Skip to main content
Schizophrenia Bulletin logoLink to Schizophrenia Bulletin
. 2015 Apr 5;41(6):1214–1219. doi: 10.1093/schbul/sbv035

Schizophrenia, Subjectivity, and Mindreading

Matthew M Nour 1–3,1–3,1–3,*, Alvaro Barrera 4,5
PMCID: PMC4601706  PMID: 25848120

Abstract

A number of recent articles, many appearing in Schizophrenia Bulletin, signal a renewed interest in phenomenological approaches to our understanding of schizophrenia. These approaches conceptualize schizophrenia as a disorder of altered self-awareness and decreased prereflective social attunement, which may manifest as an impaired understanding of self, others, and the physical world. Phenomenological approaches to psychopathology are sometimes construed as being incompatible with the reductionistic methodology of contemporary neuroscience. In this article, we re-examine findings from the phenomenological investigation of schizophrenia in light of an influential neurocomputational account of mindreading, which postulates that understanding of others is subserved by coherent internal self-models. We argue that the phenomenological approach to schizophrenia is not incompatible with a neurocomputational account of mindreading, and that the 2 approaches should instead be viewed as existing in a relationship of mutual constraint and enlightenment. Our hypothesis, while speculative, is an attempt to marry the phenomenological and neuronal realities of schizophrenia. Furthermore, it has implications for psychotherapeutic interventions and future research.

Key words: phenomenology, Bayesian inference, predictive coding, self-disorder

Introduction

In recent years, there has been a renewed interest in phenomenological exploration of mental illness in general,1,2 and schizophrenia in particular.3–7 In parallel, researchers have sought to identify points of contact between phenomenological and neuroscientific approaches to psychopathology.1,3,8–11 This article continues in that spirit.

First, we present work in the phenomenological tradition that identifies anomalies in self-experience and understanding of others as the 2 core experiential deficits in schizophrenia.4–6,12–14 We then present an influential neurocomputational account of mindreading15,16 as a potential link between these 2 experiential abnormalities. Our proposal is motivated by the recognized requirement to unify phenomenological and biological accounts in psychiatry.1,5,17–19

Schizophrenia as a Self-disorder

A phenomenological approach to psychiatry seeks to understand the pervasive structural alterations in patients’ subjective experience in an attempt to unify otherwise disparate psychopathological features.1,3,20,21 Schizophrenia has been the focus of much of this work, with a particular focus on patients’ experience of “self” and “others.”

The sense of self can be experienced on multiple interdependent levels,22–25 from a prereflective minimal-self4,5 to a sense of self-emerging from ongoing intrapersonal and interpersonal dialogues13 that occupies the center of a personal narrative grounded in the social world.26 Abnormalities at each of these levels have been proposed in schizophrenia.

Sass and Parnas4 propose that the core psychopathological alteration in schizophrenia is an “instability of prereflective self-awareness,”5 which has been termed an “ipseity-disorder” or “self-disorder.” They argue that saturating all subjective experience is a prereflective awareness of self as the unified subject of perceptual experience.4 This notion is closely related to the feeling of inhabiting a living body embedded in the world.27 Sass and Parnas suggest that the weakening of minimal self in schizophrenia has 2 facets: hyper-reflexivity (an automatic tendency to direct objectifying attention toward normally tacit self-experiences) and lack of self-affection (a reduced automatic sense of being the unified and vital subject of awareness).4,5 These facets are postulated to be the core generative features of schizophrenia. For example, reduced sense of self-affection may manifest in passivity phenomena and a feeling of depersonalization, whilst hyper-reflexivity may result in bodily sensations taking on a pathologically salient quality. Interestingly, “disturbance of the perception of self” emerged as a core dimension of the schizophrenic prodrome in an early qualitative study by Møller and Husby.28

This formulation of schizophrenia as a condition of altered subjectivity and self-awareness is not new. Kraepelin wrote of a “disunity of consciousness,”29 whilst Bleuler wrote of a slackening of the associative links that tie together thoughts, perceptions, and affects.30,31 Jaspers and Schneider described patients experiencing depersonalization who feel “estranged from themselves,”23 and for whom “Descartes’ ‘cogito ergo sum’ … is no longer a valid experience.”23,32 Minkowski wrote of an atrophy of Bergsonian intuition and a “loss of vital contact with the world,”7,33 whilst Laing’s concept of “primary ontological insecurity” resembles ipseity-disorder.34

