wu J., Springett A., Morris J.K. Survival of trisomy 18 (Edwards syndrome) and trisomy 13 (Patau syndrome) in England and Wales: 2004–2011. Am J Med Genet. 2013;161A:2512–2518. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.36127. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Lebel R.R., Roberson J., Van Dyke D.L. Regarding trisomy 18 [1] Am J Med Genet. 2006;140A:964–965. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.31170. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Fenton L.J. Trisomy 13 and 18 and quality of life: treading “softly”. Am J Med Genet. 2011;155A:1527–1528. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34084. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Bhanumathi B., Goyel N.A., Mishra Z.A. Trisomy 18 in a 50-year-old female. Ind J Hum Genet. 2006;12:146–147. [Google Scholar]
- 41.Redheendran R., Neu R.L., Bannerman R.M. Long survival in trisomy-13 syndrome: 21 cases including prolonged survival in two patients 11 and 19 years old. Am J Med Genet. 1981;8:167–172. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.1320080207. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Tunca Y., Kadandale J., Pivnick E. Long-term survival in Patau syndrome. Clin Dysmorphol. 2001;10:149. doi: 10.1097/00019605-200104000-00014. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Szabó N., Gergev G., Kóbor J., Szucs P., Túri S., Sztriha L. Holoprosencephaly in Hungary: birth prevalence and clinical spectrum. J Child Neurol. 2011;26:1029–1032. doi: 10.1177/0883073811399095. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Barr M., Jr., Cohen M.M., Jr. Holoprosencephaly survival and performance. Am J Med Genet. 1999;89:116–120. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Veneselli E., Biancheri R., Di Rocco M., Fondelli M.P., Perrone M.V., Donati P.T. Unusually prolonged survival and childhood-onset epilepsy in a case of alobar holoprosencephaly. Child's Nerv Syst. 1999;15:274–277. doi: 10.1007/s003810050392. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Stashinko E.E., Clegg N.J., Kammann H.A., Sweet V.T., Delgado M.R., Hahn J.S. A retrospective survey of perinatal risk factors of 104 living children with holoprosencephaly. Am J Med Genet. 2004;128A:114–119. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.30070. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Irving C., Richmond S., Wren C., Longster C., Embleton N.D. Changes in fetal prevalence and outcome for trisomies 13 and 18: a population-based study over 23 years. J Matern Fetal Neonatal Med. 2011;24:137–141. doi: 10.3109/14767051003758879. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Wilkinson D. The self-fulfilling prophecy in intensive care. Theor Med Bioethics. 2009;30:401–410. doi: 10.1007/s11017-009-9120-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.McCaffrey M.J. Lethality begets lethality. J Perinatol. 2011;31:630–631. doi: 10.1038/jp.2011.52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Merritt T.A., Catlin A., Wool C., Peverini R., Goldstein M., Oshiro B. Trisomy 18 and trisomy 13: treatment and management decisions. NeoReviews. 2012;13:e40–e48. [Google Scholar]
- 51.Sibiude J., Gavard L., Floch-Tudal C., Mandelbrot L. Perinatal care and outcome of fetuses with trisomies 13 and 18 following a parental decision not to terminate the pregnancy. Fetal Diagn Ther. 2011;29:233–237. doi: 10.1159/000322133. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Lakovschek I.C., Streubel B., Ulm B. Natural outcome of trisomy 13, trisomy 18, and triploidy after prenatal diagnosis. Am J Med Genet A. 2011;155:2626–2633. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34284. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Burke A.L., Field K., Morrison J.J. Natural history of fetal trisomy 18 after prenatal diagnosis. Archs Dis Child Fetal Neonatal Ed. 2013;98:F152–F154. doi: 10.1136/archdischild-2011-301589. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 54.Boghossian N.S., Hansen NI., Bell EF., Stoll BJ., Murray JC., Carey JC. Mortality and morbidity of VLBW infants with trisomy 13 or trisomy 18. Pediatrics. 2014;133:226–235. doi: 10.1542/peds.2013-1702. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Maeda J., Yamagishi H., Furutani Y., Kamisago M., Waragai T., Oana S. The impact of cardiac surgery in patients with trisomy 18 and trisomy 13 in Japan. Am J Med Genet. 2011;155A:2641–2646. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34285. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 56.Wilkinson D.J., de Crespigny L., Lees C., Savulescu J., Thiele P., Tran T. Perinatal management of trisomy 18: a survey of obstetricians in Australia, New Zealand and the UK. Prenat Diagn. 