Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2015 Aug 6.
Published in final edited form as: Mayo Clin Proc. 2015 Apr;90(4):555–557. doi: 10.1016/j.mayocp.2015.01.020

In reply- Maternal, Paternal, and Societal Efforts Are Needed to “Cure” Child Obesity

Edward Archer 1
PMCID: PMC4527549  NIHMSID: NIHMS709664  PMID: 25841259

Letter to the Editor

I welcome Drs. Ferraro and Adamo's discourse and readily admit that whenever educated readers wholly fail to comprehend the main thrust of a theory, the fault frequently lies with the author (i.e., me). Given this possibility, I now seek to remove whatever opacity led to their miscomprehension.

Science is the pursuit of lawful relations, not mere correlations; and the only test of a scientific theory ishow well it explains all the available evidence, not isolated findings. With these premises as a foundation, my theory links the socio-environmental changes over the past century to the lawful relations between the physiologic mechanisms driving epidemiologic trends and the subsequent evolutionary consequences.

In simple terms, the human body may be conceived as an ecosystem in which tissues compete for nutrient-energy. Within this framework, obesity is not a complex phenomenon but merely the result of the competitive dominance of fat cells over other tissues in the absorption and sequestering of energy. This competitive advantage is engendered via prenatal physiologic and postnatal behavioral ‘maternal effects’ (i.e., alterations in fat, muscle, and pancreatic beta cell development and learned physical inactivity). These environmentally-induced phenotypic effects have evolutionary consequences because they are transmitted progressively to the next generation through an altered maternal phenotype, independent of changes to the genome.

As stated in my title and throughout the paper, the twin epidemics of obesity and type II diabetes mellitus (T2DM) are the result of non-genetic evolution; at no point was there an “implied contribution of epigenetics...driving the intergenerational cycle of obesity.” Quite the contrary, I wrote extensively on the near-complete failure (i.e., lack of explanatory and predictive power) of the gene-centric (i.e., DNA and epigenetic) paradigm and stated explicitly that the problem of the “missing heritability...will not be found in the genome.” Furthermore, I posited that the rapid and ubiquitous phenotypic evolution evidenced over the past century was the result of “the progressive intergenerational transmission of acquired characteristics over multiple successive generations.”

My empirically supported physiologic theory of inheritance and evolution (based on accumulative maternal effects) posits that a fertilized oocyte with any human genome placed in the intrauterine milieu of a woman with an obese, inactive phenotype (i.e., with an evolutionary/familial history of high maternal resources and high levels of physical inactivity/sedentary behavior) will be born with compromised metabolic functioning. This inherited phenotype assures the adipogenic nutrient partitioning that leads to obesity and T2DM and is transmissible to the next generation via maternal effects (e.g., excessive gestational weight gain). In other words, phenotype begets phenotype because the intrauterine environment overwhelms any genetic variance across generations (i.e., the environmental determinism of obesity/T2DM; please see text of figure 4 of1). The empirical support for ‘maternal effects’ is unequivocal across species,2 including humans. For example, Brooks et al.3 examined ovum donations in humans and found that the “only discernible factor” influencing infant birth weight was the surrogate mother's body mass. Given these findings, and the fact that metabolically relevant mitochondrial DNA are (asexually) inherited via the maternal germ-line,4 I find little evidence to support the dogmatic speculation that paternal genes will have significant differential effects where it appears that maternal genes do not.

With respect to fetal development, genes are merely a necessary but not sufficient component of the development of obese/T2DM phenotypes, akin to atmospheric oxygen and water. They can be conceptualized as the ‘tools’ of the fertilized oocyte, and their use (i.e., expression) is strictly environment-dependent.5-9 As such, if we assume that a hammer is necessary to build a house, it should be obvious that the hammer does not cause a house to be built, nor determine its dimensions. Nevertheless, gene-centric dogma is based on the unsupported speculation that DNA (the hammer) is the cause of the obese/T2DM phenotypes (the house and its dimensions). Not surprisingly, if the only tool one has is a hammer, one will think everything is a nail; hence the myopic nature of genetic determinism, the irrelevance of genetic testing for obesity/T2DM, and failure of the gene/DNA-centric paradigm to explain recent epidemiologic trends.

Conversely, the most clinically relevant and scientifically important aspect of my paper is the empirical support presented for the ‘inheritance of acquired characteristics through use and disuse’ as a significant and universal mechanism of inheritance and evolution. This theory has been presented for millennia without strong evidence (e.g., Hippocrates,10 Aristotle11, Jean-Baptiste Lamarck12 and Charles Darwin13). Thus, I posited an empirically supported “in utero training effect” for fat cell development (i.e., the ‘use’ phase of “use and disuse”) and the post-natal effects of inactivity (i.e., the ‘disuse’ of skeletal muscles leading to insulin resistance, increased adiposity, etc.) leading to the intergenerational transmission of obesity and T2DM. The clinical and research implications of my theory are obvious given that it provides an unambiguous framework to intervene on the intergenerational transmission of obesity and T2DM: significantly increase the skeletal muscle energy flux of females across their lifespan.