Alternatively, Lysaker and Lysaker argue that a sense of self “develops out of dialogues both within the individual and between the self and others,” and suggest that a “disruption in the dialogical self” is often found in patients with schizophrenia.13,35 The loss of dialogical ability is likely to disrupt personal narrative formation and lead to a subjective sense of personal incoherence.36 Personal narratives have been hypothesized to occupy the highest cognitive level in an individual’s predictive hierarchy, projecting a sense of predictability, security, and order onto a world that may otherwise seem chaotic and threatening.26

Dis-sociality, Autism, and Loss of “Common Sense”

As the minimal self is related to a feeling of immersion in a social world, ipseity disturbance is closely linked to a disorder of social functioning.7,27,37,38

Bleuler postulated that schizophrenia was characterized by an autistic “detachment from reality” and the social world.7,30,31 More recently, autism in patients with schizophrenia has been recast as a qualitative disturbance of “attunement” with the social environment,7 which Stanghellini and Ballerini term “dis-sociality.”14,39 Normally, social attunement stems from an automatic participation in a social network of shared meanings and depends on what Blankenburg called “common sense.”14,38,40 For Blankenburg, a loss of common sense was prominent in certain patients with schizophrenia, who are “unable to play along with the rules of the game of interpersonal behavior.”40

From another perspective, Laing postulated that patients with schizophrenia exist in a state of primary ontological insecurity, and are liable to view dialectical interpersonal interaction as threatening.34 This reasoning has recently been explored from the perspective of dialogical difficulties.12

Dis-sociality and lack of social attunement have a number of clinical manifestations. Stanghellini talks of “deviant” behaviors as the “epiphenomena of the disorders of primordial intersubjectivity and common sense.”14 In the case of a young woman, Blankenburg wrote that “the simplest of things … seem to slip away from her: how to behave in certain situations … how to speak with the people one meets, or what one is supposed to think about them.”40 More recently, Chris Frith has proposed that the thought disorder of schizophrenia is a manifestation of the patient’s inability to keep track of what their interlocutor currently knows, resulting in an inability to appropriately signpost their speech.41

In the case where intersubjectivity is seen as threatening, patients may prefer social isolation.34 Henriksen and Parnas have described the case of Jane, a young patient who found interpersonal contact unbearable, and recalled that even as a child her classmates made her feel uneasy as “they would come too close.”42 Jane also struggled with a feeling of not truly existing in the world, and these complaints preceded psychosis. Minkowski described a patient who had lost the “sensitivity” to communicate with others, and viewed “any outside force as an attack on his personality; if he succumbed to it he would be dragged down and engulfed.”33 Minkowski’s patient also complained of a feeling of “physiological decomposition,” “emptiness in the head,” and a feeling that his voice seemed “dead.”

Empirical Studies

Evidence for self-disorder as a specific feature of schizophrenia-spectrum disorders has emerged in the last 15 years,28,43,44 most recently in 2 heterogeneous samples of first-admission patients using the validated Examination of Anomalous Self-Experiences (EASE) tool.37,45 Self-disorder appears to show only a weak correlation with positive symptom score,37 suggesting that it is a trait or vulnerability46 phenotype of schizophrenia-spectrum disorders, akin to Bleuler’s “fundamental symptoms.”6,31

Social functioning and mindreading in schizophrenia have been studied using “Theory of Mind” (ToM) paradigms. A large meta-analysis found consistent ToM impairments in patients with schizophrenia, both in psychotic and remission phases.47 In a subsequent meta-analysis, the same authors found ToM impairments not only in first-episode psychosis patients, but also in their nonpsychotic relatives and in ultra-high-risk patients.48 The magnitude of impairment in the relatives and ultra-high-risk group was intermediate between the psychotic group and control group. ToM impairment may therefore represent a trait feature of schizophrenia, conferring a vulnerability phenotype.49 ToM impairments in schizophrenia are clinically important, correlating with quality-of-life measures50 and insight.51 They may also be accompanied by a sense of loss of immediate social “attunement” and feelings of “invasiveness.”52

Self-disorder Underlies Dis-sociality

Self-understanding and understanding of others are clearly interrelated, with a number of papers proposing that dis-sociality is secondary to self-disorder in schizophrenia.53–55 In this article, we present a neurocomputational hypothesis that supports this notion. Computational neuroscience aims to understand the ability of neural circuits to extract information about the environment from sensory data, where this task is seen as a type of statistical inference. From this perspective, understanding the goals and intentions of another person is among the most challenging (statistical) inferential task that neuronal circuits must perform, because any number of “hidden” motives could underlie the observable behavior of another person.15,16,56 At first glance, this account of mindreading could not be further from that of phenomenology, in which empathic understanding of others is emphatically noninferential and often “goes beyond”57 the immediate sensory data. It must be appreciated, however, that there is no simple isomorphism between the descriptions of the “same” phenomena at neuronal and experiential levels of analysis. The understanding of another person’s intentions can be noninferential at the level of phenomenological analysis, whilst simultaneously being subserved by mechanistic computational processes at the subpersonal neuronal level.9 Indeed, this must be the case.

