Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2015 Jun 2.
Published in final edited form as: Perspect Psychol Sci. 2013 Jul;8(4):395–411. doi: 10.1177/1745691613485247

Taking Stock of Unrealistic Optimism

James A Shepperd 1, William M P Klein 2, Erika A Waters 3, Neil D Weinstein 4
PMCID: PMC4451212  NIHMSID: NIHMS691682  PMID: 26045714

Abstract

Researchers have used terms such as unrealistic optimism and optimistic bias to refer to concepts that are similar but not synonymous. Drawing from three decades of research, we critically discuss how researchers define unrealistic optimism and we identify four types that reflect different measurement approaches: unrealistic absolute optimism at the individual and group level and unrealistic comparative optimism at the individual and group level. In addition, we discuss methodological criticisms leveled against research on unrealistic optimism and note that the criticisms are primarily relevant to only one type—the group form of unrealistic comparative optimism. We further clarify how the criticisms are not nearly as problematic even for unrealistic comparative optimism as they might seem. Finally, we note boundary conditions on the different types of unrealistic optimism and reflect on five broad questions that deserve further attention.

Keywords: Unrealistic optimism, comparative optimism, optimistic bias, risk judgments


Researchers have long argued that people are not objective in their predictions (Taylor & Brown, 1988; Weinstein, 1980). Rather, people believe that their future will be better than can possibly be true. This bias towards favorable outcomes—often known as unrealistic optimism—appears for a wide variety of negative events, including diseases such as cancer (Waters et al., 2011), natural disasters such as earthquakes (Burger & Palmer, 1992), and a host of other events ranging from unwanted pregnancies (Gerrard, Gibbons, & Warner, 1991) to radon contamination (Weinstein & Lyon, 1999), to the end of a romantic relationship (MacDonald & Ross, 1999). It also emerges, albeit often less strongly, for positive events, such as graduating from university, getting married, and having favorable medical outcomes (Hoorens, Smits, & Shepperd, 2008; Jansen et al., 2011; Weinstein, 1980).

Researchers have investigated unrealistic optimism for more than 30 years, yielding on average 21 articles published per year. A Web of Knowledge database count of the five most common related terms (i.e., unrealistic optimism, comparative optimism, optimistic bias, optimism bias, and illusion of invulnerability) reveals 984 published papers. The number climbs still higher when terms like the “planning fallacy” and “positive illusions” are included. The seminal paper (Weinstein, 1980) that coined the term “unrealistic optimism” had received 1,418 citations as of February 2013. Unrealistic optimism also appears in virtually every social psychology textbook and in most introductory psychology textbooks. Researchers have demonstrated unrealistic optimism in a variety of western countries (e.g., Belgium, Canada, Denmark, England, France, and the United States) (Drace, Desrichard, Shepperd, & Hoorens, 2009; Harris, Middleton, & Joiner, 2000; Heine & Lehman, 1995; Helweg-Larsen & Nielsen, 2009; Hoorens & Buunk, 1993; Hoorens et al., 2008) and at least one eastern country (Japan) (Heine & Lehman, 1995).

Interest in unrealistic optimism extends beyond psychology. It is a pervasive concept in many social sciences (including law, economics, and decision sciences) and in medicine. For example, economists describe the perils of unrealistic optimism among entrepreneurs and investors (Bay, 2010), and medical researchers discuss unrealistic optimism among patients with advanced disease (Jansen et al., 2011). A recent book argues that unrealistic optimism has a neurological basis and that people have evolved to be unrealistically optimistic (Sharot, 2011b). In fact, unrealistic optimism is now a topic of interest in biologically-oriented journals such as Nature Neuroscience (Sharot, Korn, & Dolan, 2011) and Current Biology (Sharot, 2011a; Sharot, Guitart-Masip, Korn, Chowdhury, & Dolan, 2012). Although the neurological evidence is limited, the findings suggest that people may be predisposed to be optimistic (Sharot, 2011b).

Unrealistic optimism has clear practical implications. For example, unrealistic optimism can produce problems regarding informed consent when patients overestimate the likelihood of benefiting personally from participation in clinical trials (Jansen et al., 2011). Likewise, testimony in the United States Department of Justice lawsuit against American tobacco companies (Weinstein, 2001) highlighted how people underestimate their health risks from smoking and overestimate their ability to quit. Unrealistic optimism has received attention in mainstream media outlets such as the New York Times (Chen, 2011), in books for the general public (e.g., Kahneman, 2011), and in new media formats such as TED, the online lecture series dedicated to disseminating “ideas worth sharing,” where a lecture on unrealistic optimism posted in May 2012 was viewed by over half a million people in the first four months after it appeared (Optimism Bias, 2012). Finally, empirical evidence links unrealistic optimism to behavior. The direction of that link, however, can vary dramatically. For example, one study found that gay men infected with HIV who showed unrealistic optimism about not developing AIDS also showed more health related behavior (Taylor et al., 1992). Conversely, another found that unrealistic optimism among college students about their chances of having drinking problems in the future corresponded with experiencing more alcohol-related negative events (e.g., hang-over, missing classes) one month later (Dillard, Midboe, & Klein, 2009).

The rapid and widespread growth of unrealistic optimism research provides an opportunity to reflect on its meaning and on the ways researchers assess it. We approach this task by using the extensive empirical evidence to clarify theoretical, methodological, and practical issues surrounding unrealistic optimism and to raise several questions that deserve further research.

The Faces of Unrealistic Optimism

We define unrealistic optimism as a favorable difference between the risk estimate a person makes for him- or herself and the risk estimate suggested by a relevant, objective standard (such as epidemiological, base-rate data). Unrealistic optimism also includes comparing oneself to others in an unduly favorable manner. Our definition makes no assumption about how the difference is manifest. It may reflect a distortion in personal risk estimates, a distortion in the perceived risk of the comparison target, or both. Our definition also makes no assumption about why the difference exists. The difference may originate from motivational sources such as a desire to deny vulnerability to harm, or from cognitive processes such as such as the person positivity bias, egocentric thinking, or overuse of the representativeness heuristic (Chambers & Windschitl, 2004; Shepperd, Carroll, Grace, & Terry, 2002).

Unfortunately, researchers are not consistent in their terminology or the assessment approach they use to study unrealistic optimism. They sometimes assume that different, but similar, terms refer to the same construct and that various measurement strategies yield the same result. Similarly, researchers sometimes assume that moderators of one type of unrealistic optimism also moderate other types of unrealistic optimism. Some researchers, as well as science writers, have even conflated unrealistic optimism with dispositional optimism, the enduring tendency to expect positive outcomes. In fact, different types of optimism are not only distinct in their definition and operation, but also are distinct empirically. Different measurement approaches elicit different levels of optimism and the data from these different measures correlate across events only moderately, if at all (Radcliffe & Klein, 2002; Waters et al., 2011).

We distinguish between two broad types of unrealistic optimism: unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism (see Table 1). Both types can be expressed at either the individual level or the group level, yielding four distinct categories.

Table 1.

The Faces of Unrealistic Optimism

Type of Individual Risk Estimate Level of Analysis
Individual Group
Absolute Risk Unrealistic Absolute Optimism - Individual
An individual gives a personal absolute risk estimate that is less than the absolute risk indicated by an appropriate, individual-level objective standard (e.g., a woman says her risk is 20% but a risk calculator says that it is 30%).
Unrealistic Absolute Optimism - Group
Individuals give personal, absolute risk estimates. The average of these estimates is less than the absolute risk of an appropriate group-level objective standard (e.g., the average of the groups’ personal estimates is 20%, but the base rate for this group is 30%).
Comparative Risk Unrealistic Comparative Optimism - Individual
An individual gives a comparative risk estimate that is lower than the estimate indicated by an appropriate, individual-level comparative risk standard (e.g., a woman says her risk is below average but a risk calculator says that it is above average).
Unrealistic Comparative Optimism - Group
Individuals give estimates that compare their risk (directly or indirectly) with that of a relevant comparison group. The average of these estimates is less than the comparison group (e.g., on average, students at a college say that their risk of developing drinking problems is less than the average risk at their college).

Unrealistic Absolute Optimism

Unrealistic Absolute Optimism refers to the erroneous belief that personal negative outcomes, assessed on some form of absolute likelihood scale, are less likely to occur than is objectively warranted (see Table 1). Finding an objective standard to use in determining the accuracy of risk beliefs is the biggest challenge in this approach. Many outcomes (such as having a heart attack or dying from lung cancer) may not occur until the distant future and cannot be assessed within a reasonable time frame. Also, for the standard to be relevant, the objective indicator must apply to the particular people or groups being studied (e.g., adults, Hispanics, females), so data about the population overall may not be relevant. Nevertheless, a number of studies have solved this problem in creative ways.

As evident in Table 1, unrealistic absolute optimism has two forms. At the individual level, unrealistic absolute optimism occurs when a person’s estimate of his or her personal risk is too low relative to some individual-level standard. The individual-level standard might be personal outcomes that actually occur at a later date or personal risk as calculated from an empirically validated risk algorithm. Objective outcomes, such as whether a person does have a heart attack, represent more reliable standards than the predictions of risk algorithms and other actuarial models, which are based on group data and by definition contain uncertainty. If risk algorithms were perfect predictors, they would yield a dichotomous prediction: the event will happen or it will not. Nevertheless, we can assert that a person is displaying unrealistic absolute optimism if his or her prediction is lower than the prediction made by the best available risk algorithm.

