Skip to main content
Canadian Family Physician logoLink to Canadian Family Physician
. 2015 Apr;61(4):314–316.

Is physician-assisted death in anyone’s best interest?

Yes

James Downar 1,
PMCID: PMC4396749  PMID: 25873692

I will make 2 arguments to support the idea that assisted death is in the best interests of some patients: death can sometimes be in a patient’s best interest; and capable patients are well positioned to determine when death is in their best interests. I will then argue that physicians should have a role in assisted death by reversing the premise of this debate and arguing that nobody’s interests are served by denying patients the right to physician-assisted death (PAD).

I speak as a secular North American who supports individual autonomy, subject only to limitations that are justifiable on the basis of empirically provable facts. My arguments are intended for people with a similar moral compass. I respect those who disagree with me on a religious basis, and I recognize that my arguments might not address their concerns.

Death can sometimes be in a patient’s best interest

The value of life is great but not infinite. When faced with a dire prognosis, some patients or family members will find strength in an old proverb: “Where there’s life, there’s hope.” But this proverb is best interpreted as a prayer that things will get better rather than a literal statement that anyone with vital signs should be kept alive by any means.

Many religious authorities endorse the vitalist notion that all life is valuable. But these same authorities also believe that it is wrong to prolong a life artificially to no end, and they accept the limitations of life-prolonging treatments.1,2 Most accept the principle of double effect, which holds that a patient can receive comfort medications that have the potential to shorten life, so long as shortening life is not the intention. People who accept that lives need not be prolonged indefinitely, or that a life can be “risked” in the interest of comfort, have implicitly accepted that life is not of infinite value. They recognize that compassion can sometimes be shown only through actions that might compromise lifespan.

Death is not an optional experience, and death in Canada is usually a predictable event preceded by a chronic, incurable illness.3 Given the choice, many people try to delay death and some will seek out aggressive means of prolonging life even when faced with a hopeless situation. But other patients have limited life-prolonging options, and although they remain cognitively intact, their quality of life and function deteriorate below the threshold that they consider acceptable. These patients usually choose comfort-based care and are happy to wait for a “natural” death. But some patients prefer not to wait for a complication to end their suffering; several recent high-profile cases of Canadians with brain cancer,4 Alzheimer disease,5 and amyotrophic lateral sclerosis6 have illustrated this. In either event, the patient is comfortable with the idea that they might be forgoing some period of life in the interest of comfort. They will not avoid death—they might even seek it out—and everyone will feel a degree of relief when it arrives.

There might be a conceptual difference between actively assisting death and passively assisting death by withdrawing or withholding therapies, but both approaches are justified on the same premise: death is in the best interest of the patient. The patient’s interests are not affected by whether the outcome is achieved actively or passively.

Capable patients are well positioned to determine when death is in their best interests

Many Canadians die in intensive care units, often as the result of a decision to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining treatments. Ideally, this decision comes from the patient and we are sure that this is what he or she wants. In reality, we usually cannot involve the patient directly in the decision; instead, we rely on substitute decision makers (SDMs), who are supposed to reproduce the decision the patient would have made by considering advance directives or best interests. Substitute decision making is a flawed process. Substitute decision makers are inaccurate predictors of what a patient would want.7 Advance directives are uncommon, and they are usually too vague or too specific to be useful for medical decisions.8 Substitute decision makers also have numerous potential conflicts of interest. If the patient dies, they might inherit some material wealth, and they will no longer have to bear the emotional and physical burden of caregiving. And if the SDM was ever the victim of sexual, physical, or emotional abuse, the patient might have been the perpetrator.

Despite all of these concerns about substitute decision making, we continue to allow SDMs to decide when patients should be allowed to die. If we are comfortable with this arrangement, then why would we feel less comfortable acting on wishes that are communicated directly by patients, with none of these potential inaccuracies, misinterpretations, or conflicts of interest? Indeed, we are happy to respect capable, terminally ill patients’ desires to receive palliative care and forgo life-prolonging therapy. We do not insist that they continue chemotherapy until they die a “natural” death. We do not try to convince them that a ventilator will help them find meaning in their life. We respect their ability to know when they have had enough. If patients are allowed to decide when a passive death is in their best interests, why would they not be allowed to decide when an active death would be in their best interests?

Nobody’s interests are served by denying patients the right to PAD

If we want to prevent a rational person from pursuing his or her own best interest, we must have a strong justification for doing so. The common arguments used against legalization of PAD are framed as concerns about the effects on vulnerable people, the availability of palliative care services, and physicians as a group. None of these concerns is supported by data.

Data from the United States (US) show that among patients who receive PAD, more than 95% are white, more than 93% are high school graduates, and more than 97% have some form of health insurance.9 Data from Switzerland show that the wealthier and better educated are more than twice as likely to receive an assisted death than the poorer and less educated, while people in institutions are less likely to receive an assisted death than those living in private residences.10 The people who receive PAD are not the vulnerable—they are the privileged.

Palliative care services appeared to have done well in jurisdictions that legalized PAD. Legalization of PAD is often accompanied by a larger strategy and funding to improve end-of-life services, as described in the Netherlands11 and in Australia’s Northern Territory12 (where the law was later overturned by the federal government). In the US, the 3 states that have legalized PAD by statute—Vermont, Oregon, and Washington—are ranked first, sixth, and eighth in the nation, respectively, for the availability of palliative care services in hospitals.13 In 2010, the Economist Intelligence Unit ranked the “basic end-of-life healthcare environment” of 40 nations around the globe.12 Countries in which PAD is legal—Switzerland, the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxembourg, and the US—ranked first, fourth, fifth, seventh, and ninth, respectively. Canada ranked 20th.

Some physicians argue that legalizing PAD would compromise the physician-patient relationship. This is a difficult argument to sustain in a country where PAD is supported by 84% of the population.14 Data from Oregon show that patients are more likely to become upset by physicians who oppose PAD than by physicians who support it.15 Furthermore, the Canadian Medical Association essentially rejected this argument at its recent annual general meeting, where 90% of members voted to support “the right of all physicians, within the bonds of existing legislation, to follow their conscience when deciding whether to provide so-called medical aid in dying.”16

Some have expressed concern that PAD would be a violation of the Hippocratic oath, and suggested that a new profession of euthanasia practitioners should be created. We should remember that the Hippocratic oath has been modified extensively over the years to reflect changes in laws and sensibilities. Specifically, the prohibition on abortion and the implication that only men should be trained in medicine have both been removed from the original version.17 Laws, policies, and codes of ethics change over time. Certainly, many physicians now believe that providing PAD would be an extension of their duty of care, when other means of treating end-of-life suffering have failed. And physicians can offer a range of therapies beyond PAD, allowing an opportunity to relieve suffering through other means, right up until the last moment. What other options could a euthanasia practitioner offer?

CLOSING ARGUMENTS — YES

James Downar mdcmmhsc(Bioethics) frcpc

  • Some patients have limited life-prolonging options, and although they remain cognitively intact, their quality of life and function deteriorate below the threshold that they consider acceptable. These patients usually choose comfort-based care and are happy to wait for a “natural” death. But some patients prefer not to wait for a complication to end their suffering. In either event, the patient is comfortable with the idea that they might be forgoing some period of life in the interest of comfort.

  • We respect substitute decision makers’ decisions to effectively end a life by withdrawing or withholding life support, despite the known inaccuracies and conflicts of interest inherent in substitute decision making. Why are we less comfortable respecting patients’ own requests to end their lives, which have none of those inaccuracies and conflicts of interest?

  • The common arguments used against legalization of physician-assisted death are framed as concerns about the effects on vulnerable people, the availability of palliative care services, and physicians as a group. None of these concerns is supported by data.

Footnotes

Cet article se trouve aussi en français à la page 320.

Competing interests

Dr Downar is Co-Chair of the Physicians Advisory Council of Dying with Dignity Canada, a not-for-profit organization that advocates for improved end-of-life care and the right to an assisted death.

The parties in these debates refute each other’s arguments in rebuttals available at www.cfp.ca. Join the discussion by clicking on Rapid Responses at www.cfp.ca.

References

  • 1.Bülow HH, Sprung CL, Reinhart K, Prayag S, Du B, Armaganidis A, et al. The world’s major religions’ points of view on end-of-life decisions in the intensive care unit. Intensive Care Med. 2008;34(3):423–30. doi: 10.1007/s00134-007-0973-8. Epub 2007 Dec 19. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Paul John., II . Evangelium vitae. Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana; 1995. Available from: http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_25031995_evangelium-vitae.html. Accessed 2015 Feb 12. [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Canadian Institute for Health Information . Health care use at the end of life in western Canada. Ottawa, ON: Canadian Institute for Health Information; 2007. [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Cancer View Canada . In memory of Dr. Donald Low. San Bruno, CA: YouTube, LLC; 2011. Available from: www.youtube.com/watch?v=q3jgSkxV1rw. Accessed 2014 Aug 25. [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Bennett G. Goodbye and good luck! Bowen Island, BC: Dead at Noon [blog]; 2014. Aug 18, Available from: http://deadatnoon.com. Accessed 2014 Aug 25. [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Carter v. Canada (Attorney General) 2012. B.C.S.C. 886.
  • 7.Shalowitz DI, Garrett-Mayer E, Wendler D. The accuracy of surrogate decision makers: a systematic review. Arch Intern Med. 2006;166(5):493–7. doi: 10.1001/archinte.166.5.493. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Teno JM, Licks S, Lynn J, Wenger N, Connors AF, Jr, Phillips RS, et al. Do advance directives provide instructions that direct care? SUPPORT Investigators. Study to Understand Prognoses and Preferences for Outcomes and Risks of Treatment. J Am Geriatr Soc. 1997;45(4):508–12. doi: 10.1111/j.1532-5415.1997.tb05179.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Loggers ET, Starks H, Shannon-Dudley M, Back AL, Appelbaum FR, Stewart FM. Implementing a Death with Dignity program at a comprehensive cancer center. N Engl J Med. 2013;368(15):1417–24. doi: 10.1056/NEJMsa1213398. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Steck N, Junker C, Maessen M, Reisch T, Zwahlen M, Egger M, et al. Suicide assisted by right-to-die associations: a population based cohort study. Int J Epidemiol. 2014;43(2):614–22. doi: 10.1093/ije/dyu010. Epub 2014 Feb 18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Gordijn B, Janssens R. Euthanasia and palliative care in the Netherlands: an analysis of the latest developments. Health Care Anal. 2004;12(3):195–207. doi: 10.1023/B:HCAN.0000044926.05523.ef. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Economist Intelligence Unit . The quality of death. Ranking end-of-life care across the world. London, UK: Economist Intelligence Unit; 2010. Available from: http://graphics.eiu.com/upload/QOD_main_final_edition_Jul12_toprint.pdf. Accessed 2015 Feb 12. [Google Scholar]
  • 13.National Palliative Care Registry . A state-by-state report card on access to palliative care in our nation’s hospitals. New York, NY: Center to Advance Palliative Care; 2011. Available from: www.capc.org/reportcard/topten. Accessed 2014 Jul 4. [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Ipsos Reid [news release] Most (84%) Canadians believe a doctor should be able to assist someone who is terminally ill and suffering unbearably to end their life. Toronto, ON: Ipsos Reid; 2014. Available from: www.ipsos-na.com/news-polls/pressrelease.aspx?id=6626. Accessed 2015 Feb 25. [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Ganzini L, Nelson HD, Lee MA, Kraemer DF, Schmidt TA, Delorit MA. Oregon physicians’ attitudes about and experiences with end-of-life care since passage of the Oregon Death with Dignity Act. JAMA. 2001;285(18):2363–69. doi: 10.1001/jama.285.18.2363. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Goodman LA. Doctors debate end-of-life care at Canadian Medical Association meeting. CBC News. 2014. Aug 19, Available from: www.cbc.ca/news/canada/toronto/doctors-debate-end-of-life-care-at-canadian-medical-association-meeting-1.2740904. Accessed 2015 Feb 13.
  • 17.Wikipedia [encyclopedia online] Hippocratic oath. Los Angeles, CA: Wikipedia Foundation Ltd; 2015. Available from: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hippocratic_Oath. Accessed 2015 Feb 12. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Canadian Family Physician are provided here courtesy of College of Family Physicians of Canada

RESOURCES