2014;34:42–49. doi: 10.1002/pd.4249. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Guon J., Wilfond B.S., Farlow B., Brazg T., Janvier A. Our children are not a diagnosis: the experience of parents who continue their pregnancy after a prenatal diagnosis of trisomy 13 or 18. Am J Med Genet. 2014;164A:308–318. doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.36298. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Farlow B., Misgivings Hastings Cent Rep. 2009;39:19–21. doi: 10.1353/hcr.0.0178. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Thiele P. He was my son, not a dying baby. J Med Ethics. 2010;36:646–647. doi: 10.1136/jme.2010.036152. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Walker L.V., Miller V.J., Dalton V.K. The health-care experiences of families given the prenatal diagnosis of trisomy 18. J Perinatol. 2008;28:12–19. doi: 10.1038/sj.jp.7211860. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Janvier A., Farlow B., Wilfond B.S. The experience of families with children with trisomy 13 and 18 in social networks. Pediatrics. 2012;130:293–298. doi: 10.1542/peds.2012-0151. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Wilkinson D.J.C., Savulescu J. Knowing when to stop: futility in the ICU. Curr Opin Anaesthesiol. 2011;24:160–165. doi: 10.1097/ACO.0b013e328343c5af. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.Schneiderman L.J., Jecker N.S., Jonsen A.R. Medical futility: its meaning and ethical implications. Ann Intern Med. 1990;112:949–954. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-112-12-949. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 64.Brody B.A., Halevy A. Is futility a futile concept? J Med Philosophy. 1995;20:123–144. doi: 10.1093/jmp/20.2.123. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Helft P.R., Siegler M., Lantos J. The rise and fall of the futility movement. N Engl J Med. 2000;343:293–296. doi: 10.1056/NEJM200007273430411. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 66.Boss R.D., Holmes K.W., Althaus J., Rushton C.H., McNee H., McNee T. Ethics rounds. Trisomy 18 and complex congenital heart disease: seeking the threshold benefit. Pediatrics. 2013;132:161–165. doi: 10.1542/peds.2012-3643. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 67.Youngner S.J. Who defines futility? JAMA. 1988;260:2094–2095. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 68.Babnik J. Textbook of perinatal medicine. Parthenon; London: 1998. Ethical decisions in the delivery room; pp. 1880–1885. [Google Scholar]
- 69.Chervenak F.A., McCullough L.B. The fetus as a patient: an essential ethical concept for maternal–fetal medicine. J Maternal–Fetal Neonat Medicine. 1996;5:115–119. doi: 10.1002/(SICI)1520-6661(199605/06)5:3<115::AID-MFM3>3.0.CO;2-P. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 70.Liang C.A., Braddock B.A., Heithaus J.L., Christensen K.M., Braddock S.R., Carey J.C. Reported communication ability of persons with trisomy 18 and trisomy 13. Dev Neurorehabil. 2013 Nov 1 doi: 10.3109/17518423.2013.847980. [Epub ahead of print] [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 71.Janvier A., Okah F., Farlow B., Lantos J.D. An infant with trisomy 18 and a ventricular septal defect. Pediatrics. 2011;127:754–759. doi: 10.1542/peds.2010-1971. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 72.Caplan A. Neutrality is not morality: the ethics of genetic counselling. In: Bartels D., LeRoy B., Caplan A., editors. Prescribing our future: ethical challenges in genetic counselling. Aldine De Gruyter; Hawthorne: 1993. [Google Scholar]
- 73.Elwyn G., Gray J., Clarke A. Shared decision making and non-directiveness in genetic counselling. J Med Genet. 2000;37:135–138. doi: 10.1136/jmg.37.2.135. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 74.Resta R.G. Eugenics and nondirectiveness in genetic counseling. J Genet Couns. 1997;6:255–258. doi: 10.1023/a:1025624505382. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 75.Rentmeester C.A. Value neutrality in genetic counseling: an unattained ideal. Med Health Care Philos. 2001;4:47–51. doi: 10.1023/a:1009972728031. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 76.Williams DL., Gelijns AC., Moskowitz AJ., Weinberg AD., Ng JH., Crawford E. Hypoplastic left heart syndrome: valuing the survival. J Thorac Cardiovasc Surg. 2000;119:720–731. doi: 10.1016/S0022-5223(00)70007-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 77.Bernhardt B.A. Empirical evidence that genetic counseling is directive: where do we go from here? Am J Hum Genet. 1997;60:17–20. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 78.De Crespigny L. Words matter. Nomenclature and communication in perinatal medicine. Clin Perinatol. 2003;30:17–25. doi: 10.1016/s0095-5108(02)00088-x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 79.Breeze A.C., Lees C.C. Antenatal diagnosis and management of life-limiting conditions. Semin Fetal Neonatal Med. 2013;18:68–75. doi: 10.1016/j.siny.2012.09.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 80.Wilkinson D. Oxford University Press; Oxford: 2013. Death or disability? The Carmentis Machine and treatment decisions for critically ill children. [Google Scholar]
