Abstract
Spatial structure greatly affects the evolution of cooperation. While in two-player games the condition for cooperation to evolve depends on a single structure coefficient, in multiplayer games the condition might depend on several structure coefficients, making it difficult to compare different population structures. We propose a solution to this issue by introducing two simple ways of ordering population structures: the containment order and the volume order. If population structure is greater than population structure
in the containment or the volume order, then
can be considered a stronger promoter of cooperation. We provide conditions for establishing the containment order, give general results on the volume order, and illustrate our theory by comparing different models of spatial games and associated update rules. Our results hold for a large class of population structures and can be easily applied to specific cases once the structure coefficients have been calculated or estimated.
Keywords: evolutionary game theory, spatial structure, order theory, computational geometry, stochastic orders
1. Introduction
The evolution of cooperation is a fascinating topic that has been studied from different perspectives and theoretical approaches [1–5]. An issue that has led to considerable interest is the extent to which spatial structure allows cooperation to thrive [6–28]. Spatial structure can both enhance cooperation by inducing clustering or assortment (whereby cooperators tend to interact more often with other cooperators [11,29,30]) and oppose cooperation by inducing increased local competition (whereby cooperators tend to compete more often with other cooperators [31]). For two-player games or multiplayer games with similar strategies, the balance between these two opposing effects is captured by the ‘scaled relatedness coefficient’ of inclusive fitness theory [15,19,27,28] or the ‘structure coefficient’ of evolutionary game theory [6,16,22]. These coefficients are functions of demographic parameters, and take into account the degree of assortment, the effects of density dependence and the strength of local competition resulting from spatial interactions [10,15,22]. Two different models of spatial structure and associated evolutionary dynamics can be unambiguously compared by ranking their relatedness or structure coefficients: the greater the coefficient, the less stringent the conditions for cooperation to evolve. Hence, different models of population structure can be ordered by their potential to promote the evolution of cooperation in a straightforward way.
Despite the theoretical importance of models leading to a single relatedness or structure coefficient, many examples of social evolution ranging from microbial cooperation [32–34] to collective action in humans [35–37] involve games between more than two players with distinct strategies [38,39]. In these cases, the effects of spatial structure cannot be captured by a single coefficient, as higher degrees of association (e.g. ‘triplet relatedness’ [17,40]) are required to fully describe the condition under which cooperation is favoured [27,41,42]. The need to account for several structure coefficients has so far precluded a simple way of comparing population structures independently of the particular game used to model cooperation.
Here, we propose a framework to order population structures by their potential to promote cooperation that is also valid in the case of games between multiple players with distinct strategies. Our framework allows the comparison of two population structures without referring to any concrete game. We will distinguish two cases, depending on the inclusion relation between the sets of games for which cooperation is promoted under each population structure. (i) The set of games for which the second population structure promotes cooperation is fully contained in the set of games for which the first population structure promotes cooperation (figure 1a). In this case, we say that the first population structure is greater than the second in the containment order, and hence a stronger promoter of cooperation. (ii) The set of games for which one population structure promotes cooperation is not fully contained in the set of games for which the other population structure promotes cooperation (figure 1b). In this case, we say that the population structure promoting cooperation for a larger volume of games is greater in the volume order, and hence a stronger promoter of cooperation.
Figure 1.
Containment and volume orders of cooperation. The set of d-player cooperation games is defined by a set of linear inequalities (dashed lines) defining a polytope in a 2d-dimensional space. A given population structure (e.g. or
) is characterized by a selection condition defining a further linear inequality (solid lines). Here, we show a pictorial representation of the projection of such multidimensional objects to the plane, where polytopes are polygons. (a) The set of games for which cooperation is favoured under
is contained in the set of the games for which cooperation is favoured under
Hence, we say that
is greater than
in the containment order (and write
). (b)
and
cannot be ordered in the containment order as there are both games for which
favours cooperation but not
(purple polygon), and games for which
favours cooperation but not
(orange polygon). In both panels,
favours cooperation for more games than
does. Hence, we say that
is greater than
in the volume order (and write
).
So far, the structure coefficients for general multiplayer games have been calculated only for a few population structures, as such calculations often represent a technical challenge [43]. However, once the structure coefficients are known, the containment and volume orders we propose here enable assessment of the consequences of population structure on the evolution of cooperation independently of the game at stake. This way, our approach can help to organize myriads of results on the promotion of cooperation in spatially structured populations.
2. Methods and results
2.1. Cooperation games and polytopes
We consider symmetric games between d players with two strategies, A and B. A focal player's pay-off depends on the player's own strategy and on the strategies of its d – 1 co-players. If j co-players play A, a focal A-player obtains whereas a focal B-player obtains
These interactions are represented by the following pay-off table:
opposing A-players | 0 | 1 | ![]() |
j | ![]() |
d – 1 |
pay-off to A | ![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
pay-off to B | ![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
It follows that a game is determined by 2d real numbers and can thus be considered as a point in a 2d-dimensional space.
In which sense can we say that one population structure favours cooperation more than another? To answer this question precisely, we first need to specify what we mean by ‘cooperation’, as this could refer to different social behaviours, in particular if we move beyond two-player games [44]. We are interested in a particular subset of games that we call ‘cooperation games’. In these games, players decide whether to cooperate (play A) or defect (play B), and pay-offs are such that: (i) players prefer other group members to cooperate irrespective of their own strategy and (ii) mutual cooperation is favoured over mutual defection. In terms of our pay-off parameters, these conditions imply
![]() |
2.1 |
as well as
![]() |
2.2 |
The above conditions are often used to characterize the benefits of cooperation in multiplayer social dilemmas [44], such as the provision of collective goods [19]. However, our conditions do not specify individual costs associated with a decision to cooperate, and hence our class of cooperation games includes not only social dilemmas, but also mutualistic games in which individual and group interests are aligned. If we further restrict pay-offs to values between zero and one,
![]() |
2.3 |
then the set of all cooperation games with d players is given by a (convex) polytope [45] in a 2d-dimensional space, which we denote by A polytope is a geometric object with flat sides, the generalization of a polygon (which is a two-dimensional polytope) to higher dimensional spaces. See the electronic supplementary material for further details.
We need to specify precisely what we mean by ‘favouring’ cooperation. For our purposes, we say that cooperation is favoured if a single cooperator in a population of defectors has a higher probability of eventually reaching fixation than a single defector in a population of cooperators [46]. This also means that cooperation is more abundant than defection in a mutation-selection process in the limit of low mutation [47]. For weak selection on homogeneous populations of constant size, strategy A is favoured over B if [42]
![]() |
2.4 |
where are the d structure coefficients. These are independent of pay-offs
and
but dependent on the type of spatial structure (for instance, where the co-players of a given focal individual are located) and update rule used to model the evolutionary dynamics. In table 1, we provide examples of population structures and their corresponding structure coefficients (see the electronic supplementary material for a derivation).
Table 1.
Structure coefficients for some population structures. Parameters d and N refer to the number of players and population size, respectively. In the group splitting model, m is the number of groups and n is the group size. The structure coefficients shown here are not normalized; for our purposes it is useful to normalize them so that
The structure coefficients are uniquely determined up to a constant factor. Setting one of them to one thus gives a single non-trivial structure coefficient for two-player games [22]. We use the sequence to collect the coefficients and note that, if
for all j and
for at least one j, we can impose
without affecting the selection condition (2.4). For our purposes, this normalization turns out to be more useful than setting one coefficient to one. In particular, such normalization allows us to understand the (normalized) structure coefficients as describing a probability distribution, and to make a straightforward connection with the concept of assortment as developed for the case of linear public goods games [30,51]. To do so, let us rewrite the selection condition (2.4) as
![]() |
2.5 |
Here, plays the role of the ‘effective’ probability of interacting with j individuals of the own type (and d – 1 – j of the other type). As given by (2.5), the selection condition states that A is favoured over B if the expected pay-off of an A-player is greater than that of a B-player when the ‘interaction environments’ [30] are distributed according to
A given population structure will favour cooperation only for a subset of cooperation games. More precisely, for a population structure with structure coefficients
the set of cooperation games for which
favours A over B is given by adding the selection condition (2.5) to the inequalities defining the polytope of cooperation games,
i.e. (2.1)–(2.3). The selection condition (2.5) defines a hyperplane and thus divides the space of games into two: those for which cooperation is favoured and those for which defection is favoured. This shows that our problem is equivalent to a geometric problem in 2d dimensions. In the following, we denote by
the polytope containing the cooperation games for which cooperation is favoured under population structure
(see the electronic supplementary material).
2.2. Containment order
If the set of games for which cooperation is favoured under population structure
is contained in the set
for which cooperation is favoured under population structure
then we say that
is greater than
in the containment order [52], and we write
The ordering
implies that cooperation cannot be favoured under
without also being favoured under
Establishing the containment order is equivalent to a ‘polytope containment problem’ [53], consisting of determining whether or not a polytope is contained in another. Polytope containment problems can be solved numerically by linear programming [54]. Here, we describe an alternative and simpler approach borrowed from the literature on stochastic orders [55]. First, assume that the structure coefficients are non-negative and normalized, so that they define a probability distribution over
In this case, the left-hand side of the selection condition (2.4) can be interpreted as the expected value
where
and J is the random variable associated with the probability distribution
Consider now two population structures
and
with structure coefficients
and
and associated random variables
and
respectively. A sufficient condition leading to the containment order
is hence that
![]() |
2.6 |
for all cooperation games.
In order to evaluate this condition, we make use of the usual stochastic order [55]. A random variable is said to be greater than
in the stochastic order if and only if
for all increasing functions
This is denoted by
Conveniently, and by (2.1), the sequence
is always increasing in j, allowing us to apply this idea directly (see Proposition 1 in the electronic supplementary material for details). One advantage of expressing the containment order in terms of the stochastic order is that we can transform our original polytope containment problem into the problem of finding conditions under which random variables can be stochastically ordered. Some of these conditions follow from a simple inspection of the sequences of structure coefficients. For instance, a sufficient condition leading to the stochastic order
(and hence to the containment order
) is that
has exactly one sign change from – to + [55]. As we show in §2.4, this simple condition allows us to order different existing models of population structure in a straightforward way.
For the linear public goods game (i.e. a game with pay-offs and
for some
where
is the marginal benefit from the public good and
is the individual cost of contributing), the selection condition (2.5) can be put in a form reminiscent of Hamilton's rule with
playing the role of a measure of assortment (or relatedness), where
(resp.
) is the mean number of cooperators among the d – 1 interaction partners of a cooperator (resp. defector) [51]. For more general cooperation games, the selection condition depends not only on the mean but also on higher moments of the probability distribution given by
The stochastic order we have used for establishing the containment order is a way of measuring the association between strategies in this general case. Hence, it can be said that population structures greater in the containment order are those characterized by greater ‘effective assortment’ and thus more conducive to the evolution of cooperation. In the extreme case where
(and
for
), we have the case of a completely segregated population where As only interact with As and Bs only interact with Bs. In this case, the selection condition reduces to (2.2), and cooperation is always favoured by definition.
It can happen that neither is entirely contained in
nor
is entirely contained in
In these cases,
and
are incomparable in the containment order (i.e. neither
nor
hold) and we write
We show in Proposition 2 in the electronic supplementary material that a sufficient condition leading to such incomparability is that the sequences
and
cross twice (figure 2). In this case, there exist both a subset of cooperation games favoured under
but not under
and a subset of cooperation games favoured under
but not under
Figure 2.
Comparability in the containment order. The structure coefficients and
cross exactly once, implying that
and
are comparable in the containment order. Moreover,
crosses
from below; hence
is greater than
in the containment order
Likewise,
Contrastingly, the structure coefficients
and
cross exactly twice, implying that
and
are incomparable in the containment order
i.e. neither
nor
For such cases, the volume order provides an alternative way to order these structures. Here,
is a group splitting model with m = 10 groups of maximum size n = 6 and rare probability of splitting (
),
is a cycle of size N = 60 and
is a group splitting model with m = 6, n = 10 and
For the commonly discussed case of two-player games in structured populations [22], the sequence consists of two elements:
(usually set to one) and
(usually denoted by
and referred to as ‘the’ structure coefficient). As two sequences of two elements can only cross each other at most once, it follows that any two population structures can be ordered in the containment order if d = 2, i.e. the containment order is a total order for two-player games. Moreover, the containment order is given by the comparison of the structure coefficients
with larger
leading to greater containment order. Contrastingly, for
two sequences
can cross twice. In this case, their respective population structures cannot be compared in the containment order: for multiplayer cooperation games and for the space of all possible population structures, the containment order is only a partial order (see Proposition 3 in the electronic supplementary material).
2.3. Volume order
In order to address the cases for which two population structures are incomparable in the containment order, we introduce the ‘volume order’. We say that is greater than
in the volume order, and write
if
![]() |
2.7 |
where is the volume of polytope
In other words,
means that for a given d, cooperation is favoured under
for a greater number of cooperation games than under
If two structures are ordered in the containment order so that
this implies that they are ordered in the volume order so that
but the converse is not true.