At the group level, researchers cannot tell whether any given individual is unrealistic. Rather, unrealistic absolute optimism occurs when the average of the risk estimates given by a group of people is lower than a group-level objective standard, such as the base rate for this event in this group. Indeed, the most widely used standard for such determinations is the base rate.

Examples: Unrealistic Absolute Optimism – Individual

A number of studies find unrealistic absolute optimism when comparing personal predictions to later experience. For example, studies find unrealistic absolute optimism in students estimating the grades they will achieve on forthcoming exams (Shepperd, Grace, Cole, & Klein, 2005; Shepperd, Ouellette, & Fernandez, 1996), financial analysts predicting the economy (Calderon, 1993), and students estimating their starting salary after graduation (Shepperd et al., 1996). Studies also show unrealistic optimism in people’s predictions of the likelihood that they would engage in benevolent behavior. For example, although 83% of participants in one study said they would buy a flower from fellow students to benefit a national charity, only 43% actually did (Epley & Dunning, 2000).

Perhaps nowhere is unrealistic absolute optimism more evident than in people’s estimates of the time to complete a task, better known as the planning fallacy (Tversky & Kahneman, 1974). Researchers have demonstrated unrealistic absolute optimism in estimates for tasks such as completing one’s tax return (Buehler, Griffin, & MacDonald, 1997), solving puzzles (Buehler et al., 1997), writing a report (Koole & Spijker, 2000), completing mundane tasks (Griffin & Buehler, 1999; Newby-Clark, Ross, Buehler, Koehler, & Griffin, 2000), assembling a computer stand (Byram, 1997), and making Japanese origami (Byram, 1997).

Examples: Unrealistic Absolute Optimism – Group

Some studies have observed unrealistic absolute optimism when comparing group estimates to the population base rates. For instance, one study found that homeowners were optimistic relative to the local population base rate when asked about the likelihood of finding radon problems in their own homes (Weinstein & Lyon, 1999). Whereas 73% of homes in the area had elevated radon levels, people on average estimated that their own likelihood of having a problem was 27%. Moreover, homeowners continued to display unrealistic absolute optimism even after they were provided the base rate (revised mean estimate = 54.1%). Similarly, a study by Rothman and colleagues found evidence of unrealistic absolute optimism for 4 of 10 events (divorce, chlamydia, pregnancy, and HPV) when participants’ mean personal predictions were compared with the base rate for the events (Rothman, Klein, & Weinstein, 1996). Like the radon study, this form of unrealistic optimism persisted even when participants received accurate base rate information.

A third study asked a nationally representative sample of smokers and non-smokers to estimate the likelihood that they would live to age 75 or longer, then used a nationally representative sample of death certificates to establish the true survival rate at age 75. Participants were generally accurate in their estimates with one notable exception—heavy smokers. Men who were heavy smokers reported a 50.1% likelihood of seeing their 75th birthday and women who were heavy smokers reported a 60.1% likelihood of seeing their 75th birthday. However, the sample of death certificates suggests that only 26.3% of such men and 30.8% of such women would actually survive to age 75 (Schoenbaum, 1997).

Other studies have compared risk estimates relative to past experience or with the experience of a comparable sample. For instance, one cross-sectional study examined the perceived likelihood of an unplanned pregnancy in a sample of women in the U.S. Marine Corps. All women reported being sexually active prior to joining the Corps. The women estimated that they had on average a 14.5% chance of an unplanned pregnancy in the next 12 months. Yet 27% of the participants reported having been pregnant prior to joining the Marines. Of course, prior experience with pregnancy, coupled with the personal commitment associated with joining the Marines, may have prompted these women to use birth control in future sexual encounters. Accordingly, the 14.5% estimate could be realistic if they had altered their sexual behavior to reduce pregnancy risk. Yet evidence from a second, comparable sample of Marine Corp women who were observed longitudinally suggests that the perceived likelihood of pregnancy was indeed optimistic. The observed 12-month pregnancy rate for the comparable sample was 22%—significantly higher than the estimate of 14.5% (Gerrard et al., 1991).

Another study compared participants’ absolute personal risk estimates with the personal estimates of a second group of participants who were indisputably at less risk. Surprisingly, gay men who were infected with the HIV virus estimated a lower likelihood that they would develop AIDs than did a second sample of gay men who were uninfected (Taylor et al., 1992).

Admittedly, it may seem odd to describe people as unrealistic in their estimates when they do not know the base rate. For example, a group on average may underestimate their risk of a radon gas problem simply because they are unaware that radon gas is problem in their community. Yet, although the underestimation reflects erroneous beliefs, it is still unrealistic optimism. Relatedly, unrealistic optimism is sometimes less clear in absolute risk judgments in part because it is obscured by erroneous beliefs about the actual rate in the population, especially when people make numerical judgments. The consequence is that people underestimate their personal risk for some events and overestimate their personal risk for others. Nevertheless, unrealistic optimism likely contributes to most or all risk judgments.

Unrealistic Comparative Optimism

As evident in Table 1, unrealistic comparative optimism also has two forms. At the individual level, unrealistic comparative optimism occurs when a person incorrectly judges how his or her risk compares with that of other people. For example, an individual may claim that his risk is below that of the average man when an empirically validated individualized risk assessment algorithm(e.g., a risk calculator) indicates that his risk is above average (acknowledging, of course, the imperfect nature of risk calculators as mentioned earlier). At the group level, unrealistic comparative optimism refers to situations in which people in a sample estimate that they are less likely on average to experience a negative outcome or more likely on average to experience a positive outcome than are their peers. Studies consistently demonstrate the presence of unrealistic comparative optimism. This optimism appears across different types of samples, for many different events, and with a variety of assessment scales.

Examples: Unrealistic Comparative Optimism – Individual

Several studies have used an objective standard to evaluate whether comparative risk judgments are optimistic. In one study, participants estimated their risk of having a fatal heart attack relative to the average person. Next, researchers used a heart attack risk assessment algorithm to categorize participants’ actual risk as above average, below average, or average. Comparing the personal and objective comparative risk judgments, 56% of participants were classified as unrealistically optimistic, 25% were classified as unrealistically pessimistic, and 19% were classified as accurate. This level of unrealistic predictions was far greater than chance (p < .0001) (Radcliffe & Klein, 2002). A second study used the same approach and found that 66% of the college student sample was unrealistically optimistic about the risk of experiencing severe alcohol problems in the future (Dillard et al., 2009).

In a third study, a nationally representative sample of over 14,000 women estimated their risk for breast cancer by indicating whether they believed they were less likely, more likely, or about as likely to get breast cancer as the average woman their age. Next, the authors used the Gail risk assessment algorithm (Gail et al., 1989) to compute the objective risk of breast cancer for each woman and classified them as above average, below average, or average in risk. Comparing participants’ personal risk classification with their objective risk classification revealed that 41.8% of women were unrealistically optimistic about their breast cancer risk, 13.4% were unrealistically pessimistic, 34.7% were accurate, and 10.1% did not respond to the risk item or reported that they did not know (Waters et al., 2011). This study is important for two reasons. First, it demonstrated that a large number of women were unrealistically optimistic. Second, the sample was part of an ongoing population-based, nationally representative survey that can generalize to the larger U.S. population. Thus, this study is a better indicator than most studies regarding the prevalence of unrealistic risk beliefs in the United States. Importantly, although this finding may seem to contradict other research showing that women overestimate their breast cancer risk (Lipkus, Klein, Skinner, & Rimer, 2005), this study demonstrated unrealistic comparative optimism whereas studies showing overestimation of breast cancer risk typically examine unrealistic absolute optimism. When viewed together, the two lines of research illustrate that unrealistic comparative optimism and unrealistic absolute optimism tap different constructs and can coexist.

Finally, one nationally representative study of smokers merits mention. These smokers separately reported whether their risk of heart attack and cancer were higher, lower, or about the same as the average, same-sex person their age. Because smoking substantially increases the risks of both heart attack and cancer (U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, 2004), nearly all of the participants were above average in risk for both diseases. However, only 29% of smokers reported that their personal risk of heart attack was higher than average and only 40% believed that their personal risk of cancer was higher than average (Ayanian & Cleary, 1999).

Examples: Unrealistic Comparative Optimism – Group

Unrealistic Comparative Optimism at the group level is distinct from the other forms of unrealistic optimism in the method used to determine accuracy. Here, the requirement for accuracy is that the mean of all individual comparative risk judgments combined should be “average.” The logic of this approach is grounded in the definition of “average.” If the group as a whole is accurate, people who say they have a risk that is above average should balance others whose say their risk is below average, assuming the distribution of risk is not highly skewed. Researchers can assess this type of unrealistic optimism in two ways (Weinstein & Klein, 1995). With the direct approach people report on a single scale how much their risk of experiencing an event is higher or lower than that of an average person. Researchers define unrealistic optimism as occurring when the mean estimate of the group differs significantly from the midpoint (i.e., “average risk”) in an optimistic direction.

Most unrealistic optimism studies—hundreds of them—have examined unrealistic comparative optimism using the direct approach. For instance, the paper that first coined the term “unrealistic optimism” demonstrated that study participants estimated that they were less likely than the average person to experience such events as contracting venereal disease, getting fired from a job, and being sued by someone (Weinstein, 1980). Other research demonstrated unrealistic comparative optimism in a community sample for events as varied as drug addiction, asthma, food poisoning and sunstroke. The level of optimism was unaffected by participants’ age, sex, education, job status, or their ratings of the seriousness of the event, and they never displayed unrealistic comparative pessimism (Weinstein, 1987).

With the indirect approach, people estimate on two separate scales the likelihood that they and some comparison target, such as the average person, will experience an event. Researchers define unrealistic optimism as occurring when the mean of the personal estimates differs significantly in an optimistic direction from the mean of the estimates made for the comparison target. Although unrealistic comparative optimism is often weaker when assessed indirectly than when assessed directly (Klein & Helweg-Larsen, 2002; Otten & Van Der Pligt, 1996), the effect is nevertheless robust. Using the indirect method, researchers have demonstrated unrealistic comparative optimism for events such as suicide, alcohol problems, smoking related illnesses (McCoy et al., 1992), injury in a natural disaster (Burger & Palmer, 1992), getting AIDS or cancer (Hoorens & Buunk, 1993), and getting HPV and chlamydia (Rothman et al., 1996). Interestingly, the magnitudes of direct and indirect comparative judgments are not always closely correlated (Ranby, Aiken, Gerend, & Erchull, 2010).

Researchers recognized early on the necessity of specifying the comparison target because population differences in outcome base rates can create interpretational problems. For instance, asking college students to compare their risk for a smoking-related illness to that of the average person (which includes smokers and nonsmokers) could yield comparative optimism, not because the college students are being unrealistic, but because college graduates smoke less than the rest of the population and thus really are less likely than the average person to experience smoking-related illnesses (Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, 2011). As a solution, researchers constrain the identity of the comparison target. For example, researchers typically ask college students to compare their risk with that of the average same age, same sex student at their university. When the study group has a known risk factor, it is necessary to constrain the comparison group further. For example, researchers studying college smokers would need questions referring to the average same age, same sex student at their university. Yet even with this constraint, people show unrealistic comparative optimism. For example, immigrant farm workers rated their risk of experiencing health problems from pesticide exposure as less than the risk of the average immigrant farm worker (Vaughan, 1993), college women rated their risk of pregnancy as less than the risk of the average college woman (Whitley & Hern, 1991), 6th grade children rated their risk for a variety of health problems as less than the risk of the average 6th grader (Whalen et al., 1994), and drivers rated their risk of a road accident as less than the risk of the average driver (McKenna, 1993).

An inherent limitation of this assessment approach is that it reveals optimism only at the group level. Indeed, it is possible that the group estimate is “average,” suggesting no unrealistic optimism when individual estimates are actually quite inaccurate, with half of the participants underestimating their risk and the other half overestimating their risk to the same degree. Thus, this form of unrealistic optimism does not indicate whether any given individual is unrealistic, but only whether the group is unrealistic on average.

Alternative Accounts for Unrealistic Optimism

Although hundreds of studies demonstrate unrealistic optimism, test moderators, and explore possible causes, some researchers have argued that statistical artifacts plague studies of the phenomenon (Harris & Hahn, 2011). According to these critics, evidence for unrealistic optimism may be overstated and the phenomenon may not, in fact, exist at all.

The first proposed artifact is scale attenuation whereby the restricted nature of the response scale used to assess outcomes (e.g., a −3 to +3 relative risk scale) might force some people to supply responses that are inaccurate. Scale attenuation may be particularly problematic for uncommon events in which a small portion of the population is at high risk (e.g., a rare genetic mutation). In this case, most people are below the group average and a small number is far above the group average in risk. A scale that limits the responses of these high-risk people and prevents them from indicating their true perceptions could lead to a false appearance of unrealistic optimism in the group as a whole.

The second proposed possible artifact is minority undersampling, which could occur in studies that contain a disproportionate number of people who will not experience the negative event. Again, this artifact is most relevant for rare events, when there may be no one in the sample who will actually experience the event. In such cases, the sample might seem biased toward optimism when, in fact, respondents are responding accurately.

The third potential artifact is base rate regression (Moore & Small, 2007). People often know little about the average person, including the average person’s risk factors, family history, or actions that may increase or decrease their risk. For extreme outcomes (i.e., outcomes that are very rare or very common), researchers have argued that estimates of the average person’s risk are less extreme than the actual base rate for the outcome (i.e., estimates are regressive). Accordingly, people overestimate the average person’s likelihood of experiencing rare outcomes and underestimate the average person’s likelihood of experiencing common outcomes. For example, whereas the base rate may be 1% in the population, people might estimate that that average person’s risk is 5%. Conversely, when the base rate is 90%, they may estimate the average person’s risk is 80%. In contrast, people have more information about themselves to use in estimating their risk. For example, for rare outcomes most people will have few risk-increasing factors and many risk-decreasing factors, leading them to believe that their personal likelihood of experiencing the outcome is very low. Thus, people may accurately estimate their personal risk for a rare event is 1%. Conversely, for common outcomes people may have many risk-increasing factors and few risk-reducing factors, leading them to believe that their personal likelihood of experiencing the outcome is very high. The consequence of these two processes is that people believe rare events are less likely to happen to them than to other people, but that common events are more likely to happen to them than to other people.

A Closer Look at Scale Attenuation and Minority Undersampling

Although these three issues may seem problematic, all three refer largely to one of the four types of unrealistic optimism we have identified: Unrealistic comparative optimism – group. That is, these artifact explanations are more pertinent to the comparative estimates made by a group of people than to the estimates made by individuals or to situations where researchers compare absolute risk estimates with an objective standard. Furthermore, for several reasons, we believe scale attenuation and minority undersampling are not serious concerns.

First, the proposed artifacts are chiefly a concern for rare, negative events. Yet unrealistic optimism is not limited to rare negative events. Numerous studies reliably demonstrate unrealistic comparative optimism for common events including divorce, heart disease, hypertension, influenza, and auto accidents. Second, the scale attenuation argument claims that unrealistic optimism is caused by a ceiling effect that prevents people at high risk from indicating the full magnitude of their risk. In fact, however, responses at the top of comparative risk scales are quite rare even for people known to be at high risk. For example, three separate studies found that smokers rated their risk of smoking-related health problems about average or only slightly above average (Milam, Sussman, Ritt-Olson, & Dent, 2000; Reppucci, Revenson, Aber, & Reppucci, 1991; Strecher, Kreuter, & Kobrin, 1995). In none of the studies did smokers report that their risk was “moderately,” “substantially” or “much” higher than that of the average person. The typical observation with comparative risk judgments is that a majority of people claim much below-average to slightly below-average risk and a minority report slightly above average risk. Thus, a ceiling effect is rarely, if ever, the reason why the mean response is “below average.”

Third, some researchers have included both an attenuated and non-attenuated scale to assess personal and target risk estimates within the same study using either a within-subjects design (Taylor & Shepperd, 1998) or a between-subjects design (Otten & Van Der Pligt, 1996). Although the effect was larger when using an attenuated scale, these studies found unrealistic optimism with both types of scales, suggesting that scale attenuation, although a valid artifact in principle, may pose little threat in practice. Moreover, a host of studies that controlled for scale attenuation and minority undersampling demonstrated unrealistic comparative optimism for outcomes such as divorce (Rothman et al., 1996), heart disease (Lee, 1989), smoking related illnesses (Kreuter & Strecher, 1995; McCoy et al., 1992; McKenna, Warburton, & Winwood, 1993; Williams & Clarke, 1997), quitting smoking (Weinstein, Slovic, & Gibson, 2004; Williams & Clarke, 1997), the end of a romantic relationship (MacDonald & Ross, 1999), and for common events among students (Dunning & Story, 1991; Shepperd, Helweg-Larsen, & Ortega, 2003) and spontaneously self-generated events (Hoorens et al., 2008).

Although minority undersampling may present a problem for a single sample, it is not problematic when researchers evaluate many samples. Minority undersampling is the finding that, with an uncommon population characteristic (such as a rare genetic mutation), more samples will have less than the expected number of cases of the characteristic than will have more than the expected number of cases. Note that this finding refers to the number of samples of each type. However, the rate of an event in a population is not estimated from the number of samples, but from the number of cases in the samples. For example, a genetic mutation that occurs in only 2% of population may not appear in any given sample of 50 people. However, if we examine 20 groups of 50 people, we will on average observe the disease 2% of the time. In some samples, the incidence may be 0 or 1%; in other samples, the incidence will be higher than 2%. However, the average across samples will be 2%. Minority undersampling does not bias estimates of the frequency of a characteristic in the population. Similarly, it has no relevance to the issue of whether more people overestimate or underestimate their risk. In short, although some samples may contain no cases of a rare event, other samples may contain a disproportionate number of cases. When researchers average across samples, the sample estimates should balance out and eliminate the influence of minority undersampling.

Our comments about the first two potential artifacts are not meant to suggest that researchers can uniformly ignore issues of scale attenuation and minority undersampling. We merely note that these two issues cannot account for the widespread presence of unrealistic optimism.

A Closer Look at Base Rate Regression

Base rate regression is the tendency to make less extreme evaluations of the average person than of oneself. Base rate regression is peculiar. For several reasons we doubt that it should even be considered an artifact. Rather, it should be viewed as merely one of many explanations for the finding that people can believe that they are less at risk than their peers.

The first way in which base rate regression is peculiar is that people sometimes do not even think of the average person when asked to compare their risk to the average person. Rather, they think of an exemplar for the event (Perloff & Fetzer, 1986; Weinstein, 1980). For negative events, the exemplar is often a high-risk person. Thus, people may think of a heavy-drinker friend when estimating their comparative risk for a drinking problem and a poor-driver friend when estimating their comparative risk for an automobile accident. In short, the reason estimates for the average person depart from actual base rate is not because of base rate regression, but because people think of an exemplar high-risk person when asked to consider the average person.

Second, it can be hard to pinpoint what pattern of data is required to demonstrate the base rate artifact. When the actual base rate is extremely rare (e.g., 1%), the pattern that presumably illustrates the base rate artifact is straightforward. The pattern is less clear, though, when the actual base rate is not extreme. For example, one study reported that the actual base rate for divorce was 38% (Rothman et al., 1996). Would an estimated base rate higher or lower than 38% be regressive? One might argue that any difference between the estimated base rate and the actual base rate illustrates regression. However, such a response is problematic in that it means that both more extreme and less extreme estimates can illustrate base rate regression. Such a prospect contradicts the definition of statistical regression. Incidentally, in the Rothman et al. study, participants estimated that the average person had a 42.7% chance of divorce, yet estimated that they personally had a 21.1% chance of divorce.1 Both estimates differed significantly from the actual base rate of 38%, and it is difficult to see how this pattern illustrates base rate regression.

Third, several studies demonstrate unrealistic comparative optimism even after providing people base rate information, which should control for base rate regression. Often the studies that included base rate information were designed to examine hypotheses regarding bracing for bad news (Sweeny & Shepperd, 2007; Taylor & Shepperd, 1998). These studies find that people will show unrealistic comparative optimism even though they have base rate information.

Perhaps the most sensible approach is to think about base rate regression not as an artifact, but rather as merely one of several explanations for the observation of egocentrism in comparative judgments. When making comparative judgments, people tend to focus primarily on their personal qualities and neglect the qualities of the more generalized target (such as the average person; Chambers, Windschitl, & Suls, 2003; Eiser, Pahl, & Prins, 2001; Klar & Giladi, 1997; Kruger, 1999). When evaluating their comparative risk, people typically consider things they do that influence their personal risk yet neglect to consider things that other people do that influence their own risk (Weinstein & Lachendro, 1982). Evidence suggests that egocentricism arises for many reasons. The reasons include focusing attention on oneself rather than on the others (i.e., focalism; Windschitl, Kruger, & Simms, 2003), having more information available about self than about others when making judgments (i.e., rational discounting; Kruger, Windschitl, Burrus, Fessel, & Chambers, 2008), using different information to evaluate oneself vs. others (i.e., case based vs. distributional information; Klar, Medding, & Sarel, 1996), and, yes, base rate regression (Moore & Small, 2007). These various reasons, much like base rate regression, illustrate how unrealistic optimism can arise from how people respond to and process information at their disposal.

Other Studies that Cannot Be Explained as Artifacts

Two studies have examined the group form of unrealistic comparative optimism yet are by their very nature not subject to an artifact interpretation. In the first study, 62.5% of participants in a Phase 1 clinical trial reported that they were more likely than the average participant to experience health benefits from the trial (Jansen et al., 2011). These reports occurred even though it was clearly explained at the outset of the study (and most patients reported understanding) that the purpose of the trial was to determine the feasibility of conducting a randomized clinical trial in the future and that the treatment offered little likelihood of any health benefits. Because health benefits for all participants were effectively zero, the findings cannot be explained by minority undersampling (there was no undersampling of people who would not receive benefits), scale attenuation (even a dichotomous scale would be sufficiently sensitive to uncovering effects), or to base rate regression (the base rate for everyone was 0%).

In the second study, people rate equivalent groups differently depending on the context. Students at two equivalent universities rated their risk for eight negative events (M = 25.6%) and the risk of fellow students from their university (M = 25.6%) as the same, but as less than the risk of students at the other university (M = 28.3%) (Harris et al., 2000). Participants made estimates for several common events (controlling for minority undersampling) using a 100-point probability scale (controlling for scale attenuation). But more important, the findings themselves cannot be explained by the three artifacts, which predict that participants would show unrealistic comparative optimism relative to students at both their university and the other university. None of the three artifact accounts offer an explanation for why introducing a new comparison group should eliminate comparative optimism typically seen when people compare their risk to people at their own university.

Boundary Conditions on Unrealistic Optimism

We do not suggest that unrealistic optimism occurs at all times for all events. Research reveals a number of moderators or boundary conditions that influence the extent to which people display unrealistic optimism. People are most likely to display unrealistic absolute optimism about their future when they anticipate no imminent challenge to their predictions and when they believe that they can control the outcome (Carroll, Sweeny, & Shepperd, 2006). For example, students often overestimate the score they will receive on a forthcoming exam when the exam is several weeks away. However, as the day of the exam draws near, they tend to shelve their optimistic forecast for a more realistic one. And on the day the scored exams are returned, students abandon their optimism in favor of pessimism (Shepperd et al., 1996). In such instances, concerns with accountability and with bracing for bad news become preeminent.

Research also shows that a variety of factors can reduce unrealistic absolute optimism, including having people “unpack” their task completion estimates (i.e., asking them to estimate the time to complete each part of a task) (Kruger & Evans, 2004) and giving people base rate information (Rothman et al., 1996; Sweeny & Shepperd, 2007; Weinstein & Lyon, 1999). Other research finds situations where people are decidedly pessimistic. For example, people often overestimate their absolute risk for rare events (Chambers et al., 2003; Kruger & Burrus, 2004; Price, Pentecost, & Voth, 2002) and for highly publicized risks such as breast cancer (Lipkus et al., 2005), colon cancer (Weinstein, Atwood, et al., 2004), and AIDs (van der Velde, van der Pligt, & Hooykaas, 1994).

Several studies reveal boundary conditions for unrealistic comparative optimism. For example, a review of the literature (Helweg-Larsen & Shepperd, 2001) revealed that people show less unrealistic comparative optimism at the group level when the event is uncontrollable, when people have prior experience with the event, when feedback is proximal, and when comparing with close others as opposed to distant others. And, in contrast to the findings for unrealistic absolute optimism, researchers find that people typically display greater unrealistic comparative optimism for rare negative events than for common negative events. Indeed, a number of studies find something akin to unrealistic comparative pessimism for common negative events (Chambers et al., 2003; Kruger & Burrus, 2004; Price et al., 2002), a finding that appears to arise largely from egocentric thinking in that people fail to recognize that common events are not only likely to happen to them, but also likely to happen to other people.

The fact that unrealistic optimism is responsive to psychologically rich environmental forces such as controllability, personal experience, and outcome proximity suggests that unrealistic optimism is not easily reducible to a statistical artifact, and offers even further evidence that unrealistic optimism is a robust human characteristic.

Questions that Remain

Our identification of four categories of unrealistic optimism raises questions about the extent to which the different types of optimism are similar. Our answers to these questions are largely speculative and speak to a need for more research because few studies have assessed multiple types of unrealistic optimism simultaneously.

Conceptual Distinctions among Types of Unrealistic Optimism

The first question is whether the four types of unrealistic optimism are really different or whether they merely differ in measurement but otherwise represent a single underlying construct. We suspect that the difference between the two forms of unrealistic absolute optimism (i.e., individual vs. group) is simply one of measurement. Each represents a bias in judgment relative to some objective standard. Although measured differently, they nevertheless are likely to be highly correlated and interchangeable. We suspect the same is true for the two forms of unrealistic comparative optimism (i.e., individual vs. group); they differ in how they are measured but likely are tapping the same underlying construct. Importantly, our suspicions lack empirical demonstration. It remains to be seen whether the individual and group forms of unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism merely reflect measurement differences.

We suspect that unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism reflect different underlying constructs. With unrealistic absolute optimism, people make a single judgment—their personal risk—typically on a numerical scale. That judgment is then compared with an external, objective representation of their actual risk, about which they likely have only a vague sense. With unrealistic comparative optimism, people ostensibly make two judgments—their personal risk and the risk for someone else—both typically on a verbal scale. In some instances of unrealistic comparative optimism people do make a single judgment, but that single judgment reflects an evaluation of how their personal risk compares with the risk of someone else (e.g., “How does your risk compare with the average person’s risk?”). Either way, there is no externally derived, objective standard. Thus, with unrealistic comparative optimism, people can be inaccurate in their personal estimate, their estimate for the comparison target, or both. By contrast, with unrealistic absolute optimism, people can be inaccurate in only their personal estimates.

Prevalence

The second question is whether the different types of unrealistic optimism differ in their prevalence. We suspect that laypeople’s absolute risk estimates are largely guesses for most events and are responsive to contextual factors. For instance, the more information people have about their own risk and the objective standard (e.g., base rate information), the less likely they will show unrealistic absolute optimism. Indeed, unrealistic absolute optimism sometimes can be difficult to find in research, in part because people overestimate small probabilities and many negative events are relative rare. In contrast, unrealistic comparative optimism is quite robust. Although researchers have identified a variety of conditions that influence the occurrence of unrealistic comparative optimism (Helweg-Larsen & Shepperd, 2001) and it too is responsive to base rate information (Taylor & Shepperd, 1998), it can be quite difficult to eliminate (Weinstein & Klein, 1995). It is thus likely to be more prevalent and more resistant to intervention.

We do not wish to imply that comparative predictions are never accurate. Fast runners in a marathon can accurately predict that they are likely to finish the race sooner than the average runner, whereas slow runners can accurately predict that they are likely to finish the race later than the average runner. In a similar vein, people may understand risk in a relative sense. For example, they may know that they are more at risk for heart disease than cancer even if they overestimate (or underestimate) the risk of both outcomes. In this sense, people may be generally accurate in comparative estimates irrespective of the accuracy of their absolute estimates.

Causes

Third, do the different types of optimism have different causes? Three decades of research on unrealistic optimism suggest that cognitive, affective, and motivational factors likely contribute to both unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism. However, the specific factors that give rise to the two forms of unrealistic optimism and their ultimate effects can vary. To illustrate, many of the causes of unrealistic comparative optimism (e.g., representativeness heuristic, person-positivity bias, underestimating other’s control) arise from how people think about the comparison target such as the average person (Shepperd et al., 2002). These causes do not apply to unrealistic absolute optimism because unrealistic absolute optimism does not entail making an estimate for a comparison target. Of course, there are some causes that can contribute to both unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism, including self-enhancement and overestimations of personal control (Shepperd et al., 2002). Few studies have explored both unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism simultaneously, and thus a clear understanding of how different causes may influence the two forms of unrealistic optimism awaits further research.

Situational Determinants

Fourth, do the different types of optimism manifest in different situations? Although more research is needed on this question, some evidence suggests that the situational factors that elicit unrealistic absolute optimism may also elicit unrealistic comparative optimism. For instance, unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism are likely more common when people perceive that events are under personal control (Carroll et al., 2006; Harris, 1996; Klein & Helweg-Larsen, 2002) and when they believe that their estimates will go unchallenged (Sweeny & Shepperd, 2007). Finally, evidence suggests that negative mood and prior experience with a negative event can decrease both unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism, primarily because both appears to affect personal risk estimates rather than risk estimates for others (Helweg-Larsen & Shepperd, 2001). However, not all studies have replicated this mood effect (Drace et al., 2009).

We know of at least one situational factor—event commonality—that has opposite effects on unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism. People appear particularly inclined to show unrealistic comparative optimism for low-frequency, negative events, a finding that appears largely attributable to egocentric thinking (Chambers et al., 2003; Eiser et al., 2001; Klar & Giladi, 1997; Kruger, 1999; Kruger & Burrus, 2004; Price et al., 2002). Thus, when people compare personal risk estimates with their risk estimates for the average person, they appear optimistic. However, when their personal risk estimates for rare negative events are compared with base rates, people appear pessimistic, apparently because of a poor understanding of probability and small numbers (Lyon & Slovic, 1976). That is, people recognize that their chances of experiencing a rare event are small, yet fail to appreciate just how small those chances are. Thus the same rare event may prompt unrealistic comparative optimism and unrealistic absolute pessimism. The reverse is also possible for rare positive events: People often fail to recognize the rarity of low-frequency positive event and thus overestimate the likelihood the positive event will happen to them (demonstrating unrealistic absolute optimism). However, they often simultaneously conclude that because the event is unlikely to happen to them, it also less likely to happen to them than to others (demonstrating unrealistic comparative pessimism).

Consequences

Fifth, do unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism have different consequences? This question is perhaps most important because of the common assumption that unrealistic optimism may place people at risk for negative outcomes. A central component of several psychological models of health, such as the Health Belief Model and Protection Motivation Theory, is that people must perceive themselves as at risk before they undertake positive health behaviors (Maddux & Rogers, 1983; Rogers, 1975; Rosenstock, 1990). Moreover, evidence suggests that people are less likely to take precautions if they perceive their absolute risk as low (Floyd, Prentice-Dunn, & Rogers, 2000; Janz & Becker, 1984). The implication is that unrealistic absolute optimism about one’s health can undermine preventive health behaviors. Consistent with this notion is the finding that smokers who exhibit unrealistic absolute optimism reported lower intentions to quit smoking (Dillard, McCaul, & Klein, 2006).

These effects for unrealistic absolute optimism may extend beyond health outcomes. For example, unrealistic absolute optimism may lead to insufficient preparation to complete tasks. In addition, to the extent that it produces the planning fallacy, unrealistic absolute optimism can lead to inadequate allocation of time to complete tasks, which can lead to its own set of problems (Buehler, Griffin, & Ross, 1994). In addition, unrealistic absolute optimism can lead to disappointment, regret, and other problems when outcomes fall short of expectations (Carroll et al., 2006). For example, one study found that students who were unrealistically optimistic in their exam score estimates reported increases in negative affect after receiving their score, whereas participants who were realistic or pessimistic in their estimates reported a decrease in negative affect after receiving their score (Sweeny & Shepperd, 2010). Another study revealed that college students who displayed unrealistic absolute optimism about their academic performance suffered declines in self-esteem and well-being over time (Robins & Beer, 2001).

We would be remiss if we did not acknowledge possible benefits of unrealistic absolute optimism. Evidence suggests that dispositional optimism offers a number of benefits including greater goal persistence, positive affect, and hope (Armor & Taylor, 1998; Scheier & Carver, 1988). It stands to reason that unrealistic absolute optimism may offer similar benefits. Moreover, one study found that unrealistically optimistic, HIV-infected men displayed more healthful behavior than did HIV-infected men who were not unrealistically optimistic (Taylor et al., 1992).

Regarding unrealistic comparative optimism, some evidence suggests that unrealistic comparative optimism can have more subtle and worrisome consequences. For instance, one study found that middle-aged adults who displayed unrealistic comparative optimism about their risk of a heart attack were also less knowledgeable about the risk factors for heart disease, less able to retain new information, and less worried about having a heart attack (Radcliffe & Klein, 2002). Another study offered suggestive evidence that unrealistic optimism about the time to complete an easy (vs. difficult) task corresponded with wagering more money on the outcome of a trivia test (Moore & Small, 2007). Perhaps most persuasive are the results of an experimental study that actually manipulated rather than measured unrealistic comparative optimism, thus permitting a clearer understanding of the causal relationship. People who were led to believe that their risk of causing an automobile accident was below (as opposed to above) average reported lower intentions to use seat belts, to drive slower on the freeway, and to use public transportation (Klein, 1997).

Importantly, many of the studies of unrealistic comparative optimism, as well as many of the studies of unrealistic absolute optimism, are correlational. That is, the researchers measured comparative or absolute risk judgments and correlated these judgments with health behaviors. We cannot establish from these correlational studies whether unrealistic optimism influenced the behaviors, whether the behaviors produced the optimism, or whether a third variable produced both (Weinstein & Nicolich, 1993). Also, given that comparative risk ratings can be accurate or inaccurate even if they are low, one cannot use a correlation between comparative optimism and a behavior to infer anything about the behavioral consequences of unrealistic optimism.

Just as important as the need for experimental studies that manipulate unrealistic optimism is the need for studies that examine behavior. Few studies link unrealistic optimism to actual behavior, let alone examine whether unrealistic absolute and unrealistic comparative optimism have different behavioral consequences. The evidence is clear that unrealistic optimism can lead to negative emotional consequences, such as negative affect and declines in self-esteem (Robins & Beer, 2001; Sweeny & Shepperd, 2010) when outcomes fall short of optimistic expectations, and can influence behavior intentions. However, evidence linking unrealistic optimism to behavior remains thin. The meager evidence leads to some sobering questions. For example, what difference does it make that people underestimate their risk for cardiovascular disease or having radon gas problems if there are no behavioral consequences? Why does it matter that smokers perceive themselves as at less risk for smoking-related illnesses than other, similar smokers if it does not influence smoking rates or quitting? Although unrealistic optimism may have behavioral consequences, the behavioral consequences need empirical demonstration.

Summary and Conclusions

Unrealistic optimism is not a unitary construct. Rather, evidence suggests four distinct types of unrealistic optimism that vary according to the standard of comparison (an objective standard vs. other people) and the level of analysis (individual vs. group). As many researchers in this area are already aware, different measurement approaches to unrealistic optimism are influenced by different variables and can represent different psychological constructs (Klein & Zajac, 2009; Shepperd et al., 2002).

The Need for Consistent Terminology

Our review should be viewed as a call for researchers to take greater care in their use of terminology. First, although we have used the terms ourselves on occasion, it may be time to retire the terms optimistic bias, optimism bias, overoptimism, and illusion of unique invulnerability. Researchers have used these terms to refer to the tendency for people to believe that they are more likely to experience positive events and less likely to experience negative events than a comparison group, but the terms are too imprecise to be useful (Shepperd et al., 2002). The term illusion of unique invulnerability is particularly problematic because it is not clear that the judgment represents an illusion, is unique, or should be interpreted as conveying perceptions of invulnerability. Fortunately, we have found only a few instances of researchers using this term. Regarding optimism bias, overoptimism, or optimistic bias, the difference in estimates for oneself vs. others may arise from distortions in personal estimates, distortions in estimates for others, or both. For example, people may be pessimistic in their personal estimates yet even more pessimistic in their estimates for the average person—leading to comparative optimism. In such instances, optimism exists only in a relative sense and it is potentially misleading to label the distortion as optimism when the estimates could actually represent varying degrees of pessimism.

We advocate that researchers adopt common terminology to refer to different operations of optimistic outcome expectations and believe that common terminology will help the area in many ways. We suggest that the terms unrealistic absolute optimism and unrealistic comparative optimism describe the relevant phenomena adequately. Unrealistic absolute optimism conveys the idea that the expectation is unrealistic and optimistic relative to an objective standard, whereas unrealistic comparative optimism conveys the idea that the expectation is unrealistic and optimistic relative to the estimates the person makes for other people. At present, researchers cannot determine with certainty from the title, the list of key terms, or sometimes even the abstract what type of optimism researchers are examining in a given study. Using consistent terminology will expedite literature searches, reduce the possibility of researchers generalizing or drawing conclusions from findings regarding one type of optimism to other types of optimism, and reduce the likelihood that researchers erroneously criticize one type of optimism based on shortcomings in research on a second, empirically distinct type of optimism.

Addressing the Artifact Criticisms

Our review also reveals that recently proposed artifact explanations are not nearly as problematic as they might seem. Scale attenuation is potentially relevant, but there is scant direct evidence of bias from ceiling effects in this body of research, and unrealistic optimism remains when scales are unrestricted. In addition, careful examination reveals that minority undersampling is not relevant to any of the ways in which unrealistic optimism is actually assessed, and base rate regression does not seems to be an artifact at all. Finally, the artifacts largely pertain to only one of the four types of unrealistic optimism—unrealistic comparative optimism at the group level. Moreover, several studies demonstrating this form of unrealistic optimism cannot be explained in terms of statistical artifacts. Researchers should always attempt to minimize the potential influence of artifacts to avoid interpretational ambiguity. Indeed, we believe that some of the basic findings of comparative optimism, such as the conditions that moderate the effect, deserve replication with careful attention given to controlling for the purported statistical artifacts.

In some instances, the influence of variables other than the tendency to downplay personal risk may keep a particular measurement approach from revealing unrealistic optimism. An example is the overestimation of the base rate of colon cancer, which leads people to overestimate their probability of developing this disease despite their claim that their risk is below that of their peers. However, the collective evidence suggests that their unrealistic comparative optimism about colon cancer is real, strong, and quite robust (Rothman et al., 1996).

To minimize artifact criticisms, we recommend that researchers take the following precautions in designing studies. Our recommendations are specific to research on unrealistic comparative optimism because this form of optimism has received the most criticism by proponents of the artifactual explanations (Harris & Hahn, 2011). Our recommendations must also be viewed cautiously for reasons we discuss. First, researchers should be as specific as possible in describing the comparison group. Asking people to compare their risk to the “average person” is too vague to be useful. When possible, researchers should direct people to compare their risk to the average person of their same age and sex in their community, or at the university (if students), or participating in the research study. Constraining the comparison target eliminates interpretational ambiguity that arises from not knowing who people are thinking about when making comparative judgments. However, we acknowledge that this recommendation may be problematic if constraining the comparison target leads to unnatural or cumbersome wording of survey items. The recommendation may also be problematic when constraining the comparison target undermines the investigator’s research goal.

Second, when reasonable, researchers should use separate scales to assess participants’ estimates of their personal risk judgments and a comparison group’s risk, thereby permitting examination of which judgments change in response to experimental manipulations. Importantly, research must recognize that indirect comparative judgments are not synonymous with direct comparative judgments (Ranby et al., 2010). Moreover, there likely are circumstances where direct comparative judgments are preferable to indirect comparative judgments.

Third, when possible, researchers should examine risk perceptions using more than one scale (e.g., a 0–100% plus a Likert-type subjective probability scale). A 0% to 100% eliminates range restriction as a potential artifact. Researchers must be careful, however, not to over-interpret mean responses on this scale because of people’s poor numeracy skills and their idiosyncratic use of percentage scales (Bruine de Bruin & Carman, 2012; Cameron, Sherman, Marteau, & Brown, 2009). A Likert-type scale can create a range restriction, but is less susceptible to innumeracy problems. By including both scales in research, investigators can be more confident in their findings if results are consistent across the two scales.

Conclusions

The measurement and conceptualization of unrealistic optimism has become much richer and more complex over the past several years, which necessitates a more nuanced treatment of the role that moderating variables and artifacts might play. For instance, although people show a strong tendency toward unrealistic optimism in predictions, when people make absolute judgments, mistaken beliefs about the absolute sizes of risks can sometimes mask the tendency toward optimism, especially when people make numerical judgments. This tendency leads to underestimation of personal risk for some events and to overestimation of personal risk for others. When people make comparative judgments, however, the wealth of evidence for unrealistic optimism is clear and consistent and cannot be easily explained by statistical artifacts. Thirty years of research has illuminated the prevalence, causes, moderators, and consequences of unrealistic optimism. We hope that the next generation of research in this area witnesses more experimental work, more research on moderators and behavioral consequences, and more efforts to reduce unintended negative consequences of unrealistic optimism.

Acknowledgments

Preparation of this article was funded in part by a Templeton Foundation Grant (12829) and an Intergovernmental Personnel Act fellowship to the first author from the National Cancer Institute and support from the Barnes-Jewish Hospital Foundation and the American Cancer Society (MRSG-11-214-01-CPPB) to the third author.

Footnotes

1

This example illustrates unrealistic comparative optimism in that personal estimates (M = 21.1%) averaged lower than estimates for the average same sex person (M = 42.7%). It also illustrates unrealistic absolute optimism in that personal estimates averaged lower the population base rate of 38%.

Contributor Information

James A. Shepperd, University of Florida

William M. P. Klein, National Cancer Institute

Erika A. Waters, Washington University School of Medicine

Neil D. Weinstein, Rutgers University

References

  1. Armor DA, Taylor SE, editors. Situated optimism: Specific outcome expectancies and self-regulation. Vol. 30. New York: Academic Press; 1998. [Google Scholar]
  2. Ayanian JZ, Cleary PD. Perceived risks of heart disease and cancer among cigarette smokers. JAMA: Journal of the American Medical Association. 1999;281(11):1019–1021. doi: 10.1001/jama.281.11.1019. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Bay C. Poor Risk Management, Unrealistic Optimism Collapsed Housing: MBA. DSNews.com. 2010 http://www.dsnews.com/articles/poor-risk-management-unrealistic-optimism-collapsed-housing-mba-2010-05-26.
  4. Bruine de Bruin W, Carman KG. Measuring risk perceptions: what does the excessive use of 50% mean? Medical Decision Making. 2012;32:232–236. doi: 10.1177/0272989X11404077. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Buehler R, Griffin D, MacDonald H. The role of motivated reasoning in optimistic time predictions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1997;23(3):238–247. doi: 10.1177/0146167297233003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  6. Buehler R, Griffin D, Ross M. Exploring the “planning fallacy”: Why people underestimate their task completion times. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1994;67(3):366–381. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.67.3.366. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  7. Burger JM, Palmer ML. Changes in and generalization of unrealistic optimism following experiences with stressful events: Reactions to the 1989 California earthquake. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1992;18(1):39–43. doi: 10.1177/0146167292181006. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  8. Byram SJ. Cognitive and motivational factors influencing time prediction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied. 1997;3(3):216–239. doi: 10.1037/1076-898x.3.3.216. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  9. Calderon TG. Predictive properties of analysts’ forecasts of corporate earnings. The Mid-Atlantic Journal of Business. 1993;29:41–58. [Google Scholar]
  10. Cameron LD, Sherman KA, Marteau TM, Brown PM. Impact of genetic risk information and type of disease on perceived risk, anticipated affect, and expected consequences of genetic tests. Health Psychology. 2009;28:307–316. doi: 10.1037/a0013947. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Carroll P, Sweeny K, Shepperd JA. Forsaking optimism. Review of General Psychology. 2006;10(1):56–73. doi: 10.1037/1089-2680.10.1.56. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  12. Centers for Disease Control and Prevention. Vital Signs: Current Cigarette Smoking Among Adults Aged ≥ 18 Years - United States, 2005–2010. Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report. 2011;60(33):1207–12. Retrieved 5 October 2012, from http://www.cdc.gov/mmwr/preview/mmwrhtml/mm6035a5.htm?s_cid=%20mm6035a5.htm_w. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  13. Chambers JR, Windschitl PD. Biases in Social Comparative Judgments: The Role of Nonmotivated Factors in Above-Average and Comparative-Optimism Effects. Psychological Bulletin. 2004;130(5):813–838. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.130.5.813. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  14. Chambers JR, Windschitl PD, Suls J. Egocentrism, Event Frequency, and Comparative Optimism: When What Happens Frequently Is “More Likely to Happen to Me”. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2003;29(11):1343–1356. doi: 10.1177/0146167203256870. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Chen PW. When optimism is unrealistic. New York Times. 2011 http://www.nytimes.com/2011/03/03/health/views/03chen.html?_r=1.
  16. Dillard AJ, McCaul KD, Klein WMP. Unrealistic Optimism in Smokers: Implications for Smoking Myth Endorsement and Self-Protective Motivation. Journal of Health Communication. 2006;11(Suppl1):93–102. doi: 10.1080/10810730600637343. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Dillard AJ, Midboe AM, Klein WMP. The dark side of optimism: Unrealistic optimism about problems with alcohol predicts subsequent negative event experiences. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2009;35(11):1540–1550. doi: 10.1177/0146167209343124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  18. Drace S, Desrichard O, Shepperd JA, Hoorens V. Does mood really influence comparative optimism? Tracking an elusive effect. British Journal of Social Psychology. 2009;48(4):579–599. doi: 10.1348/014466608x387098. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Dunning D, Story AL. Depression, realism, and the overconfidence effect: Are the sadder wiser when predicting future actions and events? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1991;61(4):521–532. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.61.4.521. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Eiser JR, Pahl S, Prins YRA. Optimism, pessimism, and the direction of self–other comparisons. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2001;37(1):77–84. doi: 10.1006/jesp.2000.1438. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  21. Epley N, Dunning D. Feeling “holier than thou”: Are self-serving assessments produced by errors in self- or social prediction? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2000;79(6):861–875. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.79.6.861. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Floyd DL, Prentice-Dunn S, Rogers RW. A meta-analysis of research on protection motivation theory. Journal of Applied Social Psychology. 2000;30(2):407–429. doi: 10.1111/j.1559-1816.2000.tb02323.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  23. Gail MH, Brinton LA, Byar DP, Corle DK, Green SB, Shairer C, Mulvihill JJ. Projecting individualized probabilities of developiong breast cancer for white females who are bieng examined annually. Journal of the National Cancer Institute. 1989;81(24):1879–1886. doi: 10.1093/jnci/81.24.1879. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Gerrard M, Gibbons FX, Warner TD. Effects of reviewing risk-relevant behavior on perceived vulnerability among women marines. Health Psychology. 1991;10(3):173–179. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.10.3.173. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Griffin D, Buehler R. Frequency, probability, and prediction: Easy solutions to cognitive illusions? Cognitive Psychology. 1999;38(1):48–78. doi: 10.1006/cogp.1998.0707. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Harris AJL, Hahn U. Unrealistic optimism about future life events: A cautionary note. Psychological Review. 2011;118(1):135–154. doi: 10.1037/a0020997. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Harris P. Sufficient grounds for optimism? The relationship between perceived controllability and optimistic bias. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology. 1996;15(1):9–52. doi: 10.1521/jscp.1996.15.1.9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  28. Harris P, Middleton W, Joiner R. The typical student as an in-group member: Eliminating optimistic bias by reducing social distance. European Journal of Social Psychology. 2000;30(2):235–253. doi: 10.1002/(sici)1099-0992(200003/04)30:2&#x0003c;235::aid-ejsp990&#x0003e;3.0.co;2-g. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  29. Heine SJ, Lehman DR. Cultural variation in unrealistic optimism: Does the West feel more vulnerable than the East? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1995;68(4):595–607. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.68.4.595. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  30. Helweg-Larsen M, Nielsen GA. Smoking cross-culturally: Risk perceptions among young adults in Denmark and the United States. Psychology & Health. 2009;24(1):81–93. doi: 10.1080/08870440801932656. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  31. Helweg-Larsen M, Shepperd JA. Do moderators of the optimistic bias affect personal or target risk estimates? A review of the literature. Personality and Social Psychology Review. 2001;5(1):74–95. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr0501_5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  32. Hoorens V, Buunk BP. Social comparison of health risks: Locus of control, the person-positivity bias, and unrealistic optimism. Journal of Applied Social Psychology. 1993;23(4):291–302. doi: 10.1111/j.1559-1816.1993.tb01088.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  33. Hoorens V, Smits T, Shepperd JA. Comparative optimism in the spontaneous generation of future life-events. British Journal of Social Psychology. 2008;47(3):441–451. doi: 10.1348/014466607x236023. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  34. Jansen LA, Appelbaum PS, Klein WMP, Weinstein ND, Cook W, Fogel JS, Sulmasy DP. Unrealistic optimism in early-phase oncology trials. IRB: Ethics & Human Research. 2011;33(1):1–8. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  35. Janz NK, Becker MH. The Health Belief Model: A decade later. Health Education Quarterly. 1984;11(1):1–47. doi: 10.1177/109019818401100101. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  36. Kahneman D. Thinking, fast and slow. McMillan; 2011. [Google Scholar]
  37. Klar Y, Giladi EE. No one in my group can be below the group’s average: A robust positivity bias in favor of anonymous peers. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1997;73(5):885–901. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.73.5.885. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Klar Y, Medding A, Sarel D. Nonunique invulnerability: Singular versus distributional probabilities and unrealistic optimism in comparative risk judgments. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 1996;67(2):229–245. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1996.0076. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  39. Klein CTF, Helweg-Larsen M. Perceived control and the optimistic bias: A meta-analytic review. Psychology & Health. 2002;17(4):437–446. doi: 10.1080/0887044022000004920. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  40. Klein WM. Objective standards are not enough: Affective, self-evaluative, and behavioral responses to social comparison information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1997;72(4):763–774. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.72.4.763. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Klein WMP, Zajac LE. Imagining a rosy future: The psychology of optimism. In: Markman KD, Klein WMP, Suhr JA, editors. Handbook of imagination and mental simulation. New York, NY, US: Psychology Press; 2009. pp. 313–329. [Google Scholar]
  42. Koole S, Spijker Mt. Overcoming the planning fallacy through willpower: Effects of implementation intentions on actual and predicted task-completion times. European Journal of Social Psychology. 2000;30(6):873–888. doi: 10.1002/1099-0992(200011/12)30:6&#x0003c;873::aid-ejsp22&#x0003e;3.0.co;2-u. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  43. Kreuter MW, Strecher VJ. Changing inaccurate perceptions of health risk: Results from a randomized trial. Health Psychology. 1995;14(1):56–63. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.14.1.56. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Kruger J. Lake Wobegon be gone! The “below-average effect” and the egocentric nature of comparative ability judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1999;77(2):221–232. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.77.2.221. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Kruger J, Burrus J. Egocentrism and focalism in unrealistic optimism (and pessimism) Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2004;40(3):332–340. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2003.06.002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  46. Kruger J, Evans M. If you don’t want to be late, enumerate: Unpacking reduces the planning fallacy. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2004;40(5):586–598. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2003.11.001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  47. Kruger J, Windschitl PD, Burrus J, Fessel F, Chambers JR. The rational side of egocentrism in social comparisons. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2008;44(2):220–232. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2007.04.001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  48. Lee C. Perceptions of immunity to disease in adult smokers. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1989;12(3):267–277. doi: 10.1007/bf00844871. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  49. Lipkus IM, Klein WMP, Skinner CS, Rimer BK. Breast cancer risk perceptions and breast cancer worry: What predicts what? Journal of Risk Research. 2005;8(5):439–452. doi: 10.1080/1366987042000311018. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  50. Lyon D, Slovic P. Dominance of accuracy information and neglect of base rates in probability estimation. Acta Psychologica. 1976;40(4):286–298. doi: 10.1016/0001-6918(76)90032-9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  51. MacDonald TK, Ross M. Assessing the accuracy of predictions about dating relationships: How and why do lovers’ predictions differ from those made by observers? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1999;25(11):1417–1429. doi: 10.1177/0146167299259007. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  52. Maddux JE, Rogers RW. Protection motivation and self-efficacy: A revised theory of fear appeals and attitude change. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 1983;19(5):469–479. doi: 10.1016/0022-1031(83)90023-9. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  53. McCoy SB, Gibbons FX, Reis TJ, Gerrard M, Luus CAE, Wald Sufka A. Perceptions of smoking risk as a function of smoking status. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1992;15(5):469–488. doi: 10.1007/bf00844942. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  54. McKenna FP. It won’t happen to me: Unrealistic optimism or illusion of control? British Journal of Psychology. 1993;84(1):39–50. [Google Scholar]
  55. McKenna FP, Warburton DM, Winwood M. Exploring the limits of optimism: The case of smokers’ decision making. British Journal of Psychology. 1993;84(3):389–394. doi: 10.1111/j.2044-8295.1993.tb02490.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Milam JE, Sussman S, Ritt-Olson A, Dent CW. Perceived invulnerability and cigarette smoking among adolescents. Addictive Behaviors. 2000;25(1):71–80. doi: 10.1016/s0306-4603(99)00034-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Moore DA, Small DA. Error and bias in comparative judgment: On being both better and worse than we think we are. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2007;92(6):972–989. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.92.6.972. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Newby-Clark IR, Ross M, Buehler R, Koehler DJ, Griffin D. People focus on optimistic scenarios and disregard pessimistic scenarios while predicting task completion times. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied. 2000;6(3):171–182. doi: 10.1037/1076-898x.6.3.171. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  59. Optimism Bias. 2012 Retrieved August 25, 2012, from http://www.ted.com/talks/tali_sharot_the_optimism_bias.html.
  60. Otten W, Van Der Pligt J. Context effects in the measurement of comparative optimism in probability judgments. Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology. 1996;15(1):80–101. [Google Scholar]
  61. Perloff LS, Fetzer BK. Self–other judgments and perceived vulnerability to victimization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1986;50(3):502–510. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.50.3.502. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  62. Price PC, Pentecost HC, Voth RD. Perceived event frequency and the optimistic bias: Evidence for a two-process model of personal risk judgments. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2002;38(3):242–252. doi: 10.1006/jesp.2001.1509. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  63. Radcliffe NM, Klein WMP. Dispositional, unrealistic and comparative optimism: Differential relations with the knowledge and processing of risk information and beliefs about personal risk. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2002;28(6):836–846. doi: 10.1177/0146167202289012. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  64. Ranby KW, Aiken LS, Gerend MA, Erchull MJ. Perceived susceptibility measures are not interchangeable: Absollute, direct comparative, and indirect comparative risk. Health Psychology. 2010;29:20–28. doi: 10.1037/a0016623. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  65. Reppucci JD, Revenson TA, Aber M, Reppucci ND. Unrealistic optimism among adolescent smokers and nonsmokers. The Journal of Primary Prevention. 1991;11(3):227–236. doi: 10.1007/bf01326505. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  66. Robins RW, Beer JS. Positive illusions about the self: Short-term benefits and long-term costs. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2001;80(2):340–352. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.80.2.340. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  67. Rogers RW. A protection motivation theory of fear appeals and attitude change. Journal of Psychology: Interdisciplinary and Applied. 1975;91(1):93–114. doi: 10.1080/00223980.1975.9915803. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  68. Rosenstock IM. The health belief model: Explaining health behavior through expectancies. In: Glanz K, Lewis FM, Rimer BK, editors. Health behavior and health education: Theory, research, and practice. San Francisco, CA, US: Jossey-Bass; 1990. pp. 39–62. [Google Scholar]
  69. Rothman AJ, Klein WM, Weinstein ND. Absolute and relative biases in estimations of personal risk. Journal of Applied Social Psychology. 1996;26(14):1213–1236. doi: 10.1111/j.1559-1816.1996.tb01778.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  70. Scheier MF, Carver CS. Advances in experimental social psychology, Vol. 21: Social psychological studies of the self: Perspectives and programs. San Diego, CA, US: Academic Press; 1988. A model of behavioral self-regulation: Translating intention into action; pp. 303–346. [Google Scholar]
  71. Schoenbaum M. Do smokers understand the mortality effects of smoking? Evidence from the health and retirement survey. American Journal of Public Health. 1997;87(5):755–759. doi: 10.2105/ajph.87.5.755. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  72. Sharot T. The optimism bias. Curr Biol. 2011a;21(23):R941–945. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2011.10.030. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  73. Sharot T. The optimism bias: A tour of the irrationally positive brain. New York, NY, US: Pantheon/Random House; 2011b. [Google Scholar]
  74. Sharot T, Guitart-Masip M, Korn CW, Chowdhury R, Dolan RJ. How dopamine enhances an optimism bias in humans. Curr Biol. 2012;22(16):1477–1481. doi: 10.1016/j.cub.2012.05.053. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Sharot T, Korn CW, Dolan RJ. How unrealistic optimism is maintained in the face of reality. Nature Neuroscience. 2011;14(11):1475–1479. doi: 10.1038/nn.2949. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  76. Shepperd JA, Carroll P, Grace J, Terry M. Exploring the causes of comparative optimism. Psychologica Belgica. 2002;42(1–2):65–98. [Google Scholar]
  77. Shepperd JA, Grace J, Cole LJ, Klein C. Anxiety and Outcome Predictions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2005;31(2):267–275. doi: 10.1177/0146167204271322. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  78. Shepperd JA, Helweg-Larsen M, Ortega L. Are Comparative Risk Judgments Consistent Across Time and Events? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2003;29(9):1169–1180. doi: 10.1177/0146167203254598. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  79. Shepperd JA, Ouellette JA, Fernandez JK. Abandoning unrealistic optimism: Performance estimates and the temporal proximity of self-relevant feedback. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1996;70(4):844–855. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.70.4.844. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  80. Strecher VJ, Kreuter MW, Kobrin SC. Do cigarette smokers have unrealistic perceptions of their heart attack, cancer, and stroke risks? Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1995;18(1):45–54. doi: 10.1007/bf01857704. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  81. Sweeny K, Shepperd JA. Do people brace sensibly? Risk judgments and event likelihood. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2007;33(8):1064–1075. doi: 10.1177/0146167207301024. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  82. Sweeny K, Shepperd JA. The costs of optimism and the benefits of pessimism. Emotion. 2010;10(5):750–753. doi: 10.1037/a0019016. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  83. Taylor KM, Shepperd JA. Bracing for the worst: Severity, testing, and feedback timing as moderators of the optimistic bias. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1998;24(9):915–926. doi: 10.1177/0146167298249001. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  84. Taylor SE, Brown JD. Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin. 1988;103(2):193–210. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.103.2.193. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  85. Taylor SE, Kemeny ME, Aspinwall LG, Schneider SG, Rodriguez R, Herbert M. Optimism, coping, psychological distress, and high-risk sexual behavior among men at risk for acquired immunodeficiency syndrome (AIDS) Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1992;63(3):460–473. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.63.3.460. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  86. Tversky A, Kahneman D. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science. 1974;185(4157):1124–1131. doi: 10.1126/science.185.4157.1124. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. The health consequences of smoking: A report of the surgeon general. 2004 Retrieved October 15 2012, from http://www.surgeongeneral.gov/library/reports/smokingconsequences/index.html.
  88. van der Velde FW, van der Pligt J, Hooykaas C. Perceiving AIDS-related risk: Accuracy as a function of differences in actual risk. Health Psychology. 1994;13(1):25–33. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.13.1.25. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  89. Vaughan E. Chronic exposure to an environmental hazard: Risk perceptions and self-protective behavior. Health Psychology. 1993;12(1):74–85. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.12.1.74. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  90. Waters EA, Klein WMP, Moser RP, Yu M, Waldron WR, McNeel TS, Freedman AN. Correlates of unrealistic risk beliefs in a nationally representative sample. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 2011;34(3):225–235. doi: 10.1007/s10865-010-9303-7. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  91. Weinstein ND. Unrealistic optimism about future life events. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1980;39(5):806–820. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.39.5.806. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  92. Weinstein ND. Unrealistic optimism about susceptibility to health problems: Conclusions from a community-wide sample. Journal of Behavioral Medicine. 1987;10(5):481–500. doi: 10.1007/bf00846146. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  93. Weinstein ND. Written direct examination. United States of America v. Philip Morris Inc., et al; 2001. Civil Complaint No. 99-CV-02496 (GK) in the United States District Court for the District of Columbia. Retrieved October 5, 2012, from http://www.justice.gov/civil/cases/tobacco2/01_Weinstein%20Written%20Direct%20Testimony.pdf. [Google Scholar]
  94. Weinstein ND, Atwood K, Puleo E, Fletcher R, Colditz G, Emmons KM. Colon Cancer: Risk Perceptions and Risk Communication. Journal of Health Communication. 2004;9(1):53–65. doi: 10.1080/10810730490271647. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  95. Weinstein ND, Klein WM. Resistance of personal risk perceptions to debiasing interventions. Health Psychology. 1995;14(2):132–140. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.14.2.132. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  96. Weinstein ND, Lachendro E. Egocentrism as a source of unrealistic optimism. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1982;8(2):195–200. doi: 10.1177/0146167282082002. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  97. Weinstein ND, Lyon JE. Mindset, optimistic bias about personal risk and health-protective behaviour. British Journal of Health Psychology. 1999;4(Part 4):289–300. doi: 10.1348/135910799168641. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  98. Weinstein ND, Nicolich M. Correct and incorrect interpretations of correlations between risk perceptions and risk behaviors. Health Psychology. 1993;12(3):235–245. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.12.3.235. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  99. Weinstein ND, Slovic P, Gibson G. Accuracy and optimism in smokers’ beliefs about quitting. Nicotine & Tobacco Research. 2004;6(Suppl3):375–380. doi: 10.1080/14622200412331320789. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  100. Whalen CK, Henker B, O’Neil R, Hollingshead J, Holman A, Moore B. Optimism in children’s judgments of health and environmental risks. Health Psychology. 1994;13(4):319–325. doi: 10.1037/0278-6133.13.4.319. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  101. Whitley BE, Hern AL. Perceptions of vulnerability to pregnancy and the use of effective contraception. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1991;17(1):104–110. doi: 10.1177/0146167291171016. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  102. Williams T, Clarke VA. Optimistic bias in beliefs about smoking. Australian Journal of Psychology. 1997;49(2):106–112. doi: 10.1080/00049539708259861. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
  103. Windschitl PD, Kruger J, Simms EN. The Influence of Egocentrism and Focalism on People’s Optimism in Competitions: When What Affects Us Equally Affects Me More. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2003;85(3):389–408. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.85.3.389. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES