Introduction
Kidney cancer is a common and lethal cancer; in 2014 it will account for an estimated 63,920 new diagnoses and 13,860 deaths in the United States alone1. The clinical care of affected patients, as well as participation in clinical research involving kidney cancer, poses many potential ethical challenges for the clinician and investigator. The issues discussed in this review, while commonly encountered in this setting, are not exclusive to kidney cancer and will be relevant to many facets of medical care and clinical research.
Informed Consent, Disclosure of Surgeon Experience, and Outcomes
Surgical therapy is the mainstay of treatment for renal cell carcinoma2 and, therefore, issues of informed consent prior to surgical intervention are paramount. The concept of informed consent developed in the early 20th century as advances in surgical and anesthetic techniques made elective surgery possible3. Today, informed consent is well-accepted as a central aspect of the surgeon-patient relationship. Traditional informed consent has required the surgeon to disclose certain procedure-specific factors: potential surgical complications and risks, benefits of the proposed surgery, available alternatives and likely outcomes of the treatment. The American Urological Association goes even further in its Code of Ethics, requiring the surgeon to provide the patient with “all of the information necessary to consent and to make his own choice of treatment, regardless of my own advice or judgment. The information provided must include known risks and benefits, costs, reasonable expectations and possible complications, available alternative treatments and their cost, as well as the identification of other medical personnel who will be participating directly in the care delivery”4.
The need to disclose physician-specific factors (experience, previous outcomes, training), however, is more controversial. Studies have correlated surgeon volume5 and objective ratings of surgeon skill6 with patient outcomes; these findings suggest that disclosure of these surgeon-specific factors may be relevant to patients' informed decision making. A survey of patients supported this, as a majority of respondents found information on surgeon volume and outcomes essential7. Legal opinion on this matter, however, is conflicted. Many states have adopted a “reasonable person” standard for determining the content of an informed consent discussion3,8 and two State Supreme Courts have addressed the specific issue of surgeon experience9. In 1996, the Wisconsin State Supreme Court held that physician experience and outcomes as compared to other physicians’ is a meaningful part of the “alternative treatment options” that need to be discussed during the process of informed consent9. In 2001, however, the Pennsylvania State Supreme Court defined informed consent as including procedure-specific factors only and categorized information about the physician as outside of the scope of informed consent9.
The ethical principle of autonomy is central to this debate. If knowledge of surgeon experience is necessary for patient decision making, its disclosure enhances patient autonomy and therefore is appropriate. While the Wisconsin Supreme Court categorized this information as an important aspect of “surgical alternatives”, Clarke and Oakley10 argue that surgeon ability is an important risk factor, and therefore an essential component of any informed consent discussion. While accepting the importance of patient autonomy, Burger reasons that disclosure of surgeon-specific performance information is only imperative if it is accurate enough to affect patient decision-making9. She contends that physician-specific outcomes data is often tied to arbitrary end-points, can be manipulated by patient selection, and is unfairly biased against younger surgeons9.
The issue of disclosure of surgeon experience is very relevant to the surgical management of renal cancer. Laparoscopic and robotic-assisted partial nephrectomy have become popular and widely utilized interventions for small renal masses11. Several studies have demonstrated a learning curve with the use of these surgical modalities and surgeon experience has been shown to independently predict patient outcomes12. Whether currently available individual surgeon-level data is of high enough quality to impact patient decision-making is unclear. Nevertheless, most authors agree that providing this information when asked by the patient is imperative to maintain an open and honest physician-patient relationship8. With patients’ increasing use of internet data sources, the proliferation of physician rating systems, and a widespread interest in healthcare quality improvement, the question of individual physician-level outcomes data is likely to be an area of discussion for the foreseeable future.
Referral to Other Surgeons or Medical Centers
The optimal management of kidney cancer adds another facet to this discussion - that of referral to other surgeons. Surgeons are sometimes reluctant to refer a patient to another surgeon for multiple reasons: to keep patients close to home and their local health system, to avoid the loss of income from performing surgery, and to avoid the loss of referrals from primary care providers13. In this era of rapidly advancing technology, there are multiple surgical options for renal cancer utilizing new instruments and surgical techniques14. It is reasonable to expect that not all urologic surgeons will be able to provide every available option to a patient seeking minimally-invasive surgery, nephron-sparing approaches, cytoreductive nephrectomy, or care in other complex situations (i.e. solitary kidney, local recurrence after therapy, familial renal cancer syndrome, etc.). The referral of a patient who would be best served by a procedure that one cannot offer, or not offer well, is relatively easy to accept. More difficult, however, is the question: is a surgeon ethically obliged to refer a patient to another surgeon or institution who reports better results?