We find that the volume of all d-player cooperation games is given by (Proposition 10 in the electronic supplementary material; figure 3):
![]() |
2.8 |
which decreases rapidly with the number of players d. For d = 2, this volume is equal to 5/24. In this case, the four pay-offs and
can be ordered in 4! = 24 possible ways, five of which satisfy inequalities (2.1) and (2.2), namely (i)
(Prisoner's Dilemma), (ii)
(snowdrift game), (iii)
(stag hunt), (iv)
(harmony game) and (v)
(Prisoner's Delight [56]). For large d, condition (2.2) becomes less important and the volume of cooperation games is approximately
which is the volume of games satisfying conditions (2.1) and (2.3).
Figure 3.
Fraction of cooperation games for which cooperation is favoured in population structures with symmetric structure coefficients (main figure) and volume of cooperation games (inset figure) as functions of the number of players d. As d increases, the probability that a population structure with symmetric structure coefficients promotes cooperation for a randomly chosen cooperation game quickly approaches 1/2. At the same time, the probability that a randomly chosen game is a cooperation game quickly goes to zero, an effect that seems to be underappreciated in the literature emphasizing the importance of cooperation in evolution.
For some population structures, such as large well-mixed populations updated with a Moran process, the structure coefficients are symmetric, i.e. for all j. For these cases, the fraction of cooperation games for which cooperation is favoured becomes
![]() |
2.9 |
(Proposition 11 in the electronic supplementary material; figure 3). This fraction is equal to 3/5 for d = 2, and reduces to 1/2 in the limit of large d.
2.4. Examples
Let us now illustrate our approach with particular models of spatial structure and associated update rules. Consider first the baseline scenario of a well-mixed population of size updated with a death–birth (Moran) process [38,46]. In the death–birth process, in each time step, one individual is chosen at random to die and another one is chosen proportional to its pay-off to reproduce by making a copy of itself. We find that for any
well-mixed populations updated with a death–birth process are ordered in the containment order with respect to the total population size N, such that larger populations are more conducive to multiplayer cooperation (Proposition 4 in the electronic supplementary material). Our result generalizes previous results for two-player games and multiplayer games with similar strategies according to which smaller population sizes are less conducive to cooperation because of the stronger local competition among cooperators ([22], eqn 22; [28], eqn B.1). In the limit of large N and by equation (2.9), well-mixed populations updated with a death–birth process favour cooperation for exactly one-half of all possible cooperation games.
Consider now the effect of introducing spatial structure while keeping the same update rule. One of the simplest spatial models is the cycle [8]. It has been shown that cycles updated with a death–birth process are better promoters of cooperation than well-mixed populations in the case of two-player games [9,57], and for several examples of multiplayer social dilemmas (such as linear public goods games, snowdrift games and stag hunt games) in the limit of large population size [49]. Our theory allows us to extend these results to all multiplayer cooperation games and arbitrary population sizes. Indeed, we find that cycles are greater than well-mixed populations in the containment order for any given population size N (Proposition 6 in the electronic supplementary material). This implies that cycles are better promoters of cooperation than well-mixed populations for any cooperation game, any number of players d and any population size N.
A second model of spatial structure for which structure coefficients are readily available is the group splitting model of [26]. In this model, a finite population of size N is subdivided into m groups, which can grow in size and split with probability q when reaching the maximum size n. In the limit of rare group splitting (), all groups are typically of the maximum size n and the structure coefficients can be calculated analytically for general d-player games [50]. Consider well-mixed and group splitting populations updated according to a death–birth process. If the number of groups is greater than two, the group splitting model is greater than any well-mixed population in the containment order (Proposition 7 in the electronic supplementary material). Moreover, in the limit of
the structure coefficients of the group splitting model become
and
for
In this limit, the group splitting model is greater in the containment order than any other population structure. Hence, it is the population structure that favours cooperation most among all theoretically possible population structures.
The cycle and the group splitting model are better promoters of cooperation than the well-mixed population. But which one promotes cooperation under more cooperation games, the cycle or the group splitting model? Consider cycles of size N and group splitting models with rare group splitting consisting of m groups of maximum size n, so that the total maximum population size is equal to N = mn. Assuming that the population size N is large, the containment order depends on the number of groups m of the group splitting model in the following way (Proposition 8 in the electronic supplementary material). (i) If the number of groups is small
the group splitting model is smaller than the cycle in the containment order. (ii) If the number of groups is intermediate
the group splitting model and the cycle are incomparable in the containment order. (iii) If the number of groups is large
the group splitting model is greater than the cycle in the containment order. As a particular example, consider a cycle of size N = 1000 and a group splitting model with m = 10 groups of maximum size n = 100 (figure 4). In this case, the cycle is greater than the group splitting model in the containment order if
while the two population structures are incomparable in the containment order if
Concerning the volume order, exact computations and numerical simulations suggest that the cycle is greater than the group splitting model for
and smaller than the group splitting model otherwise.
Figure 4.
Normalized volumes of cooperation for two different population structures: a cycle of size N = 1000 () and a group splitting model with m = 10 groups of maximum size n = 100 (
). Volumes are calculated exactly for small values of d (squares) and approximately using a Monte Carlo method (circles); see appendix A. The cycle is greater than the group splitting model in the volume order for
and smaller in this sense for
We can also show that the cycle is greater than the group splitting model in the containment order (
) for
but the two population structures are incomparable in the containment order (
) for
Up until now we have compared different models of spatial structure (the well-mixed population, the cycle, the group splitting model) with a single update rule (the Moran death–birth process). However, the structure coefficients depend both on spatial structure and on the update rule. For two-player games, different update rules can have important consequences on the evolutionary dynamics, as they lead to different ‘circles of compensation’, or how far the effects of density dependence extend from a given focal individual [10]. What are the effects of different update rules on multiplayer cooperation games? As an example, consider well-mixed populations with two different update rules: the Moran process, where a random individual dies and its neighbours compete for the empty site, and the aspiration dynamics, where an individual is likely to switch its strategy if the current pay-off does not meet an aspiration level [48,58]. The two update rules can be ordered in the containment order only if (Proposition 9 in the electronic supplementary material). In this case, aspiration dynamics is greater in the containment order than the Moran process, meaning that if cooperation is favoured under the Moran process it will also be favoured under aspiration dynamics, but not necessarily vice versa. If
the two structures are incomparable in the containment order. However, for any finite population size N, aspiration dynamics is greater in the volume order: overall, cooperation is favoured for more games under aspiration dynamics than under the Moran process.
3. Discussion
Our approach to compare models of population structure sheds new light on how to study and analyse the evolution of cooperation in spatially structured populations. We have shown how several existing results, obtained under the assumptions of pairwise interactions, similar strategies or particular classes of multiplayer social dilemmas, generalize to the case of multiplayer cooperation games with distinct strategies that we have considered here. Perhaps more importantly, one can find two population structures such that there is a class of cooperation games for which cooperation is favoured under the first but not under the second, and a class of cooperation games for which the opposite holds true (figure 1b). Thus, arbitrarily choosing one or a few games from the set of all possible cooperation games to compare the effects of population structure on the evolution of cooperation can be misleading, even when focusing on the comparison of fixation probabilities under weak selection. This is different from the case of either two-player games or multiplayer games with similar strategies, where a ranking of population structures is always possible in terms of a single real value, and where it is sufficient to focus on a single game without loss of generality [15,22].
We made use of the theory of stochastic orders [55] to provide conditions under which two population structures are comparable or incomparable in the containment order. Within social evolution theory, stochastic orders have recently also been used to tackle the question of whether variability in group size distribution would lead to less stringent conditions for the evolution of cooperation in multiplayer social dilemmas [59]. Our use of stochastic orders in this paper relies on the assumption (fulfilled by all the population structures we used as examples) that the structure coefficients can always be normalized to define a probability distribution. It would be interesting to investigate under which general conditions such an assumption is valid. Another open question is whether two population structures incomparable in the containment order could favour cooperation in disjoint subsets of cooperation games. If the structure coefficients define a probability distribution, this will never be the case, as it will always be possible to find a cooperation game for which the selection condition holds for any two population structures. Consider for instance a game for which and
for all j, with
(a mutualistic game where the group optimal action A is also individually optimal). In this case, and provided that the structure coefficients are non-negative, the selection condition (2.4) is always satisfied.
We considered a very broad definition of cooperation and a particular measure of evolutionary success, and investigated subset containment relations and volumes of the resulting polytopes. In this respect, our approach is related to a classical study by Mattesi & Jayakar [60], who first defined an ‘altruism domain’ from a set of linear inequalities involving ‘local fitness functions’ and then investigated the problem of finding and measuring the relative volume of the ‘subset of the altruism domain in which A is more fit than B on average, that is, altruism can evolve’. We note, however, that our definition of cooperation is different from the definition of altruism adopted by Matessi & Jayakar: the ‘multi-level interpretation’ of altruism, in the sense of Kerr et al. [44]. In particular, we only focused on the group benefits, not the individual costs, associated with expressing the cooperative action A. Such costs could be introduced by adding further sets of inequalities to the ones we used here, for instance by requiring that for some or all j [19,44]. As we did not specify any costs, our class of cooperation games contains a relatively large set of mutualistic games for which group beneficial behaviours are also individually beneficial. Our measure of evolutionary success is also different, as we focused on the comparison of fixation probabilities in the limit of weak selection, whereas Matessi & Jayakar focused on the one-step change in frequency. Finally, Matessi & Jayakar limited themselves to ‘linear fitness functions’ (equivalent to linear games in our set-up) while we considered more general multiplayer games. The differences between our study and the one by Matessi & Jayakar pinpoint possible future work along these lines. For instance, alternative definitions of cooperation that take into consideration the cost of cooperation [44,61] and exclude mutualistic games could be explored, possibly together with alternative measures of evolutionary success [62]. As long as it is possible to write all conditions as a set of linear inequalities (and hence as polytopes) involving the pay-offs of the game, our definitions can be used and adapted to these cases. It would be interesting to see the extent to which comparisons of different population structures based on the containment and volume orders defined here are robust to changes in the way cooperation and evolutionary success are defined and implemented.
Supplementary Material
Acknowledgements
We would like to thank Laurent Lehmann, Georg Nöldeke and three anonymous referees for their valuable comments on previous versions of this paper.
Appendix A. Computing volumes
There are many exact methods for computing volumes of polytopes, including triangulation methods [63] and signed decomposition methods [64]. Computing the exact volume of a polytope is however known to be #P-hard [65], and a simple task only for low dimensions. In figure 4, the volumes for were calculated exactly using the function volume of the class Polyhedron of the mathematics software Sage (v. 6.5). For
we used a Monte Carlo method for approximating the volumes. For each value of d, we randomly generated
increasing sequences
and
and retained only those which fulfilled (2.2). We then checked how many of these sequences verified the selection condition (2.4). The fraction of cooperation games was then approximated by the ratio between these two numbers. Our source code in Python is publicly available on GitHub (https://github.com/jorgeapenas/ordering).
Authors' contributions
J.P. designed the study and wrote the code; J.P. and B.W. performed research; all authors wrote the manuscript.
Competing interests
We declare we have no competing interests.
Funding
J.P. acknowledges funding support by the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant no. PBLAP3-145860).
References
- 1.Axelrod R. 1984. The evolution of cooperation. New York, NY: Basic Books. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Frank SA. 1998. Foundations of social evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 3.Hamilton WD. 1964. The genetical evolution of social behavior I and II. J. Theoret. Biol. 7, 1–16. ( 10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Hamilton WD. 1964. The genetical evolution of social behavior II. J. Theoret. Biol. 7, 17–52. ( 10.1016/0022-5193(64)90039-6) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Nowak MA. 2006. Evolutionary dynamics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 6.Allen B, Nowak MA, Dieckmann U. 2013. Adaptive dynamics with interaction structure. Am. Nat. 181, E139–E163. ( 10.1086/670192) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Débarre F, Hauert C, Doebeli M. 2014. Social evolution in structured populations. Nat. Commun. 5, 3409 ( 10.1038/ncomms4409) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Ellison G. 1993. Learning, local interaction and coordination. Econometrica 61, 1047–1071. ( 10.2307/2951493) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Grafen A. 2007. An inclusive fitness analysis of altruism on a cyclical network. J. Evol. Biol. 20, 2278–2283. ( 10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01413.x) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Grafen A, Archetti M. 2008. Natural selection of altruism in inelastic viscous homogeneous populations. J. Theor. Biol. 252, 694–710. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2008.01.021) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Hamilton W. 1971. Selection of selfish and altruistic behavior in some extreme models. In Man and beast: comparative social behavior (eds Eisenberg JF, Dillon WS), pp. 57–91. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Press. [Google Scholar]
- 12.Ladret V, Lessard S. 2007. Fixation probability for a beneficial allele and a mutant strategy in a linear game under weak selection in a finite island model. Theor. Popul. Biol. 72, 409–425. ( 10.1016/j.tpb.2007.04.001) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Lehmann L, Keller L, Sumpter DJT. 2007. The evolution of helping and harming on graphs: the return of the inclusive fitness effect. J. Evol. Biol. 20, 2284–2295. ( 10.1111/j.1420-9101.2007.01414.x) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Lehmann L, Keller L, West S, Roze D. 2007. Group selection and kin selection: two concepts but one process. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 104, 6736–6739. ( 10.1073/pnas.0700662104) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Lehmann L, Rousset F. 2010. How life history and demography promote or inhibit the evolution of helping behaviours. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 365, 2599–2617. ( 10.1098/rstb.2010.0138) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Nowak MA, Tarnita CE, Antal T. 2010. Evolutionary dynamics in structured populations. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 365, 19–30. ( 10.1098/rstb.2009.0215) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Ohtsuki H. 2010. Evolutionary games in Wright's island model: kin selection meets evolutionary game theory. Evolution 64, 3344–3353. ( 10.1111/j.1558-5646.2010.01117.x) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18.Ohtsuki H, Hauert C, Lieberman E, Nowak MA. 2006. A simple rule for the evolution of cooperation on graphs. Nature 441, 502–505. ( 10.1038/nature04605) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Peña J, Nöldeke G, Lehmann L. 2015. Evolutionary dynamics of collective action in spatially structured populations. J. Theor. Biol. 382, 122–136. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2015.06.039) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Rousset F. 2004. Genetic structure and selection in subdivided populations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 21.Szabó G, Fáth G. 2007. Evolutionary games on graphs. Phys. Rep. 446, 97–216. ( 10.1016/j.physrep.2007.04.004) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Tarnita CE, Ohtsuki H, Antal T, Fu F, Nowak MA. 2009. Strategy selection in structured populations. J. Theor. Biol. 259, 570–581. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2009.03.035) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Taylor PD, Day T, Wild G. 2007. From inclusive fitness to fixation probability in homogeneous structured populations. J. Theor. Biol. 249, 101–110. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2007.07.006) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Taylor PD. 1992. Altruism in viscous populations—an inclusive fitness approach. Evol. Ecol. 6, 352–356. ( 10.1007/BF02270971) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Taylor PD, Day T, Wild G. 2007. Evolution of cooperation in a finite homogeneous graph. Nature 447, 469–472. ( 10.1038/nature05784) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Traulsen A, Nowak MA. 2006. Evolution of cooperation by multi-level selection. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 103, 10 952–10 955. ( 10.1073/pnas.0602530103) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Van Cleve J. 2015. Social evolution and genetic interactions in the short and long term. Theor. Popul. Biol. 103, 2–26. ( 10.1016/j.tpb.2015.05.002) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Van Cleve J, Lehmann L. 2013. Stochastic stability and the evolution of coordination in spatially structured populations. Theor. Popul. Biol. 89, 75–87. ( 10.1016/j.tpb.2013.08.006) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Eshel I, Cavalli-Sforza LL. 1982. Assortment of encounters and evolution of cooperativeness. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 79, 1331–1335. ( 10.1073/pnas.79.4.1331) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Fletcher JA, Doebeli M. 2009. A simple and general explanation for the evolution of altruism. Proc. R. Soc. B 276, 13–19. ( 10.1098/rspb.2008.0829) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Platt TG, Bever JD. 2009. Kin competition and the evolution of cooperation. Trends Ecol. Evol. 24, 370–377. ( 10.1016/j.tree.2009.02.009) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Gore J, Youk H, van Oudenaarden A. 2009. Snowdrift game dynamics and facultative cheating in yeast. Nature 459, 253–256. ( 10.1038/nature07921) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Li X-Y, Pietschke C, Fraune S, Altrock PM, Bosch TCG, Traulsen A. 2015. Which games are growing bacterial populations playing? J. R. Soc. Interface 12, 20150121 ( 10.1098/rsif.2015.0121) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Xavier JB, Foster KR. 2007. Cooperation and conflict in microbial biofilms. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 104, 876–881. ( 10.1073/pnas.0607651104) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Hilbe C, Wu B, Traulsen A, Nowak MA. 2014. Cooperation and control in multiplayer social dilemmas. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 111, 16 425–16 430. ( 10.1073/pnas.1407887111) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Milinski M, Semmann D, Krambeck H-J, Marotzke M. 2006. Stabilizing the Earth's climate is not a losing game: supporting evidence from public goods experiments. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 103, 3994–3998. ( 10.1073/pnas.0504902103) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Ostrom E. 1990. Governing the commons: the evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- 38.Gokhale CS, Traulsen A. 2010. Evolutionary games in the multiverse. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 107, 5500–5504. ( 10.1073/pnas.0912214107) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Peña J, Lehmann L, Nöldeke G. 2014. Gains from switching and evolutionary stability in multi-player matrix games. J. Theor. Biol. 346, 23–33. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2013.12.016) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Ohtsuki H. 2014. Evolutionary dynamics of n-player games played by relatives. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B 369, 20130359 ( 10.1098/rstb.2013.0359) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Roze D, Rousset F. 2008. Multilocus models in the infinite island model of population structure. Theor. Popul. Biol. 73, 529–542. ( 10.1016/j.tpb.2008.03.002) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Wu B, Traulsen A, Gokhale CS. 2013. Dynamic properties of evolutionary multi-player games in finite populations. Games 4, 182–199. ( 10.3390/g4020182) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 43.McAvoy A, Hauert C. 2015. Structure coefficients and strategy selection in multiplayer games. J. Math. Biol. 72, 203–238. ( 10.1007/s00285-015-0882-3) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P, Feldman MW. 2004. What is altruism? Trends Ecol. Evol. 19, 135–140. ( 10.1016/j.tree.2003.10.004) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Ziegler GM. 1995. Lectures on polytopes, vol. 152 Berlin, Germany: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- 46.Nowak MA, Sasaki A, Taylor C, Fudenberg D. 2004. Emergence of cooperation and evolutionary stability in finite populations. Nature 428, 646–650. ( 10.1038/nature02414) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Fudenberg D, Imhof LA. 2006. Imitation processes with small mutations. J. Econ. Theory 131, 251–262. ( 10.1016/j.jet.2005.04.006) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Du J, Wu B, Altrock PM, Wang L. 2014. Aspiration dynamics of multi-player games in finite populations. J. R. Soc. Interface 11, 20140077 ( 10.1098/rsif.2014.0077) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.van Veelen M, Nowak MA. 2012. Multi-player games on the cycle. J. Theor. Biol. 292, 116–128. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2011.08.031) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Kurokawa SS, Ihara Y. 2013. Evolution of social behavior in finite populations: a payoff transformation in general n-player games and its implications. Theor. Popul. Biol. 84, 1–8. ( 10.1016/j.tpb.2012.11.004) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Bijma P, Aanen DK. 2010. Assortment, Hamilton's rule and multilevel selection. Proc. R. Soc. B 277, 673–675. ( 10.1098/rspb.2009.1093) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 52.Fishburn PC, Trotter WT. 1999. Geometric containment orders: a survey. Order 15, 167–182. ( 10.1023/A:1006110326269) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 53.Kaibel V, Pfetsch ME. 2003. Some algorithmic problems in polytope theory. In Algebra, geometry and software systems (eds Joswig M, Takayama N), pp. 23–47. Berlin, Germany: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- 54.Freund RM, Orlin JB. 1985. On the complexity of four polyhedral set containment problems. Math. Program. 33, 139–145. ( 10.1007/BF01582241) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 55.Shaked M, Shanthikumar JG. 2007. Stochastic orders. Berlin, Germany: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- 56.Binmore K. 2004. Reciprocity and the social contract. Politics Philos. Econ. 3, 5–35. ( 10.1177/1470594X04039981) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 57.Ohtsuki H, Nowak MA. 2006. Evolutionary games on cycles. Proc. R. Soc. B 273, 2249–2256. ( 10.1098/rspb.2006.3576) [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 58.Szabó G, Töke C. 1998. Evolutionary Prisoner's Dilemma game on a square lattice. Phys. Rev. E 58, 69–73. ( 10.1103/PhysRevE.58.69) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 59.Peña J, Nöldeke G. 2016. Variability in group size and the evolution of collective action. J. Theor. Biol. 389, 72–82. ( 10.1016/j.jtbi.2015.10.023) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 60.Matessi C, Jayakar SD. 1976. Conditions for the evolution of altruism under Darwinian selection. Theor. Popul. Biol. 9, 360–387. ( 10.1016/0040-5809(76)90053-8) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 61.Dawes RM. 1980. Social dilemmas. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 31, 169–193. ( 10.1146/annurev.ps.31.020180.001125) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 62.Tarnita CE, Taylor PD. 2014. Measures of relative fitness of social behaviors in finite structured population models. Amer. Nat. 184, 477–488. ( 10.1086/677924) [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 63.Cohen J, Hickey T. 1979. Two algorithms for determining volumes of convex polyhedra. J. ACM 26, 401–414. ( 10.1145/322139.322141) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 64.Lawrence J. 1991. Polytope volume computation. Math. Comput. 57, 259–271. ( 10.1090/S0025-5718-1991-1079024-2) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- 65.Dyer M, Frieze A. 1988. On the complexity of computing the volume of a polyhedron. SIAM J. Comput. 17, 967–974. ( 10.1137/0217060) [DOI] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.