- 81.British Association of Perinatal Medicine . British Association of Perinatal Medicine; London: 2010. Palliative care (supportive and end of life care): a framework for clinical practice in perinatal medicine. [Google Scholar]
- 82.Kutzsche S., Partridge J.C., Leuthner S.R., Lantos J.D. When life-sustaining treatment is withdrawn and the patient doesn't die. Pediatrics. 2013;132:893–897. doi: 10.1542/peds.2013-0413. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 83.Cote-Arsenault D., Denney-Koelsch E. “My baby is a person”: parents' experiences with life-threatening fetal diagnosis. J Palliat Med. 2011;14:1302–1308. doi: 10.1089/jpm.2011.0165. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 84.Kilby M.D., Pretlove S.J., Bedford Russell A.R. Multidisciplinary palliative care in unborn and newborn babies. BMJ. 2011;342:d1808. doi: 10.1136/bmj.d1808. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 85.Heuser C.C., Eller A.G., Byrne J.L. Survey of physicians' approach to severe fetal anomalies. J Med Ethics. 2012;38:391–395. doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100340. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 86.Chervenak F.A., McCullough L.B. Nonaggressive obstetric management. An option for some fetal anomalies during the third trimester. JAMA. 1989;261:3439–3440. doi: 10.1001/jama.261.23.3439. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 87.Chervenak F.A., McCullough L.B. Ethical dimensions of non-aggressive fetal management. Semin Fetal Neonatal Med. 2008;13:316–319. doi: 10.1016/j.siny.2008.03.006. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 88.Spinnato J.A., Cook V.D., Cook C.R., Voss D.H. Aggressive intrapartum management of lethal fetal anomalies: beyond fetal beneficence. Obstet Gynecol. 1995;85:89–92. doi: 10.1016/0029-7844(94)00310-a. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 89.Wilkinson D.J.C. Antenatal diagnosis of trisomy 18, harm and parental choice. J Med Ethics. 2010;36:644–645. doi: 10.1136/jme.2010.040212. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 90.Kumar P. Care of an infant with lethal malformation: where do we draw the line? Pediatrics. 2011;128:e1642–e1643. doi: 10.1542/peds.2011-2869A. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 91.Strong C. Fetal anomalies: ethical and legal considerations in screening, detection, and management. Clin Perinatol. 2003;30:113–126. doi: 10.1016/s0095-5108(02)00083-0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 92.Tex Health and Safety Code. Section A170.002 Prohibited Acts; exemption [available at: http://www.statutes.legis.state.tx.us/Docs/SDocs/HEALTHANDSAFETYCODE.pdf], eff. September 1, 1999.
- 93.Texas Health and Safety Code. Section 285.202 Use of tax revenue for abortions; exception for medical emergency [available at: http://www.weblaws.org/texas/laws/tex._health_and_safety_code_section_285.202_use_of_tax_revenue_for_abortions;_exception_for_medical_emergency], eff. September 28, 2011.
- 94.Women's Link Worldwide, C-355/2006 . 2007. Women's Link Worldwide.http://www.womenslinkworldwide.org/pdf_pubs/pub_c3552006.pdf accessed at: on February 19, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- 95.Human Rights Watch, Brazil. Supreme Court abortion ruling a positive step: expands exceptions to criminal penalties to include fatal disorder of fetus [available at: http://www.hrw.org/news/2012/04/19/brazil-supreme-court-abortion-ruling-positive-step]; April 19, 2012.
- 96.Savulescu J. Is current practice around late termination of pregnancy eugenic and discriminatory? Maternal interests and abortion. J Med Ethics. 2001;27:165–171. doi: 10.1136/jme.27.3.165. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 97.Bienstock J.L., Birsner M.L., Coleman F., Hueppchen N.A. Successful in utero intervention for bilateral renal agenesis. Obstet Gynecol. 2014;124(2 Pt 2):413–415. doi: 10.1097/AOG.0000000000000339. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 98.Song K. Survival of Rep. Herrera Beutler's child a celebrated case study. Seattle Times. 23 August 2014 available at http://seattletimes.com/html/localnews/2024377057_herrerabeutlerxml.html. [Google Scholar]