The American Urological Association advises each surgeon to “respect my colleagues, seek their counsel when in doubt about my own abilities, and assist my colleagues whenever requested. I will accept that “competence” includes having adequate and proper knowledge to make professionally appropriate and acceptable decisions regarding management of the patient's problems, as well as the ability and skill to perform what is necessary to be done and to ensure that the aftercare is the best available to the patient”4. While this guidance emphasizes the need for honest evaluation of a surgeon's own competence and the humility to seek assistance when needed, it does not address the question of referral to another provider or medical center based on outcomes data or for procedures that he or she does not offer.
An analogous question has been discussed in the thoracic surgery literature13. In support of the obligation to refer, Kouchoukos argues that not referring the patient to a more experienced surgeon is unethical as it places self-interest above the patient's best interest. He concedes that there are no clearly established guidelines for this situation, but the ethical principle of avoiding harm (nonmaleficence) and general professionalism should compel a referral to a more-experienced and better performing surgeon13. Cohn, on the other hand, argues that such a referral is not an ethical imperative. While having the best surgeon in the world operate on every patient may seem ideal, he argues, it is not possible nor is it truly desirable13. Cohn contends that it would not be physically possible for a small group of experienced surgeons to perform all of one type of surgery and it would undesirable to limit the dissemination of knowledge of a new technique13. Ultimately, both authors agree that there are certain situations (i.e. a procedure with which a surgeon has no experience or one which requires a vast expenditure of resources or coordinated team) in which referral to a more experienced surgeon is ethically necessary. As universally applicable guidance on this issue is not likely to be produced, each surgeon must, in the context of honest discussion with patients, make such decisions on a case-by-case basis.
While individual physician-level data collection has not been widely adopted, the UK National Health Service (NHS) has published nephrectomy data that includes mortality, complications, and length of stay. This data, collected by the British Association of Urological Surgeons (BAUS), has recently been the source of significant controversy due to errors15,16. These errors have led to a recommendation from the BAUS to revise or close the NHS website hosting this data17. This experience underscores concerns that the problems inherent in widespread public reporting of individual surgeon-level data can compromise the quality of any analysis drawing on such data. Furthermore, the effects of these data on patient selection strategies and access to surgical treatment for high-risk patients are not yet fully understood.
When considering the question of referral to a higher-volume or better performing institution, many of the same issues exist: questions of patient-selection, fear of lost revenue and the quality of publicly-reported data can diminish enthusiasm for referral to high volume centers. Nevertheless, Becker et al. examined the hospital volume-outcome relationship for nephrectomy and found that patients treated at lower-volume hospitals were at higher risk of adverse outcomes18. Smaldone et al demonstrated that the use of partial nephrectomy for small renal masses increased as hospital volume increased19. Monn and colleagues demonstrated that high hospital volume is associated with fewer blood transfusions and complications after robotic assisted partial nephrectomy20. The movement towards regionalization for cancer care has occurred in multiple fields of oncology, including prostate and bladder cancer21.
One resource for the transfer of cancer patients in the United States is the National Cancer Institute's (NCI) cancer center program. Forty-one institutions have been designated “Comprehensive Cancer Centers” by the NCI and are centers of excellence in the research and clinical care of oncology patients. Patients treated at NCI-designated cancer centers have been shown to have lower surgical mortality rates22, improved post-operative and long-term survival23, and a higher number of harvested lymph nodes24 for various malignancies. While the outcomes of kidney cancer patients treated at NCI-designated centers have not been specifically studied, these data make a compelling case for regionalization.
Clinical Research
Clinical research aims to advance our understanding of the pathophysiology and treatment of disease and ultimately to improve the care and health of the patient25. Unfortunately, such research often carries a risk of harm to participating subjects. Possible harms include side effects and complications of treatment, loss of confidentiality, and exposure to additional procedures or tests. Balancing these risks with benefits is essential for the ethical conduct of clinical research. Several policy statements exist to guide researchers; these include the Nuremberg Code26, the Declaration of Helsinki27, and the Belmont Report28. All of these documents emphasize the importance of protecting the research subject and ensuring respect for subjects’ rights. While these documents have laid the historical and ethical framework for modern research ethics, they are not without limitations. Some have argued that the Nuremberg Code, drafted in response to the atrocities perpetrated by Nazi doctors in World War II, is inadequate in its protection of research subjects and provides loopholes for the conduct of unethical research29. The Declaration of Helsinki, a document that has undergone several revisions since its initial adoption in 1964, has been criticized as being too restrictive and vague in its recommendations regarding placebo-controlled and phase 1 clinical trials 30. The Belmont Report, which emphasizes the ethical principles of autonomy, beneficence and justice, does not provide guidance on how to navigate situations in which these principles come into conflict with each other28.
In 2000, Emanuel and colleagues proposed a universal list of requirements for ethical research 25 (Table 1). The seven elements described below are, the authors propose, like a constitution – a good framework for the ethical conduct of research, but in need of occasional interpretation and revision 25. As a framework, it is a flexible set of rules that is broadly applicable to human research across many domains: all phases of clinical trials, oncology and non-oncology studies, and research done in both developed and economically developing communities.
Table 1.
Table 2. Seven Requirements for Determining Whether a Research Trial Is Ethical* | |||
---|---|---|---|
Requirement | Explanation | Justifying Ethical Values | Expertise for Evaluation |
Social or scientific value | Evaluation of a treatment, Intervention, or theory that will improve health and well-being or Increase knowledge | Scarce resources and nonexploitation | Scientific knowledge; citizen's understanding of social priorities |
Scientific validity | Use of accepted scientific principles and methods, including statistical techniques, to produce reliable and valid data | Scarce resources and nonexploitation | Scientific and statistical knowledge; knowledge of condition and population to assess feasibility |
Fair subject selection | Selection of subjects so that stigmatized and vulnerable individuals are not targeted for risky research and the rich and socially powerful not favored for potentially beneficial research | Justice | Scientific knowledge; ethical and legal knowledge |
Favorable risk-benefit ratio | Minimization of risks; enhancement of potential benefits; risks to the subject are proportionate to the benefits to the subject and society | Nonmaleficence, beneficence, and nonexploitation | Scientific knowledge; citizen's understanding of social values |
Independent review | Review of the design of the research trial, Its proposed subject population, and risk-benefit ralo by individuals unaffiliated with the research | Public accountability; minimizing Influence of potential conflicts of interest | Intellectual, financial, and otherwise independent researchers; scientific and ethical knowledge |
Informed consent | Provision of information to subjects about purpose of the research, Its procedures, potential risks, benefits, and alternatives, so that the individual understands this information and can make a voluntary decision whether to enroll and continue to participate | Respect for subject autonomy | Scientific knowledge; ethical and legal knowledge |
Respect for potential and enrolled subjects | Respect for subjects by
|
Respect for subject autonomy and welfare | Scientific knowledge; ethical and legal knowledge; knowledge of particular subject population |
Ethical requirements are listed in chronological order from conception of research to its formulation and implementation
Mandatory Research Biopsies
Having presented some guidelines for the ethical conduct of clinical research in general, we turn now to a discussion of some specific issues in kidney cancer research. One issue is that of mandatory research biopsies. Traditionally, renal mass biopsies were used sparingly and in limited clinical scenarios. The expansion of efficacious targeted agents in metastatic renal cell cancer has increased the desire for pre- and post-treatment renal mass research biopsies31. Additionally, improvements in image-guided biopsy technique and increased incidental diagnosis of small renal masses have led to renewed interest in the utility of biopsy for small, localized renal masses31. One study has demonstrated that patients can be assigned to surgery or surveillance with 97% agreement between biopsy and final pathology 32. Unlike renal biopsies performed in the course of the clinical care of a patient, however, research biopsies will often not provide any direct benefit to the patient. This has led commentators to question the ethics of making such biopsies mandatory in clinical trials 33-35.
Peppercorn et al 33 argue that research biopsies that are a condition of enrollment in a clinical trial may be coercive to prospective subjects. This argument alludes to the concept of therapeutic misconception – that patients who are considering clinical trials often believe the trial will benefit them in some way that standard therapy will not. Operating under that assumption, patients may feel coerced to agree to a biopsy in order to obtain the benefits of trial participation they implicitly expect. How can we remedy this issue? The solution is not to make research biopsies optional, argue Peppercorn et al, but to ensure that potential subjects understand the nature of the study, how it differs from standard care, and the risks and lack of direct benefit of the biopsy 33. Furthermore, research biopsies should not be part of a research protocol without “strong scientific rationale, meaningful informed consent and a low to minimal risk of expected complications” 36.
Overman et al evaluated all clinical trials with research biopsies at MD Anderson Cancer Center from 2005-2010 to determine how the scientific rationale for biopsy was presented to subjects, if the biopsy was mandatory, and if the risks and benefits were clearly communicated in the informed consent document 34. Of 57 clinical trials examined, 67% included at least one mandatory biopsy. Of these, 71% of studies had biopsy as an eligibility criterion. The complication rate of research biopsies was 5.2% (overall) and 0.8% (major). The study found that discussion of biopsy-related risks was inadequate in the informed consent documentation: the discussion of biopsy risks spanned fewer words on average than that of venipuncture, and risks were rarely presented in a site-specific manner 34. Furthermore, the statistical rationale for number of research biopsies needed was rarely present or adequate 34.
To better understand the varying roles biopsies can play, Peppercorn et al categorize them into three categories: clinical biopsy, research biopsy for correlative science, and research biopsy for integral biomarker research33. Clinical biopsies are used in the care of the patient and have a direct benefit to the patient. These biopsies may be useful for research if excess tissue is used or stored for future study. Research biopsies for correlative science are used to correlate a novel or known biomarker with a patient's clinical outcome or response to treatment, and will not impact the care of the subject in any way. Finally, research biopsies for integral biomarker studies are used to establish the presence of a biomarker that is necessary for patient enrollment in a study that is assessing or validating that biomarker. Clinical biopsies should be considered ethical based on their risk and benefit to the patient, as the primary utility of this biopsy is in the direct clinical care of the patient. Research biopsies for integral biomarker research, while not providing a definite benefit to the patient, will direct the patient's care by allowing their inclusion in a trial or in a particular arm of a trial. The most ethically challenging research biopsy is that for correlative research. Opponents argue that tissue for this purpose can be often obtained from clinically indicated biopsies or tissue banks, and therefore could be made optional rather than mandatory for many research protocols33.
While there is certainly utility to research biopsies, they should not be mandatory without appropriate scientific justification and detailed statistical planning. As with all aspects research, thorough informed consent is essential. The purpose of the biopsy and the risks specific to it, stratified by the site of biopsy, must be discussed with prospective subjects.
Placebo-controlled trials
Randomized, controlled clinical trials are one of the most important tools of clinical research. The issue of what to use as the control, however, can be controversial. Placebo-controlled studies often raise the greatest concern, and have been used frequently in the targeted therapy era. (Table 2)
Table 2.
Therapy | Target | Treatment Line | Comparison Arm | Primary Endpoint |
---|---|---|---|---|
Axitinib 37 | VEGFR | Second-Line | Sorafenib | PFS |
Bevacizumab + IFN- α (AVOREN) 38 | VEGF | First-line | Placebo + IFN- α | OS |
Bevacizumab + IFN- α (CALGB) 39 | VEGF | First-line | IFN- α | OS |
Everolimus | mTOR | VEGFR Failure | Placebo | PFS |
Pazopanib | VEGFR | First-line or Cytokine Failure | Placebo | PFS |
Sorafenib 42 | VEGFR | Cytokine Failure | Placebo | OS |
Sunitinib43 | VEGFR | First-line | IFN- α | PFS |
Temsirolimus 44 | mTOR | First-line | IFN- α | OS |
IFN, interferon; mTOR, mammalian target of rapamycin; OS, overall survival; PFS, progression-free survival; VEGF, vascular endothelial growth factor; VEGFR, vascular endothelial growth factor receptor.
Modified with permission from 45
Emanuel and Miller have compared the merits of placebo-control and active-control trials46. Placebo-control advocates argue that methodological purity requires the use of placebo as a control group. Often, they argue, new treatments may not demonstrate benefits over an existing therapy due to variances in response, small effect sizes, or spontaneous improvement in some patients46,47. Furthermore, proponents claim, even if a treatment isn't better than an existing therapy, it may have fewer side effects or less cost46. This argument centers on the idea that placebo controlled trials are the most scientifically sound and therefore should be allowed. Conversely, supporters of an active-control argue that withholding the standard therapy from the control group is not morally acceptable. Additionally, they argue that the superiority of a new intervention over placebo is not as clinically relevant as its ability to show improvement over an active control46. Allowing the use of placebo, they argue, would be to prioritize scientific rigor over the well-being of patients.
Emanuel and Miller argue that there are ethical problems with each of these views and that a middle ground is called for46. They argue that withholding efficacious medication from a placebo group, even if it does not result in lasting harm, can lead to increased suffering and is therefore unethical46. The active-control argument also has flaws, they argue, as it creates a false dichotomy between rigorous science and ethical research46. (Table 1)
Emanuel and Miller remind us that in order for research to be ethical, it must be methodologically sound, as exposing subjects to any risk without the possibility of scientifically useful results (as in a methodologically unsound study design) is unethical25. Further, they contend, the harm of placebo can occasionally be non-existent or so small as to be negligible. Indeed, in many studies the placebo effect can lead to significant clinical improvement. Finally, Emanuel and Miller argue that the use of placebo allows for increased statistical power, and in some cases may allow for meaningful results from a study with fewer participants – therefore exposing overall fewer patients to potential harm from an investigational therapy46. In general, they argue, that most scientists will agree that when live-saving or life-prolonging interventions are available and assignment to placebo would significantly increase the chance for harm, it is unethical to randomize patients to placebo46. Similarly, in research involving non-serious ailments, where the chance for harm or discomfort is negligible, placebo-control is ethical46.
In controversial cases, between these two extremes, placebo controlled trials should only be used when methodologically necessary: there is a high placebo response rate; the condition has a waxing-waning course or spontaneous improvements; existing therapies have serious side-effects or only partial efficacy; the disease is so rare that a trial with active-control would require so many participants as to make the trial not feasible46. If these criteria are met, they argue, the use of placebo control should be evaluated for potential risks of death, disability, harm or discomfort46,48. Only in the absence of a substantial difference in these risks can a placebo control ethically be used46.
While previous revisions of the Declaration of Helsinki prohibited the use of placebo when any active treatment existed for a condition48, the most recent revision (2013) allows for the use of placebo controls when “for compelling and scientifically sound methodological reasons the use of any intervention less effective than the best proven one, the use of placebo, or no intervention is necessary to determine the efficacy or safety of an intervention and the patients who receive any intervention less effective than the best proven one, placebo, or no intervention will not be subject to additional risks of serious or irreversible harm as a result of not receiving the best proven intervention.27”
Daugherty et al emphasize that placebo-control trials can be ethical in oncology as placebo should always be accompanied by the best available palliative and supportive care48,49. In many scenarios in advanced cancer, available third- and subsequent-line therapies do not offer a high probability of benefit and do carry the risk of significant toxicities50. In this setting, there may be equipoise, or uncertainty, when comparing placebo with best supportive care to these active control options48. Daugherty et al also propose several methodological strategies to minimize the potential harms of placebo. First, the use of clinically relevant surrogate endpoints instead of survival can shorten the duration of a study and therefore decrease exposure and risk of harm to subjects48. Additionally, creative study methodology such as cross-over and randomized withdrawal designs can minimize ethical dilemmas and potential harms related to the use of placebo controls48.
A recent example of the use of placebo in clinical kidney cancer trials is the 2010 Phase III trial of pazopanib in metastatic and locally advanced kidney cancer41. This study compared pazopanib with placebo in patients enrolled from 2006-2007. Around this time, evidence was emerging for the benefits of targeted therapy with tyrosine-kinase inhibitors (TKIs). Furthermore, prior to the widespread adoption of TKI therapy, cytokine-based therapy was the standard of care for advanced renal cancer. The investigators justified the use of placebo in this study by allowing for the enrollment of patients without prior systemic therapy only if “they were living in countries where there were barriers to the access of established therapies”41. Furthermore, the authors cited limited access to targeted therapies and emerging doubts about the value of cytokine based therapy as their rationale for the use of placebo in this study. The pazopanib trial also raises the issue of performing clinical research in resource-limited settings.
Joffe and Miller, in considering the use of placebo in clinical trials in developing countries, argue that the ideal research design would utilize two comparison groups – the best available (therapeutic, diagnostic, or prophylactic) intervention as well as the local standard of care51. This design is the most scientifically sound and allows for the most useful analysis. The most controversial design, as in the case of the pazopanib study, is the use of a local standard of care control only. Critics argue that the use of placebo in this case is a disadvantage to participants as it is inferior to the best available therapy. Joffe and Miller argue, however, that this is a flawed argument that ignores the reality of the alternatives available to potential participants in low-resource settings 51. If placebo and supportive care is equivalent to the best care available to potential participants, no harm is being done by enrollment in the study. On the contrary, entry into the trial is beneficial as it gives the patient a chance of being assigned to a potentially beneficial therapy. In cases such as this, Joffe and Miller support the use of the “independent clinician” heuristic – “ask how a knowledgeable independent clinician responsible for an eligible patient would advise her, bearing in mind the available treatment options” 51.
The high burden of cancer in the developing world highlights the need for clinical research in low-resource settings51. Such research is essential but can be ethically challenging and requires thoughtful experimental design, adherence to established principles of ethical research, as well as consideration of the needs and societal values of host communities.
Conclusion
The field of kidney cancer is robust with clinical scenarios and research questions that may pose ethical dilemmas. In this review, we have attempted to discuss a few of these dilemmas and provide some framework for arriving at a practical and ethically sound solution. We strongly recommend the use of clinical and research ethics consultations when considering complex ethical questions. These resources are invaluable in assisting ethical decision-making as well as involving key stakeholders during routine patient care or the design and conduct of clinical research.
Due to the growth of clinical research in this field as well as the increasing incidence of kidney cancer, continued and nuanced examination of these ethical issues, and others, will be needed. Moreover, an understanding of these issues is an important aspect of the training of clinicians and researchers at all levels.
Supplementary Material
Acknowledgments
Funding:
This work is supported by a grant from the National Cancer Institute (P30CA072720).
Glossary
- NHS
National Health Service
- BAUS
British Association of Urological Surgeons
- NCI
National Cancer Institute
- TKI
Tyrosine kinase inhibitor
References
- 1.Siegel R, Ma J, Zou Z, Jemal A. Cancer statistics, 2014. CA: a cancer journal for clinicians. 2014;64(1):9–29. doi: 10.3322/caac.21208. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Campbell SC, Lane, Brian R. Malignant Renal Tumors. In: Wein AJ, Kavoussi Louis R., Novick Andrew C., Partin Alan W., Peters Craig A., editors. Campbell-Walsh Urology. 10th Ed. Vol. 2. Elsevier Saunders; Philadelphia, PA: 2011. pp. 1413–1474. 10th ed. [Google Scholar]
- 3.Cainzos MA, Gonzalez-Vinagre S. Informed consent in surgery. World journal of surgery. 2014;38(7):1587–1593. doi: 10.1007/s00268-014-2585-0. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Association AU. [12/10/2014];AUA Code of Ethics. https://www.auanet.org/common/pdf/myaua/Code-of-Ethics.pdf. 2014.
- 5.Birkmeyer JD, Stukel TA, Siewers AE, Goodney PP, Wennberg DE, Lucas FL. Surgeon volume and operative mortality in the United States. The New England journal of medicine. 2003;349(22):2117–2127. doi: 10.1056/NEJMsa035205. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Birkmeyer JD, Finks JF, O'Reilly A, et al. Surgical skill and complication rates after bariatric surgery. The New England journal of medicine. 2013;369(15):1434–1442. doi: 10.1056/NEJMsa1300625. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.Char SJ LB, Kirkwood KS. How important is disclosing surgeon experience when obtaining informed consent? J Am Coll Surg. 2011;213(3S):S112–S113. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Ganai S. Disclosure of surgeon experience. World journal of surgery. 2014;38(7):1622–1625. doi: 10.1007/s00268-014-2558-3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Burger I, Schill K, Goodman S. Disclosure of individual surgeon's performance rates during informed consent: ethical and epistemological considerations. Annals of surgery. 2007;245(4):507–513. doi: 10.1097/01.sla.0000242713.82125.d1. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Clarke S, Oakley J. Informed consent and surgeons' performance. The Journal of medicine and philosophy. 2004;29(1):11–35. doi: 10.1076/jmep.29.1.11.30415. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Ghani KR, Sukumar S, Sammon JD, Rogers CG, Trinh QD, Menon M. Practice patterns and outcomes of open and minimally invasive partial nephrectomy since the introduction of robotic partial nephrectomy: results from the nationwide inpatient sample. The Journal of urology. 2014;191(4):907–912. doi: 10.1016/j.juro.2013.10.099. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Mathieu R, Verhoest G, Droupy S, et al. Predictive factors of complications after robot-assisted laparoscopic partial nephrectomy: a retrospective multicentre study. BJU international. 2013;112(4):E283–289. doi: 10.1111/bju.12222. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Kouchoukos NT, Cohn LH, Sade RM. Are surgeons ethically obligated to refer patients to other surgeons who achieve better results? The Annals of thoracic surgery. 2004;77(3):757–760. doi: 10.1016/S0003-4975(03)01447-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Campbell SC, Novick AC, Belldegrun A, et al. Guideline for management of the clinical T1 renal mass. The Journal of urology. 2009;182(4):1271–1279. doi: 10.1016/j.juro.2009.07.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15.Henderson JM, Fowler S, Joyce A, Dickinson A, Keeley FX, Baus Perioperative outcomes of 6042 nephrectomies in 2012: surgeon-reported results in the UK from the British Association of Urological Surgeons (BAUS) nephrectomy database. BJU international. 2014 doi: 10.1111/bju.12770. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Keeley FX. Public reporting of individual surgeons' outcomes in the UK. The Canadian journal of urology. 2014;21(5):7429. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Surgeons TBAoU [11/25/2014];Surgical Outcomes Data. 2014 Nov; 2014. 2014. [Google Scholar]
- 18.Becker A, Bianchi M, Hansen J, et al. Benefit in regionalization of care for patients treated with nephrectomy: a Nationwide Inpatient Sample. World journal of urology. 2014;32(6):1511–1521. doi: 10.1007/s00345-014-1256-y. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Marc Smaldone JS, Canter Daniel, Starkey Russell, Zhu Fang, Stitzenberg Karyn, Kutikov Alexander, Uzzo Robert. REGIONALIZATION OF RENAL SURGERY: IMPACT OF HOSPITAL VOLUME ON UTILIZATION OF PARTIAL NEPHRECTOMY. Journal of Urology. 2012;187(4S):e174–175. [Google Scholar]
- 20.Monn MF, Bahler CD, Flack CK, Dube HT, Sundaram CP. The impact of hospital volume on postoperative complications following robot-assisted partial nephrectomy. Journal of endourology / Endourological Society. 2014;28(10):1231–1236. doi: 10.1089/end.2014.0265. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Cooperberg MR, Modak S, Konety BR. Trends in regionalization of inpatient care for urological malignancies, 1988 to 2002. The Journal of urology. 2007;178(5):2103–2108. doi: 10.1016/j.juro.2007.07.040. discussion 2108. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Birkmeyer NJ, Goodney PP, Stukel TA, Hillner BE, Birkmeyer JD. Do cancer centers designated by the National Cancer Institute have better surgical outcomes? Cancer. 2005;103(3):435–441. doi: 10.1002/cncr.20785. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23.Paulson EC, Mitra N, Sonnad S, et al. National Cancer Institute designation predicts improved outcomes in colorectal cancer surgery. Annals of surgery. 2008;248(4):675–686. doi: 10.1097/SLA.0b013e318187a757. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24.Bilimoria KY, Talamonti MS, Wayne JD, et al. Effect of hospital type and volume on lymph node evaluation for gastric and pancreatic cancer. Archives of surgery. 2008;143(7):671–678. doi: 10.1001/archsurg.143.7.671. discussion 678. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Emanuel EJ, Wendler D, Grady C. What makes clinical research ethical? Jama. 2000;283(20):2701–2711. doi: 10.1001/jama.283.20.2701. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Nuremberg Military T. The Nuremberg Code. Jama. 1996;276(20):1691. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27.Assembly WMAG [12/1/2014];WMA Declaration of Helsinki - Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. 1964 http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/. 2014.
- 28.Protection of human subjects; Belmont Report: notice of report for public comment. Federal register. 1979;44(76):23191–23197. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Ghooi RB. The Nuremberg Code-A critique. Perspectives in clinical research. 2011;2(2):72–76. doi: 10.4103/2229-3485.80371. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Millum J, Wendler D, Emanuel EJ. The 50th anniversary of the Declaration of Helsinki: progress but many remaining challenges. Jama. 2013;310(20):2143–2144. doi: 10.1001/jama.2013.281632. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Volpe A, Finelli A, Gill IS, et al. Rationale for percutaneous biopsy and histologic characterisation of renal tumours. European urology. 2012;62(3):491–504. doi: 10.1016/j.eururo.2012.05.009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Halverson SJ, Kunju LP, Bhalla R, et al. Accuracy of determining small renal mass management with risk stratified biopsies: confirmation by final pathology. The Journal of urology. 2013;189(2):441–446. doi: 10.1016/j.juro.2012.09.032. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Peppercorn J, Shapira I, Collyar D, et al. Ethics of mandatory research biopsy for correlative end points within clinical trials in oncology. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2010;28(15):2635–2640. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2009.27.2443. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34.Overman MJ, Modak J, Kopetz S, et al. Use of research biopsies in clinical trials: are risks and benefits adequately discussed? Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2013;31(1):17–22. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2012.43.1718. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Olson EM, Lin NU, Krop IE, Winer EP. The ethical use of mandatory research biopsies. Nature reviews. Clinical oncology. 2011;8(10):620–625. doi: 10.1038/nrclinonc.2011.114. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Peppercorn J. Toward improved understanding of the ethical and clinical issues surrounding mandatory research biopsies. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2013;31(1):1–2. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2012.44.8589. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Rini BI, Escudier B, Tomczak P, et al. Comparative effectiveness of axitinib versus sorafenib in advanced renal cell carcinoma (AXIS): a randomised phase 3 trial. Lancet. 2011;378(9807):1931–1939. doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(11)61613-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Escudier B, Bellmunt J, Negrier S, et al. Phase III trial of bevacizumab plus interferon alfa-2a in patients with metastatic renal cell carcinoma (AVOREN): final analysis of overall survival. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2010;28(13):2144–2150. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2009.26.7849. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39.Rini BI, Halabi S, Rosenberg JE, et al. Phase III trial of bevacizumab plus interferon alfa versus interferon alfa monotherapy in patients with metastatic renal cell carcinoma: final results of CALGB 90206. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2010;28(13):2137–2143. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2009.26.5561. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Motzer RJ, Escudier B, Oudard S, et al. Phase 3 trial of everolimus for metastatic renal cell carcinoma : final results and analysis of prognostic factors. Cancer. 2010;116(18):4256–4265. doi: 10.1002/cncr.25219. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.Sternberg CN, Davis ID, Mardiak J, et al. Pazopanib in locally advanced or metastatic renal cell carcinoma: results of a randomized phase III trial. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2010;28(6):1061–1068. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2009.23.9764. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 42.Escudier B, Eisen T, Stadler WM, et al. Sorafenib in advanced clear-cell renal-cell carcinoma. The New England journal of medicine. 2007;356(2):125–134. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa060655. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43.Motzer RJ, Hutson TE, Tomczak P, et al. Sunitinib versus interferon alfa in metastatic renal-cell carcinoma. The New England journal of medicine. 2007;356(2):115–124. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa065044. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 44.Hudes G, Carducci M, Tomczak P, et al. Temsirolimus, interferon alfa, or both for advanced renal-cell carcinoma. The New England journal of medicine. 2007;356(22):2271–2281. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa066838. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 45.Singer EA, Gupta GN, Marchalik D, Srinivasan R. Evolving therapeutic targets in renal cell carcinoma. Current opinion in oncology. 2013;25(3):273–280. doi: 10.1097/CCO.0b013e32835fc857. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 46.Emanuel EJ, Miller FG. The ethics of placebo-controlled trials--a middle ground. The New England journal of medicine. 2001;345(12):915–919. doi: 10.1056/NEJM200109203451211. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 47.Temple R, Ellenberg SS. Placebo-controlled trials and active-control trials in the evaluation of new treatments. Part 1: ethical and scientific issues. Annals of internal medicine. 2000;133(6):455–463. doi: 10.7326/0003-4819-133-6-200009190-00014. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 48.Daugherty CK, Ratain MJ, Emanuel EJ, Farrell AT, Schilsky RL. Ethical, scientific, and regulatory perspectives regarding the use of placebos in cancer clinical trials. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2008;26(8):1371–1378. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2007.13.5335. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 49.Smith TJ, Temin S, Alesi ER, et al. American Society of Clinical Oncology provisional clinical opinion: the integration of palliative care into standard oncology care. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2012;30(8):880–887. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2011.38.5161. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 50.Peppercorn JM, Smith TJ, Helft PR, et al. American society of clinical oncology statement: toward individualized care for patients with advanced cancer. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2011;29(6):755–760. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2010.33.1744. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 51.Joffe S, Miller FG. Ethics of cancer clinical trials in low-resource settings. Journal of clinical oncology : official journal of the American Society of Clinical Oncology. 2014;32(28):3192–3196. doi: 10.1200/JCO.2014.56.9780. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.