Significance
This paper uncovers the empirical content of many behavioral models of decisions under uncertainty. Studies of global financial markets often ignore a very important piece of the puzzle: individual behavior. We provide tests (and as such, predictions) about how individuals behave when facing uncertainty, such as that faced in financial or asset markets. Behavior at the individual level must be understood before the behavior of the economy at large can even begin to be understood.
Keywords: revealed preference, translation invariance, homotheticity, uncertainty
Abstract
We describe the observable content of some of the most widely used models of decision under uncertainty: models of translation invariant preferences. In particular, we characterize the models of variational, maxmin, constant absolute risk aversion, and constant relative risk aversion utilities. In each case we present a revealed preference axiom that is satisfied by a dataset if and only if the dataset is consistent with the corresponding utility representation. We test our axioms using data from an experiment on financial decisions.
This paper is an investigation of the testable implications of models of decision under uncertainty. We carry out this investigation in financial markets, one of the most common environments in which human subjects face uncertainty.
Risk is uncertainty that can be objectively quantified probabilistically. A gambler in a casino faces risk: He may calculate the probability that a roulette wheel stops on the number 7, or that a die lands on 5. Most scientists, in contrast, face the more general concept of uncertainty and study subjects who face uncertainty. Scientists conduct or analyze experiments with outcomes that they do not know, and for which no probabilities are objectively given.
Of course, the scientist or the subject may have a subjective judgment of how likely different events are. Such judgments may even have a probabilistic expression, but the uncertainty is not resolved by means of a mechanical device for which probabilities can be objectively calculated. Moreover, this fact may cause subjects to display uncertainty aversion, a tendency to prefer risky bets over uncertain ones. Uncertainty aversion was famously documented by David Ellsberg (1), and the theories we treat in our paper are in part designed to describe uncertainty aversion.
In uncertain situations, human subjects choose among uncertain prospects. These are functions specifying an “outcome” for each element of a given set of “states of the world.” Think of an insurance contract that pays off a given sum only if some accident occurs. The set of states of the world is the binary set that codifies whether an accident has occurred, and the outcome is the payoff. In financial markets, the uncertain prospects correspond to financial assets, whereas the state of the worlds describe the relevant economic fundamentals, and the outcomes monetary payoffs.*
A long tradition in decision theory develops models of how humans make decisions under uncertainty. A crucial idea in this development is that of translation invariance. Translation invariance means that if two uncertain prospects are transformed in the same way, by adding to each prospect a given, fixed, monetary payment, then the subject’s preference between the two prospects should be preserved. For example, if the subject prefers insurance contract A over B, then the preference should be maintained after the price of each insurance contract has been raised by the same amount. A related idea is homotheticity, where scaling the payoffs of the two contracts should not affect how they are ranked. Translation invariance and homotheticity give rise to different theories of decision under uncertainty.
Theories demand to be tested, and our contribution lies in working out the testable implications of theories of homothetic and translation invariant behavior under uncertainty. We focus on financial markets because these are some of the most familiar and common uncertain environments for human subjects. If one is to test a theory, it makes sense to study it in the subjects’ most familiar environments. It is plausible that agents do not know how to behave in an artificial environment, but that they have learned how to deal with uncertainty in familiar environments. For human subjects, few uncertain environments are as familiar as financial markets. Most existing experimental environments are artificial: They involve human subjects choosing among bets on extractions of colored balls from urns of uncertain composition [Ellsberg’s thought experiments are the best known of these (1)]. Our contribution is instead to focus on designs based on financial markets.
Our main results characterize the financial datasets that are consistent with the theories. Given is a finite collection of data on purchases of financial assets. The question is, When are such data consistent with a theory of choice under uncertainty? We provide answers for some of the most commonly encountered theories, those based on translation invariance and homotheticity.
We show that our results are applicable to the analysis and design of experiments by using a recent experiment by Hey and Pace (2). Hey and Pace have subjects decide on purchases of financial assets. We use the data they collect to test for consistency with maxmin expected utility, a theory of decision under uncertainty based on translation invariance and homotheticity. The conclusion of our analysis is that Hey and Pace’s data reject the maxmin theory. The finding is preliminary and meant mainly as an illustration of our methods, but if confirmed it would mean that some of the best-known theories of choice under uncertainty, theories that are thought of as weak, and accommodating of diverse behavioral and psychological phenomena, do not in fact stand up to empirical scrutiny on data from financial experiments.
The theories covered by our results include risk-neutral variational preferences (3), risk-neutral maxmin preferences (4), and subjective expected utility preferences with constant absolute risk aversion: so-called CARA preferences. Analogously to the CARA case, we also work out the testable implications of subjective expected utility preferences with constant relative risk aversion: so-called CRRA preferences. The theories have been used for different purposes. Variational and maxmin preferences are the most commonly used models of uncertainty aversion (3–6). They are also used to capture model robustness (7). CARA and CRRA preferences are extremely common in applied work in macroeconomics and finance, among other fields.
The authors of refs. 8, 9, and 10 carried out exercises similar to ours, also focusing on financial market experiments, but in a context of risk, not uncertainty. The closest papers to ours are those given in refs. 11, 12, and 13. Echenique and Saito (11) studied the case of subjective expected utility but did not address the more general theories studied here, and that have been proposed to address the empirical shortcomings of subjective expected utility. Bayer et al. (12) and Polisson and Quah (13) treat some of the same theories we do but give a characterization in terms of the solution of a system of inequalities. We give a revealed preference axiom (a characterization that references only observable data) that has to be satisfied for the data to be rationalizable. It can be written in the UNCAF (universal negation of concatenations of atomic formulas) form, which is the kind of axiom that characterizes the empirical content of a theory (14). A system of (nonlinear) inequalities may not give an economic interpretation to the characterization, and it may not be computationally feasible.†
Definitions
Let S be a finite set of states of the world. An act is a function from S into ; is the set of acts. An act can be interpreted as a state-contingent monetary payment. Define . represents the set of probability distributions on S, that is, .
A preference relation on is a complete and transitive binary relation ; we denote by the strict part of . A function defines a preference relation by if and only if . We say that u represents , or that it is a utility function for . A preference relation on is locally nonsatiated if for every x and every there is y such that and .
Preferences, Utilities, and Data
A dataset D is a finite collection , where each is a vector of strictly positive (so-called Arrow–Debreu) prices, and each is an act. The interpretation of a dataset is that each pair consists of an act chosen from the budget of affordable acts. Such datasets are common in financial markets experiments (2, 12, 15).
A dataset is rationalizable by a preference relation if whenever . So, a dataset is rationalizable by a preference relation when the choices in the dataset would have been optimal for that preference relation. A dataset is rationalizable by a utility function u if it is rationalizable by the preference relation represented by u. So, a dataset is rationalizable by a utility function when the choices in the dataset would have maximized that utility function in the relevant budget set.
A preference relation is translation invariant if for all and all , we have if and only if .
A preference relation is homothetic if for all and all , we have if and only if .
A preference relation is a risk-neutral variational preference if there is a convex and lower semicontinuous function such that the function
represents . If a dataset is rationalizable by a risk-neutral variational preference relation, we will say that the dataset set is risk-neutral variational-rationalizable.
A special case of variational preference is maxmin: A preference relation is risk-neutral maxmin if there is a closed and convex set such that the utility function
represents . If a dataset is rationalizable by a risk-neutral maxmin preference relation, we will say that the dataset set is risk-neutral maxmin-rationalizable. More generally, a preference relation is risk-averse maxmin if there is a closed and convex set , where for each and each , , and a concave utility such that the utility function
represents . If a dataset is rationalizable by a maxmin preference relation, we will say that the dataset set is maxmin-rationalizable.
A utility is CARA if there is and for which for all , , and
Note that CARA is a special case of subjective expected utility.‡
A utility is CRRA if there is and for which for all , , and
If a dataset is rationalizable by a CARA (CRRA) utility, we will say that the dataset set is CARA (CRRA) rationalizable.
Variational and Maxmin Preferences
We present the results on variational and maxmin rationalizability as Theorems 1 and 2. These models satisfy the hypothesis that for any , . This hypothesis is known as convexity of preference. Convexity is related to uncertainty aversion in the sense of ref. 4. In fact, given the assumptions of monotonicity found in that paper, together with the assumption that the preference is risk-neutral (i.e., lotteries are evaluated according to their expected value), it is equivalent to uncertainty aversion. Uncertainty aversion is the idea that an agent dislikes uncertainty and suffers from his or her ignorance of the possible probability distribution that governs outcomes.
One important conclusion that emerges from our analysis is that convexity is not testable with market data. This therefore means that under the maintained hypothesis of risk neutrality (and monotonicity), uncertainty aversion cannot be detected with financial data.
Theorem 1.
The following statements are equivalent:
-
i)
Dataset D is rationalizable by a locally nonsatiated, translation invariant preference.
-
ii)
Dataset D is rationalizable by a continuous, strictly increasing, concave utility function satisfying the property .
-
iii)
Dataset D is risk-neutral variational-rationalizable.
-
iv)
For every , and every sequence ,
where addition is modulo M, as usual.
Note that the equivalence between ii and iii is due to ref. 3.
Remark:
The fact that i implies ii and iii implies that if a dataset is rationalizable by a translation invariant preference, the dataset is also rationalizable by a risk-neutral variational preference (which automatically satisfies convexity).
Remark:
The preceding result can be generalized. Suppose we were interested in the testable implications of preferences that are β-translation invariant, for some , . That is, we want to know whether for all , we have if and only if for all t, . Define the seminorm . Then it is an easy exercise to verify that the testable implications of β-translation invariance are given by Eq. 4, replacing with .
Remark:
The test in ref. 4 is related to cyclic monotonicity. This is similar to the test given in ref. 17 for quasilinear preferences (and to a result in ref. 18).
We now turn our attention to maxmin preferences.
We say that a function is linearly homogeneous if for all and all , we have .
Theorem 2.
The following statements are equivalent:
-
i)
Dataset D is rationalizable by a locally nonsatiated, homothetic and translation invariant preference.
-
ii)
Dataset D is rationalizable by a continuous, strictly increasing, linearly homogeneous and concave utility function satisfying the property that .
-
iii)
Dataset D is risk-neutral maxmin-rationalizable.
-
iv)
For every k and l,
The equivalence between ii and iii is due to ref. 4.
It is interesting to note that, just as in Theorem 1, under the maintained hypotheses of risk aversion and monotonicity, uncertainty aversion has no content for behavior.
Remark:
The rationalizing variational and maxmin preferences can be taken to imply “full support” priors. In the proof of Theorem 1, we shown that there is satisfying , which implies for all , . In the proof of Theorem 2 we show that for each and all , .
CARA and CRRA
The previous section considers translation invariance and homotheticity as general properties of preferences in choice under uncertainty. Here we focus on the case of subjective expected utility. So, we consider models in which the agent has a single prior over states, and maximizes his or her expected utility. The prior is unknown and must be inferred from his or her choices. Translation invariance gives rise to CARA preferences, and homotheticity to CRRA.
Theorem 3.
A dataset D is CARA rationalizable if and only if there is such that Eq. 1 holds for all and and CRRA rationalizable if and only if there is such that Eq. 2 holds for all and .
[1] |
[2] |
The conditions in Theorem 3 may look like existential conditions: essentially Afriat inequalities. Afriat inequalities are indeed the source of Eqs. 1 and 2, as evidenced by the proof of Theorem 3, but note that the statements are equivalent to nonexistential statements: Eq. 1 says that when ,
is independent of k, t, and s, and that when then . Similarly for Eq. 2.
It is worth pointing out that, except in the case when for all observations, all prices are equal, and consumption of all goods are equal, Eq. 1 can have only one solution. Hence, risk preferences are uniquely identified.
The next corollary also shows that beliefs are identified. Recall that a CARA utility is defined by a pair , with and .
Corollary.
If and define CARA utilities that rationalize D, then . Furthermore, coincide with the unique solution to Eq. 1. Similarly for CRRA rationalizability and Eq. 2.
Risk-Averse Maxmin with Two States
Theorem 2 is about risk-neutral maxmin. Here we turn to maxmin with risk aversion. In this section, we assume that there are two states (i.e., ). A preference relation is maxmin if there is a closed and convex set , where for each and each , , and a concave utility such that the utility function
represents . If a dataset is rationalizable by a maxmin preference relation, we will say that the dataset set is maxmin-rationalizable.
Let be the set of all k such that . Let be the set of all k such that , and be the set of all k such that . Note that .
Say that a sequence of pairs is balanced if each k appears as (on the left of the pair) the same number of times it appears as (on the right).
Given a sequence of pairs , consider the following notation: Let , , for and .
Axiom: Strong Axiom of Revealed Maxmin Expected Utility.
For any balanced sequence of pairs in which
-
i)
for all i;
-
ii)
The product of price ratios satisfies
[3] |
Theorem 4.
A dataset is maxmin rationalizable if and only if it satisfies strong axiom of revealed maxmin expected utility (SARMEU).
Echenique and Saito (11) show that a stronger axiom, strong axiom of revealed subjective expected utility (SARSEU), characterizes rationalizability by subjective expected utility. Instead of condition ii of SARMEU, SARSEU requires
[4] |
Theorem 4 is useful because it makes explicit what one would need to see in an experiment (with two states, a common setup in laboratory experiments) in order for choices to be consistent with maxmin utility, but inconsistent with subjective expected utility. For a dataset to be maxmin rationalizable, but inconsistent with subjective expected utility, it needs to contain a sequence in the conditions of SARSEU in which , but where .
As we have emphasized, the result in Theorem 4 is for two states. There are two simplifications afforded by the assumption of two states, and the two are crucial in obtaining the theorem. The first is that with two states there are only two extreme priors to any set of priors. With the assumption that u is monotonic, one can know which of the two extremes is relevant to evaluate any given act.§ The second simplification is a bit harder to see, but it comes from the fact that one can normalize the probability of one state to be one and only keep track of the probability of the other state. Then the property of being an extreme prior carries over to the probability of the state that is left “free.”¶
Testing Maxmin
Hey and Pace (2) studied models of decision making under uncertainty using data from a laboratory experiment; 129 subjects are asked to allocate 50 experimental tokens between two states, states s or . Tokens allocated to each state have a value of and . If a subject decides to allocate tokens to state s, then he obtains a payment of when state s realizes; and when state realizes.
In each decision problem, each subject’s decision is characterized by a triple , where is the number of tokens she decides to allocate to state s. To map such decision to our notion of data, set prices to be and (a normalization), and . Then, we define consumptions (monetary amounts) as and .
In the experiment, there are three underling states: “color” 1, 2, and 3. However, only two states are relevant in each decision. So, we can test SARMEU. Hey and Pace (2) used a Bingo Blower to decide a realization of a state. The Bingo Blower is a rectangular-shaped, glass-sided object in which many balls, whose color is either 1, 2, or 3, are in continuous motion, being moved by a wind from a fan in the base. A ball is drawn is from the Bingo Blower and the color of the ball determines the state.# In total, each subject thus completes 76 decision problems. There are two types of decision problems. Type 1 problems asked subjects to allocate tokens between two of the three colors, and type 2 problems asked them to make allocations between one of the three colors and the other two. There were 41 type 1 problems and 35 type 2 problems. For example, in a type 1 problem, state ; state . In a type 2 problem, state ; state .
One of the conclusions made by Hey and Pace (2) is that according to the Bayesian information criterion the loss in predictive power in using SEU instead of generalizations of SEU is relatively small in magnitude. We test SARMEU for each individual subject and for each type of decision problem. The tests are based on linearized Afriat inequalities.
Table 1 summarizes the results. Across six types of decision problems, we find that about 3–8% of the 129 subjects are MEU-rational. Our result shows that MEU does not explain the subjects’ choices. This implies that SEU, a special case of MEU, does not explain the subjects’ choices either. One conclusion of our results is that decision theorists’ efforts to account for experimental behavior do not seem to go very far in explaining the data of Hey and Pace (2).
Table 1.
Type | Allocation | K | Pass rate |
1a | Color 2 and 3 | 14 | 0.054 |
1b | Color 3 and 1 | 15 | 0.031 |
1c | Color 1 and 2 | 12 | 0.070 |
2a | Color 1 and (2 or 3) | 9 | 0.078 |
2b | Color 2 and (1 or 3) | 14 | 0.039 |
2c | Color 3 and (1 or 2) | 12 | 0.054 |
Proofs
We provide the proofs of Theorems 1, 2, and 3. We omit the proof of Theorem 4 (20), which is similar to the proofs in ref. 11.
Proof of Theorem 1:
That iii ⇒ i is obvious. We shall first prove that i ⇒ iv.
Suppose, toward a contradiction, D is a dataset satisfying i but not iv. Then, we have a cycle . Let us without loss assume the sequence is so as to avoid cumbersome notation. Let .
Define a new sequence inductively. Let , and let , where is chosen so that . Specifically, and
for . Let and consider the dataset , .
The original dataset is rationalizable by some locally nonsatiated and translation invariant preference . It is easy to see that the same preference rationalizes the dataset . Indeed, if , then , by definition of and . So , and thus by translation invariance of .
Observe that
and that for . Therefore, . In particular, for (mod M). Thus, as is rationalizable by and is locally nonsatiated. This contradicts the transitivity of .
Now we show that iv ⇒ i. Let . Let be the set of all subsequences for which and define . By iv, if has a cycle (meaning that for with ), then there is a shorter sequence with
Therefore, is well defined, because the infimum can be taken over a finite set.
That defined in this fashion is concave, strictly increasing and continuous is immediate. To see that it rationalizes the data, suppose that . Then . It is clear then by definition that .
Finally, to show that , note that for any , we have . The result then follows by construction.
We end the proof by showing that ii ⇒ iii. Let be as in the statement of ii. Define the concave conjugate of u by
where the second equality uses that . Now note that if . Note also that the monotonicity of u implies that if there is s such that . One can also show that there is for which .‖ Finally, observe that by strict monotonicity, if there is for which , then . Hence, we can consider the domain of f to be a subset of . Moreover, implies for all , .
Now, since u is continuous, it is a standard application of the separating hyperplane theorem to establish that . Because u rationalizes the dataset, the dataset is variational rationalizable.
Proof of Theorem 2:
It is obvious that iii ⇒ ii and that ii ⇒ i. Hence, to show the theorem, it suffices to show that iv implies iii and that i implies iv.
For a dataset D, let . It is easy to see that iv ⇒ iii. Let be the convex hull of . Then, it is immediate that rationalizes D. Moreover, for each and all , because for all and .
We prove that i ⇒ iv. Suppose that D satisfies i but not iv. Then, there are k and l for which . Let be a preference relation as stated in i. By homotheticity of , for any scalar , rationalizes the data . To see this, observe that if , then , so that , and by homogeneity, . Now, for sufficiently small, implies that
So either or . Then the dataset violates iv in Theorem 1, contradicting the fact that it is rationalized by , which is assumed to be translation invariant.
Proof of Theorem 3:
The idea in the proof is to solve the first-order conditions for the unknown terms. Consider first the case of CARA. Let and rationalize D. Then, we know that maximizes subject to . By considering the Lagrangean and the first-order conditions, we may conclude that for every and every , we have
Conclude that . By taking logs, the system becomes
[5] |
In the case of CRRA, the existence of a rationalizing π and parameter α imply a first-order condition of the form
[6] |
We can denote by in Eqs. 5 and 6. Thus, we obtain that D is rationalizable if and only if there exist and such that the following equation is solved for all with :
where for CARA rationalizability, and for CRRA rationalizability.
Now the necessity of the axioms is obvious. Let , then
for any s and t. Thus
So, i is satisfied for the case of CARA rationalizability, and ii is satisfied for the case of CRRA rationalizability.
To prove sufficiency, let
Let be such that for all k, , s, and t,
Then in particular, for all k, , s, and t,
[7] |
Note also that
[8] |
Fix and let be arbitrary. For any , define by
for some k. In fact, by Eq. 7, this definition is independent of k because .
Given this definition, note that
where the second equality uses Eq. 8.
Hence, with the constructed we have
for all and k. The first-order conditions for rationalizability are therefore satisfied.
Acknowledgments
We thank Simon Grant and Massimo Marinacci, who posed questions to us that led to some of the results in this paper. We also thank John Hey and Noemi Pace for allowing us to use their data and Taisuke Imai for carrying out our test. This work was supported by National Science Foundation Grant SES-1426867 (to C.P.C.).
Footnotes
The authors declare no conflict of interest.
This article is a PNAS Direct Submission.
*In probability theory, an uncertain prospect together with an underlying probability over the states of the world is termed a “random variable.”
†The paper by Bayer et al. (12) is a case in point, where the solution to the system of inequalities is implemented by a grid search. A conclusive test is not possible since they results depend on the assumed granularity of the grid.
‡In fact, it is also a special case of a risk neutral variational preference, a fact exploited by ref. 16.
§This would also be true in the model of ref. 19, whose uncertainty averse counterpart is equivalent to MEU in the case of two states.
¶This can be seen in the proof of Lemma 1 when we go from to .
#The idea behind the use of a Bingo Blower was that subjects could not have sufficient information to calculate objective probabilities.
‖For example, take π to support at 0. We claim that . Suppose by means of contradiction that there is for which . Observe that π supports at the act y, which returns in each state. Observe that implies , by continuity of u and definition of the supporting hyperplane, that is, implies because the latter sets are the interiors of the former. Therefore, if , we conclude , a contradiction.
References
- 1.Ellsberg D. Risk, ambiguity, and the Savage axioms. Q J Econ. 1961;75(4):643–669. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Hey J, Pace N. The explanatory and predictive power of non two-stage-probability theories of decision making under ambiguity. J Risk Uncertain. 2014;49(1):1–29. [Google Scholar]
- 3.Maccheroni F, Marinacci M, Rustichini A. Ambiguity aversion, robustness, and the variational representation of preferences. Econometrica. 2006;74(6):1447–1498. [Google Scholar]
- 4.Gilboa I, Schmeidler D. Maxmin expected utility with non-unique prior. J Math Econ. 1989;18(2):141–153. [Google Scholar]
- 5.Cerreia-Vioglio S, Maccheroni F, Marinacci M, Montrucchio L. Classical subjective expected utility. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA. 2013;110(17):6754–6759. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1207805110. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Cerreia-Vioglio S, Maccheroni F, Marinacci M, Montrucchio L. Uncertainty averse preferences. J Econ Theory. 2011;146(4):1275–1330. [Google Scholar]
- 7.Hansen LP, Sargent TJ. Robustness. Princeton Univ Press; Princeton: 2008. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Green RC, Srivastava S. Expected utility maximization and demand behavior. J Econ Theory. 1986;38(2):313–323. [Google Scholar]
- 9.Varian HR. Estimating risk aversion from Arrow-Debreu portfolio choice. Econometrica. 1988;43(4):973–979. [Google Scholar]
- 10.Kubler F, Selden L, Wei X. Asset demand based tests of expected utility maximization. Am Econ Rev. 2014;104(11):3459–3480. [Google Scholar]
- 11.Echenique F, Saito K. Savage in the market. Econometrica. 2015;83(4):1467–1495. [Google Scholar]
- 12.Bayer R, Bose S, Polisson M, Renou L. 2012. Ambiguity revealed (Univ of Essex¸ Essex, UK)
- 13.Polisson M, Quah J. 2013. Revealed preference tests under risk and uncertainty. Working Paper 13/24 (Univ of Leicester, Leicester, UK)
- 14.Chambers CP, Echenique F, Shmaya E. The axiomatic structure of empirical content. Am Econ Rev. 2014;104(8):2303–2319. [Google Scholar]
- 15.Ahn D, Choi S, Gale D, Kariv S. Estimating ambiguity aversion in a portfolio choice experiment. Quant Econom. 2014;5(2):195–223. [Google Scholar]
- 16.Strzalecki T. Axiomatic foundations of multiplier preferences. Econometrica. 2011;79(1):47–73. [Google Scholar]
- 17.Brown DJ, Calsamiglia C. The nonparametric approach to applied welfare analysis. Econ Theory. 2007;31(1):183–188. [Google Scholar]
- 18.Rockafellar RT. Convex Analysis. Princeton Univ Press; Princeton: 1997. [Google Scholar]
- 19.Schmeidler D. Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica. 1989;57(3):571–587. [Google Scholar]
- 20.Chambers CP, Echenique F, Saito K. 2015 doi: 10.1073/pnas.1517760113. Testable implications of translation invariance and homotheticity: Variational, maxmin, cara and CRRA preferences. Working paper (California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA). Available at www.hss.caltech.edu/content/testable-implications-translation-invariance-and-homotheticity-variational-maxmin-cara-and. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]