Perception as Unconscious Inference

In predictive coding accounts, mindreading is construed as a special case of perceptual inference.15,16 In perceptual inference, the brain infers the current “state of the world” by combining incoming sensory data with prior knowledge gained through experience.56,58,59

Neuronal sensory processing circuits are arranged hierarchically.56,58,60 New sensory information propagates up neuronal hierarchies, starting at the bottom level of sensory epithelia. In parallel, high levels of the processing hierarchy make online predictions about the expected sensory input given the likely current “state of the world” (known as “prior probabilities” or ‘priors”). Prior sensory predictions cascade down the circuit and constrain the interpretation of incoming sensory signals, which would otherwise be open to an infinite variety of interpretations.56,61 At all levels of the hierarchy, the (top-down) prior predictions and (bottom-up) sensory data are compared, and any discrepancy (“prediction error”) is used to fine-tune the current estimate of the “state of the world.”56

This iterative process results in an automatic convergence toward an internally coherent hierarchical representation of the state of the world that is accurate and multi-layered,56 and represents the circuit’s best estimate of the current state of the world (the “posterior probability”).

Importantly, the top-down generation of sensory predictions relies on the brain’s internal “generative model” of the causal structure of the world, which enables sensory signals to be predicted from representations of the likely “state of the world.”56 These generative models are sculpted and optimized in light of experience. By suppressing the generative model’s prediction errors, the process described above achieves a Bayesian inversion of these hard-won generative models. This inversion essentially reverses the inputs and outputs of the generative model, resulting in a “recognition model” that can identify the “states of the world” given new sensory data (ie, a model capable of perceptual inference).58,59 Mathematical treatments of this proposal are outlined elsewhere.58–60

Mindreading and Perceptual Inference

An intriguing suggestion is that the task of inferring the hidden mental states of others from observations of their actions uses a special class of internal generative models that have been fine-tuned to optimize self-generated motor actions.15,16

These specialized generative models transform self-generated motoric commands, themselves hierarchically determined by personal goals and intentions, into predicted sensory consequence of the voluntary action. The models may be thought of as “self-models” composed of self-organizing hierarchies of personal priorities, goals, and intentions, which relate to a given social context.16 Kilner et al16 propose that an iterative Bayesian inversion of these generative models, occurring at the subpersonal level as described above, would result in recognition models capable of grasping another person’s goals and intentions from observations of their actions. This inversion would allow the neuronal circuit to converge on the internally coherent hierarchical configuration of “hidden causes” that best predicts the observed actions of the other person, and is as experientially “inferential” as seeing the world when you open your eyes.

What makes mindreading a special case of perceptual inference is that this final hierarchical configuration is actually taken from the observer’s own personal repertoire of generative models linking an understanding of environmental context to self-generated action, through a hierarchy of intentions, priorities, and goals specific to the observer.15,16 Thus, an accurate prediction of the intentions of another person will depend on an intuitive grasp of how intentions, goals, and desires are organized within a person, and how they relate to wider environmental and social contexts. This understanding is reminiscent of Blankenburg’s “common sense.”40

If schizophrenia-spectrum disorders are characterized by instability in the self-model4 and a reduced ability to form stable dialogical self-representations,13 then the foundation (generative models) upon which intuitive mindreading is based would be disrupted. Consequently, social interactions become less predictable, and hence more threatening. In this way, mindreading is secondary to the presence of a stable and internally coherent self-model that is attuned to the world of social and environmental contexts. Interestingly, patients diagnosed with certain personality disorders, in which the sense of self is affected, have also been found to have impairments in mindreading.53

Therapeutic and Research Implications

The speculative hypothesis presented in this article has implications for therapeutic approaches and future research. If coherent self-models of goal-directed action subserve mindreading abilities, therapies that improve self-awareness and help reconstruct self-narratives in schizophrenia may enhance patients’ experiences of living in the social world. Lysaker and colleagues have demonstrated that, in the course of individual psychotherapy, increased reflective self-awareness often emerges many months before the capacity to form mature relationships with other people.35,62–64 Therapeutic approaches that strengthen the patient’s sense of self and improve the coherence of personal life narratives may aid recovery and social functioning.12,65–70

Future studies should address how the different facets of altered self-awareness and dis-sociality are related within an individual. Furthermore, disorders of social functioning and self-awareness occur in psychiatric disorders other than schizophrenia, and further work will be required to fully characterize the features that are specific to schizophrenia.

Conclusions

We have presented theoretical and empirical work suggesting that alterations in self-awareness and awareness of others form the core experiential abnormalities in schizophrenia. We proposed a speculative hypothesis connecting these findings to an influential neurocomputational account of mindreading, which suggests that mindreading is subserved by internal self-models. The hypothesis presented here is an example of how phenomenological and neuroscientific approaches to psychopathology can coexist in a relationship of mutual enlightenment and constraint.21 The phenomenological finding that schizophrenia is characterized by disorders of self-awareness and social functioning raises the question of how these facets may be related at the neuronal level, whilst a neurocomputational formulation positing an asymmetry in the relationship between the core experiential deficits has implications for phenomenologically minded psychotherapeutic interventions.

The current effort to empirically demonstrate the reality of phenomenological abnormalities in schizophrenia and relate them to neuroscientific theories is an encouraging step toward a richer and more valid understanding of psychopathology.

Funding

M.M.N. and A.B. received no funding for this work.

Acknowledgment

We thank 2 anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments. The authors have declared that there are no conflicts of interest in relation to the subject of this study.

References

  • 1. Fuchs T. The challenge of neuroscience: psychiatry and phenomenology today. Psychopathology. 2002;35:319–326. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2. Stanghellini G, Broome MR. Psychopathology as the basic science of psychiatry. Br J Psychiatry. 2014;205:169–170. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 3. Stanghellini G, Rossi R. Pheno-phenotypes: a holistic approach to the psychopathology of schizophrenia. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2014;27:236–241. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 4. Sass LA, Parnas J. Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self. Schizophr Bull. 2003;29:427–444. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5. Sass L, Parnas J, Zahavi D. Phenomenological psychopathology and schizophrenia: contemporary approaches and misunderstandings. Philos. Psychiatry Psychol. 2011;18:1–23. [Google Scholar]
  • 6. Parnas J. A disappearing heritage: the clinical core of schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2011;37:1121–1130. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7. Parnas J, Bovet P. Autism in schizophrenia revisited. Compr Psychiatry. 1991;32:7–21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 8. Schilbach L, Timmermans B, Reddy V, et al. Toward a second-person neuroscience. Behav Brain Sci. 2013;36:393–414. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 9. Zahavi D. Simulation, projection and empathy. Conscious Cogn. 2008;17:514–522. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10. Shad MU, Brent BK, Keshavan MS. Neurobiology of self-awareness deficits in schizophrenia: a hypothetical model. Asian J Psychiatr. 2011;4:248–254. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11. Gallagher S, Zahavi D. The Phenomenological Mind. New York, NY: Routledge; 2008. [Google Scholar]
  • 12. Lysaker PH, Johannesen JK, Lysaker JT. Schizophrenia and the experience of intersubjectivity as threat. Phenomenol Cogn Sci. 2005;4:335–352. [Google Scholar]
  • 13. Lysaker PH, Lysaker JT. Narrative structure in psychosis: schizophrenia and disruptions in the dialogical self. Theory Psychol. 2002;12:207–220. [Google Scholar]
  • 14. Stanghellini G, Ballerini M. Dis-sociality: the phenomenological approach to social dysfunction in schizophrenia. World Psychiatry. 2002;1:102–106. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 15. Wolpert DM, Doya K, Kawato M. A unifying computational framework for motor control and social interaction. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2003;358:593–602. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16. Kilner JM, Friston KJ, Frith CD. Predictive coding: an account of the mirror neuron system. Cogn Process. 2007;8:159–166. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 17. Varela F. Neurophenomenology. A methodological remedy for the hard problem. J Conscious Stud. 1996;3:330–349. [Google Scholar]
  • 18. Lutz A, Thompson E. Neurophenomenology. Integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. J Conscious Stud. 2003;10:31–52. [Google Scholar]
  • 19. Gallagher S. Phenomenology and experimental design. toward a phenomenologically enlightened experimental science. J Conscious Stud. 2003;10:85–99. [Google Scholar]
  • 20. Broome M, Harland R, Owen G, Stringaris A. The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological Psychiatry. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press; 2012. [Google Scholar]
  • 21. Parnas J, Sass LA, Zahavi D. Recent developments in philosophy of psychopathology. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2008;21:578–584. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 22. Moutoussis M, Fearon P, El-Deredy W, Dolan RJ, Friston KJ. Bayesian inferences about the self (and others): a review. Conscious Cogn. 2014;25:67–76. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 23. Jaspers K. General Psychopathology. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press; 1997. [Google Scholar]
  • 24. James W. Psychology: The Briefer Course. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications; 2001. [Google Scholar]
  • 25. Cermolacce M, Naudin J, Parnas J. The “minimal self” in psychopathology: re-examining the self-disorders in the schizophrenia spectrum. Conscious Cogn. 2007;16:703–714. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 26. Hirsh JB, Mar RA, Peterson JB. Personal narratives as the highest level of cognitive integration. Behav Brain Sci. 2013;36:216–217. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 27. Stanghellini G. Embodiment and schizophrenia. World Psychiatry. 2009;8:56–59. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 28. Møller P, Husby R. The initial prodrome in schizophrenia: searching for naturalistic core dimensions of experience and behavior. Schizophr Bull. 2000;26:217–232. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 29. Raballo A. Self-disorders and the experiential core of schizophrenia spectrum vulnerability. Psychiatr Danub. 2012;24:303–310. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 30. Moskowitz A, Heim G. Eugen Bleuler’s dementia praecox or the group of schizophrenias (1911): a centenary appreciation and reconsideration. Schizophr Bull. 2011;37:471–479. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 31. Bleuler E. Dementia Praecox or The Group of Schizophrenias. New York, NY: International University Press; 1950. [Google Scholar]
  • 32. Nordgaard J, Arnfred SM, Handest P, Parnas J. The diagnostic status of first-rank symptoms. Schizophr Bull. 2008;34:137–154. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 33. Minkowski E. “The essential disorder underlying schizophrenia and schizophrenic thought” (1927) Translated by Cutting J. In: Broome M, Harland R, Owen G, Stringaris A, eds. The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological Psychiatry. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press; 2012:143–155. [Google Scholar]
  • 34. Laing R. The Divided Self. An Existential Study in Sanity and Madness. London: Penguin Books; 1959. [Google Scholar]
  • 35. Lysaker PH, Hermans HJ. The dialogical self in psychotherapy for persons with schizophrenia: a case study. J Clin Psychol. 2007;63:129–139. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 36. Dimaggio G, Salvatore G, Azzara C, Catania D. Rewriting self-narratives: the therapeutic process. J Constr Psychol 2003;16:155–181. [Google Scholar]
  • 37. Nordgaard J, Parnas J. Self-disorders and the schizophrenia spectrum: a study of 100 first hospital admissions. Schizophr Bull. 2014;40:1300–1307. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 38. Stanghellini G. Psychopathology of common sense. Philos. Psychiatry Psychol. 2001;8:201–218. [Google Scholar]
  • 39. Stanghellini G, Ballerini M. What is it like to be a person with schizophrenia in the social world? A first-person perspective study on Schizophrenic dissociality–part 1: state of the art. Psychopathology. 2011;44:172–182. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 40. Blankenburg W. “First steps toward a psychopathology of ‘common sense’” (1968) Translated by Mishara AL. In: Broome M, Harland R, Owen G, Stringaris A, eds. The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological Psychiatry. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press; 2012:158–165. [Google Scholar]
  • 41. Frith CD. The Cognitive Neuropsychology of Schizophrenia. New York, NY: Psychology Press; 1992. [Google Scholar]
  • 42. Henriksen MG, Parnas J. Clinical manifestations of self-disorders and the Gestalt of schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2012;38:657–660. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 43. Parnas J, Jansson L, Sass L, Handest P. Self-experience in the prodromal phases of schizophrenia: a pilot study of first admissions. Neurol Psychiatry Brain Res. 1998;6:107–116. [Google Scholar]
  • 44. Parnas J, Handest P, Jansson L, Saebye D. Anomalous subjective experience among first-admitted schizophrenia spectrum patients: empirical investigation. Psychopathology. 2005;38:259–267. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 45. Haug E, Lien L, Raballo A, et al. Selective aggregation of self-disorders in first-treatment DSM-IV schizophrenia spectrum disorders. J Nerv Ment Dis. 2012;200:632–636. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 46. Raballo A, Parnas J. The silent side of the spectrum: schizotypy and the schizotaxic self. Schizophr Bull. 2011;37:1017–1026. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 47. Bora E, Yucel M, Pantelis C. Theory of mind impairment in schizophrenia: meta-analysis. Schizophr Res. 2009;109:1–9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 48. Bora E, Pantelis C. Theory of mind impairments in first-episode psychosis, individuals at ultra-high risk for psychosis and in first-degree relatives of schizophrenia: systematic review and meta-analysis. Schizophr Res. 2013;144:31–36. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 49. Stanghellini G. Vulnerability to schizophrenia and lack of common sense. Schizophr Bull. 2000;26:775–788. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 50. Maat A, Fett AK, Derks E. Social cognition and quality of life in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2012;137:212–218. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 51. Konstantakopoulos G, Ploumpidis D, Oulis P, et al. The relationship between insight and theory of mind in schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2014;152:217–222. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 52. Stanghellini G, Ballerini M. What is it like to be a person with Schizophrenia in the social world? A first-person perspective study on Schizophrenic Dissociality–part 2: methodological issues and empirical findings. Psychopathology. 2011;44:183–192. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 53. Dimaggio G, Lysaker PH, Carcione A, Nicolò G, Semerari A. Know yourself and you shall know the other to a certain extent: multiple paths of influence of self-reflection on mindreading. Conscious Cogn. 2008;17:778–789. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 54. Lysaker PH, Dimaggio G, Buck KD, Carcione A, Nicolò G. Metacognition within narratives of schizophrenia: associations with multiple domains of neurocognition. Schizophr Res. 2007;93:278–287. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 55. Nelson B, Sass LA, Thompson A, et al. Does disturbance of self underlie social cognition deficits in schizophrenia and other psychotic disorders? Early Interv Psychiatry. 2009;3:83–93. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 56. Clark A. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behav Brain Sci. 2013;36:181–204. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 57. Northoff G. Neuropsychoanalysis in Practice. Brain, Self and Objects. New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2011. [Google Scholar]
  • 58. Friston K. Learning and inference in the brain. Neural Netw. 2003;16:1325–1352. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 59. Friston K. The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nat Rev Neurosci. 2010;11:127–138. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 60. Friston K. A theory of cortical responses. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 2005;360:815–836. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 61. Howe CQ, Beau Lotto R, Purves D. Comparison of Bayesian and empirical ranking approaches to visual perception. J Theor Biol. 2006;241:866–875. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 62. Lysaker PH, Buck KD, Ringer J. The recovery of metacognitive capacity in schizophrenia across 32 months of individual psychotherapy: a case study. Psychother Res. 2007;17:713–720. [Google Scholar]
  • 63. Lysaker PH, Davis LW, Eckert GJ, Strasburger AM, Hunter NL, Buck KD. Changes in narrative structure and content in schizophrenia in long term individual psychotherapy: a single case study. Clin Psychol Psychother. 2005;12:406–416. [Google Scholar]
  • 64. Lysaker PH, Carcione A, Dimaggio G, et al. Metacognition amidst narratives of self and illness in schizophrenia: associations with neurocognition, symptoms, insight and quality of life. Acta Psychiatr Scand. 2005;112:64–71. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 65. Roe D, Davidson L. Self and narrative in schizophrenia: time to author a new story. Med Humanit. 2005;31:89–94. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 66. Dimaggio G, Salvatore G, Azzara C, Catania D. Rewriting self-narratives: the therapeutic process. J Constr Psychol. 2003;16:155–181. [Google Scholar]
  • 67. Lysaker PH, Buck KD, Roe D. Psychotherapy and recovery in schizophrenia: a proposal of key elements for an integrative psychotherapy attuned to narrative in schizophrenia. Psychol Serv. 2007;4:28–37. [Google Scholar]
  • 68. Stanghellini G, Lysaker PH. The psychotherapy of schizophrenia through the lens of phenomenology: intersubjectivity and the search for the recovery of first- and second-person awareness. Am J Psychother. 2007;61:163–179. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 69. Lysaker PH, Dimaggio G. Metacognitive capacities for reflection in schizophrenia: implications for developing treatments. Schizophr Bull. 2014;40:487–491. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 70. Lysaker PH, Roe D. The processes of recovery from schizophrenia: the emergent role of integrative psychotherapy, recent developments, and new directions. J Psychother Integr. 2012;22:287–297. [Google Scholar]

Articles from Schizophrenia Bulletin are provided here courtesy of Oxford University Press

RESOURCES