My theory of inheritance and evolution: 1) directly challenges and potentially refutes the hyper-reductionist gene-centric Modern Synthesis,14 2) flouts the central dogma of molecular biology15 and Weismann Barrier,16 and 3) subsumes and extends the ground-breaking (and brilliant) work of both Barker17 and Pedersen.18 From a clinical standpoint, because gene expression is environmentally determined,5-9,19 genes are a merely a marker of what was and what is, not what will be.7 Therefore, gene-centric research is a costly, unnecessary tangent to clinically relevant scientific progress. As the great evolutionary geneticist Richard Lewontin wrote in 2006, it is time to dispel the “naive current prejudice that DNA has in it all the information necessary to specify the organism.”20 I could not agree more and look forward to scientific and clinical progress.

Acknowledgments

Grant Support: The work was supported by the National Institute of Diabetes and Digestive and Kidney Diseases of the National Institutes of Health under award number T32DK062710.

The content is solely the responsibility of the author and does not necessarily represent the official views of the National Institutes of Health.

References

  • 1.Archer E. The Childhood Obesity Epidemic as a Result of Nongenetic Evolution: The Maternal Resources Hypothesis. Mayo Clinic Proceedings. 2015;XX(XX):1–16. doi: 10.1016/j.mayocp.2014.08.006. [xxx1] [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Fox CW, Mousseau TA. Maternal effects as adaptations for transgenerational phenotypic plasticity (TPP). In: Mousseau TA, Fox CW, editors. Maternal Effects as Adaptations. Oxford University Press; New York: 1998. [Google Scholar]
  • 3.Brooks AA, Johnson MR, Steer PJ, Pawson ME, Abdalla HI. Birth weight: nature or nurture? Early Hum Dev. 1995 May 12;42(1):29–35. doi: 10.1016/0378-3782(95)01637-i. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Hoekstra RF. Evolutionary origin and consequences of uniparental mitochondrial inheritance. Hum Reprod. 2000 Jul;15(Suppl 2):102–111. doi: 10.1093/humrep/15.suppl_2.102. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Bissell MJ, Mian IS, Radisky D, Turley E. Tissue Specificity: Structural Cues Allow Diverse Phenotypes from a Constant Genotype. In: Muller GB, Newman AB, editors. Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionay Biology. A Bradford Book/MIT Press; Cambridge MA: 2003. pp. 103–118. [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Crabbe JC, Wahlsten D, Dudek BC. Genetics of Mouse Behavior: Interactions with Laboratory Environment. Science. 1999 Jun 4;284(5420):1670–1672. doi: 10.1126/science.284.5420.1670. 1999. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Rosenquist JN, Lehrer SF, O'Malley AJ, Zaslavsky AM, Smoller JW, Christakis NA. Cohort of birth modifies the association between FTO genotype and BMI. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2014 Dec 29;2014 doi: 10.1073/pnas.1411893111. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Kilpelainen TO, Qi L, Brage S, et al. Physical Activity Attenuates the Influence of FTO Variants on Obesity Risk: A Meta-Analysis of 218,166 Adults and 19,268 Children. PLoS Med. 2011 Nov;8(11):e1001116. doi: 10.1371/journal.pmed.1001116. PubMed. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9.Vimaleswaran KS, Li S, Zhao JH, et al. Physical activity attenuates the body mass index-increasing influence of genetic variation in the FTO gene. Am J Clin Nutr. 2009 Aug;90(2):425–428. doi: 10.3945/ajcn.2009.27652. PubMed. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Hippocrates Stevenson DC, editor. On Airs, Waters, and Places. Available online at http://classics.mit.edu//Hippocrates/airwatpl.html/2000.
  • 11.Aristotle . On the Generation of Animals. Harvard University Press; Cambridge: 1943. [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Lamarck JB. Zoological Philosophy: Exposition with Regard to the Natural History of Animals; [Philosophie Zoologique, Ou Exposition Des Considérations Relatives À L'histoire Naturelle Des Animaux.] Macmillan; London: 1809/1914. [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Darwin C. The variation of animals and plants under domestication. 1st ed. John Murray; London: 1868. [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Huxley J. Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. Allen & Unwin; London: 1942. [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Crick F. Central dogma of molecular biology. Nature. 1970 Aug 8;227(5258):561–563. doi: 10.1038/227561a0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.Weismann A. The Germ-Plasm. Charles Scribner's Sons/Electronic Scholarly Publishing; 1893. Available at: http://www.esp.org/books/weismann/germ-plasm/facsimile/ [Google Scholar]
  • 17.Hales CN, Barker DJ. Type 2 (non-insulin-dependent) diabetes mellitus: the thrifty phenotype hypothesis. Diabetologia. 1992 Jul;35(7):595–601. doi: 10.1007/BF00400248. PubMed. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Pedersen J. The pregnant diabetic and her newborn: problems and management. Munksgaard; Copenhagen: 1967/1977. [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Bhat R, Bissell MJ. Of plasticity and specificity: dialectics of the microenvironment and macroenvironment and the organ phenotype. Wiley interdisciplinary reviews. Developmental biology. 2014 Mar-Apr;3(2):147–163. doi: 10.1002/wdev.130. PubMed. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Lewontin RC. Commentary: statistical analysis or biological analysis as tools for understanding biological causes. Int J Epidemiol. 2006 Jun;35(3):536–537. doi: 10.1093/ije/dyl070. PubMed. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES