Skip to main content
Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine logoLink to Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine
. 2016 May 5;109(5):184–189. doi: 10.1177/0141076816643332

The revised Declaration of Helsinki: cosmetic or real change?

Aisha Y Malik 1,, Charles Foster 2
PMCID: PMC4872207  PMID: 27150712

Abstract

The Declaration of Helsinki, adopted by the World Medical Association’s General Assembly in 1964, is the most important set of guidelines about research on human participants. It both reflects and shapes the ethos of international research ethics. It is a living instrument and is reviewed and revised regularly. Its latest revision was in 2013. There are four substantial changes, reflected in the new Paragraph 15 (which deals with compensation for trial related injuries), Paragraph 33 (relating to placebos), Paragraph 20 (relating to vulnerable groups) and the new Paragraph 34 (relating to post-trial provisions). This article analyses these changes, and asks whether they indicate any shift in the overall philosophy of the Declaration. We conclude that these changes, though significant, are not tectonic. They accord with the spirit that has motivated the Declaration through all its iterations, and indicate a steady, incremental evolution towards a holistic code of research ethics for research on human participants. Patient autonomy, though crucial, is no longer the only concern of the Declaration; distributive justice and beneficence are motivating forces too. While the Declaration is aware of the need to facilitate research, it is equally aware of the need to protect the vulnerable, and of the practical difficulties involved in that protection.

Keywords: Global health, ethics, medical education


The Declaration of Helsinki was adopted by the World Medical Association in 1964 at its 18th General Assembly. It is a set of ethical guidelines relating to research on human subjects and is widely regarded as authoritative.1 It is reviewed and revised regularly.2

The latest revision of the Declaration was in 2013. New paragraphs have been added and it has been rearranged, with the paragraphs organised into specific sections. There are four substantial changes, reflected in Paragraph 15 (which deals with compensation for trial-related injuries), Paragraph 33 (relating to placebos), Paragraph 20 (relating to vulnerable groups) and Paragraph 34 (relating to post-trial provisions). This article analyses these changes, and asks whether they indicate any shift in the overall philosophy of the Declaration.

The new Paragraph 15: Compensation for harm

Paragraph 15 reads:

‘Appropriate compensation and treatment for subjects who are harmed as a result of participating in research must be ensured’.3

This is wholly new. It had, surprisingly, no counterpart in previous versions, though the 2008 version required that information regarding compensation be stated in the research protocol – implying that participants were (morally) entitled to compensation, but did nothing to ensure that they got it.

While earlier iterations focused on ensuring that the autonomy interests of participants were respected, this new clause is an acknowledgment that bodily integrity and financial interests are important too.

Paragraph 33: Use of placebos

The period between 1996 and 2000 saw a debate over the paragraphs concerning the use of inert placebos for patients in control groups. The debate became particularly heated in relation to short regimen Azidothymidine trials to prevent mother to child transmission of HIV/AIDS in sub-Saharan Africa. The issue was whether the control group should be given the ‘best proven’ or the ‘best available’ treatment, or where there was no available treatment, as is often the case in developing countries (due to financial constraints), whether the control group should be given the placebo.

The clause of using placebos as comparator was introduced in 1996. Following concerns that this clause had been inconsistently interpreted, clarifications were added. But there was criticism that the clarification’s appeal to scientific methodology could expose participants to ‘serious or irreversible harm’.4 This issue was addressed in various ways (Table 1), culminating in this formulation in the 2013 version:

Where for compelling and scientifically sound methodological reasons the use of any intervention less effective than the best proven one, the use of placebo, or no intervention is necessary to determine the efficacy or safety of an intervention and the patients who receive any intervention less effective than the best proven one, placebo or no intervention will not be subject to additional risks of serious or irreversible harm as a result of not receiving the best proven intervention. [3, para. 33, emphasis added]

Table 1.

Changes relating to the use of placebo in the Declaration of Helsinki (1989–2013).

1989 1996 2000 Note of clarification 2002 2008 2013
The potential benefits, hazards and discomfort of a new method should be weighed against the advantages of the best current diagnostic and therapeutic methods (Section II: para. 2) In any medical study, every patient – including those of the control group, if any- should be assured of the best proven diagnostic and therapeutic method (Section II: para. 3) The potential benefits, hazards and discomfort of a new method should be weighed against the advantages of the best current diagnostic and therapeutic methods (Section II: para. 2) In any medical study, every patient – including those of the control group, if any- should be assured of the best proven diagnostic and therapeutic method. This does not exclude the use of inert placebo in studies where no proven diagnostic or therapeutic method exists (Section II: para. 3) The benefits, risks, burdens and effectiveness of a new method should be tested against those of the best current prophylactic, diagnostic and therapeutic methods. This does not exclude the use of placebo, or no treatment, in studies where no proven prophylactic, diagnostic or therapeutic method exists (Section C: para. 29) The WMA hereby reaffirms its position that extreme care must be taken in making use of placebo-controlled trial and that in general this methodology should only be used in the absence of existing proven therapy. However, a placebo-controlled trial may be ethically acceptable, even if proven therapy is available, under the following circumstances: Where for compelling and scientifically sound methodological reasons its use is necessary to determine the efficacy or safety of a prophylactic, diagnostic or therapeutic method: or Where a prophylactic, diagnostic or therapeutic method is being investigated for a minor condition and the patients who receive the placebo will not be subject to any additional risk of serious or irreversible harm. The benefits, risks, burdens and effectiveness of a new intervention must be tested against those of the best current proven intervention except in the following circumstances: The use of placebo, or no treatment, is acceptable in studies where no current proven intervention exists; or Where for compelling and scientifically sound methodological reasons the use of placebo is necessary to determine the efficacy or safety of an intervention and the patients who receive placebo or no treatment will not be subject to any risk of serious or irreversible harm. Extreme care must be taken to avoid abuse of this option (para. 32) The benefits, risks, burdens and effectiveness of a new intervention must be tested against those of the best proven intervention(s), except in the following circumstances: Where no proven intervention exists, the use of placebo, or no intervention, is acceptable; or Where for compelling and scientifically sound methodological reasons the use of any intervention less effective than the best proven one, the use of placebo, or no intervention is necessary to determine the efficacy or safety of an intervention and the patients who receive any intervention less effective than the best proven one, placebo or no intervention will not be subject to additional risks of serious or irreversible harm as a result of not receiving the best proven intervention. Extreme care must be taken to avoid abuse of this option (para. 33)

Was it right to add: ‘the use of any intervention less effective than the best proven one’? There are two main concerns:

First: the vast majority of subjects in outsourced clinical trials (typically in developing countries) – will not have the best proven intervention available. Here, instead of encouraging efforts to make the best treatment options available, new but sub-optimal interventions may become the standard – so exacerbating disparities, within and between countries.

Second: in locations where the best proven intervention may be available, giving the control group the less effective intervention is ethically dubious. Patients may be harmed by not having the best available treatment. In these circumstances, the research ethics committee is likely to refuse to approve the trial. If the trial did go ahead, patients suffering ‘additional’ harm may invoke their right to compensation under Paragraph 15 of the Declaration.

The trend is obvious enough: though there is much opposition by the proponents of placebo-controlled trials,5 the Declaration is opposed to the use of placebos.

Paragraph 20 and 34: The general philosophy of justice and beneficence

Justice, applied to research, entails fair distribution of risks and benefits and equal access to the fruits of research. Beneficence means to do good, to make efforts to maximise possible benefits and minimise harms. It is said that the Declaration has moved from being a purely ethical document to one that is increasingly concerned with social justice.5 This is a curious observation: social justice is an essential element of ethics.

Paragraph 20: Vulnerable groups and individuals

The exploitation of vulnerable populations, whether in the developing countries or developed countries, is a real danger in medical research.69 The problem is compounded by the fact that much research is conducted by commercial organisations motivated by profit.9,10 One way of reducing the chance of exploitation is to insist, as all versions of the Declaration have done, on informed consent. Although the Declaration allows for consultation with the family or community leaders in some contexts, thus respecting local cultural norms,7 it emphasises that the decision to enroll must be made freely by the participant herself/himself [3, para.25].

Distributive justice is the basis for other anti-exploitation mechanisms. The 2013 version states, at Paragraph 20:

Medical research with a vulnerable group is only justified if the research is responsive to the health needs or priorities of this group and the research cannot be carried out in a non-vulnerable group. In addition, this group should stand to benefit from the knowledge, practices or interventions that result from the research. [3, emphasis added]

In this revised Paragraph 20, there is a stern normative: the vulnerable group ‘should’ stand to benefit as opposed to a ‘reasonable likelihood’ of benefit in the previous versions (Table 2). This is a widely repercussive change. It affects all research participants.

Table 2.

Responsiveness and the Declaration of Helsinki 2000–2013.

2000 Note of clarification 2004 2008 2013
Medical research is only justified if there is a reasonable likelihood that the populations in which the research is carried out stand to benefit from the results of the research (para. 19) Medical research involving a disadvantaged or vulnerable population or community is only justified if research is responsive to the health needs and priorities of this population or community and if there is a reasonable likelihood that this population or community stands to benefit from the results of the research (para. 17) Medical research with a vulnerable group is only justified if the research is responsive to the health needs or priorities of this group and the research cannot be carried out in a non-vulnerable group. In addition, this group should stand to benefit from the knowledge, practices or interventions that result from the research (para. 20)
At the conclusion of the study, every patient entered into study should be assured of access to the best proven prophylactic, diagnostic and therapeutic methods identified in the study (para. 30) The WMA reaffirms its position that it is necessary during the study planning process to identify post-trial access by study participants to prophylactic, diagnostic and therapeutic procedures identified as beneficial in the study or access to appropriate care—. At the conclusion of the study, patients entered into the study are entitled to be informed about the outcome of the study and to share any benefits that result from it, for example, access to interventions identified as beneficial in the study or to other appropriate care or benefits (para. 33) In advance of a clinical trial, sponsors, researchers and host country governments should make provisions for post-trial access for all participants who still need an intervention identified as beneficial in the trial. This information must also be disclosed to participants during the informed consent process (para. 34) —All medical research subjects should be given the option of being informed about the general outcome and results of the of the study—(para. 26)
Post-trial access arrangements or other care must be described in the study protocol so that ethical review committee may consider such arrangements during its review The design and performance of each research study involving human subjects must be clearly described in a research protocol—. The protocol should describe arrangements for post-study access by study subjects to interventions identified as beneficial in the study or access to other appropriate care or benefits (para. 14) The design and performance of each research study involving human subjects must be clearly described and justified in a research protocol. —In clinical trials, the protocol must also describe appropriate arrangements for post-trial provisions (para. 22)

A key principle, embodied increasingly in successive iterations, is the ‘Responsiveness principle’ (Table 2). This demands that the trial should be relevant to the health needs of the local population (and participants should be selected fairly on the basis of their appropriateness to the research aims) and that the local population should benefit from the research. Whereas a narrow interpretation of benefits may be that the proven intervention is provided, a broader interpretation is that research benefits communities in other ways too, i.e. that post-trial benefits should not be limited to the provision of the proven intervention.8 Benefits might include collateral health services not related to the research study, improvements in health and healthcare, employment and economic activity, long-term research collaboration, capacity building, and the sharing of financial rewards from research results.11

Although the 2013 version endorses a broad conception of ‘benefits’, it will give rise to much discussion as to what ‘priorities’ may legitimately be considered. Power differentials between local physician-researchers and patient-participants, to the degree that the former may have unquestioned authority,1214 make it challenging to ascertain ‘fair benefits’ from patient-participants’ perspective. Priorities considered important by the physician-researchers should not trump health needs of patient-participants. This means that patients enrolled in the trial must be represented in the process of developing the plan for the allocation of ‘fair benefits’.

The requirement to be responsive to the ‘health needs or priorities’ rather than ‘health needs and priorities’ – that was present in the 2008 version (Table 2) – may compromise the responsiveness principle.

The new Paragraph 34: Post-trial provisions

Paragraph 34 of the 2013 version requires that:

In advance of a clinical trial, sponsors, researchers and host country governments should make provisions for post-trial access for all participants who still need an intervention identified as beneficial in the trial. [3, emphasis added]

This indicates a change from 2008 – where enrolled patients were ‘entitled’ to be informed, as opposed to the 2000 version where enrolled patients were ‘assured of access’ (Table 2). The new, sternly imperative ‘should’ is a significant endorsement of the responsiveness principle.

However, the phrase ‘access —to other appropriate care or benefits’, present in the 2008 version, is conspicuous by its absence from the new Paragraph 34 (Table 2). This is likely to lead to restrictive application of this requirement and may weaken the protection for participants, especially in low and middle income countries.15 Having said this, reading the new Paragraph 34 and Paragraph 20 together ought to effectively meet the requirement of ‘access— to other appropriate care or benefits’ through fulfilling the requirement: ‘this group should stand to benefit from the knowledge, practices or interventions that result from the research’ (para. 20). It is plainly important that participants are aware of their rights. Hence, the Declaration emphasises in Paragraphs 26 and 34 that information regarding post-trial provisions must be disclosed to participants during the consent process.3

The ethical principles underpinning the demands of Paragraphs 20 and 34 are justice and beneficence. In clinical trials, researchers gain a benefit by the acceptance of risk by patient-participants. Justice demands that, as a rule, there is compensation for the assumption of this risk, in the form of access to the proven intervention,16,17 and there is empirical evidence that patient-participants consider ensuring post-trial access to the trial drug a moral obligation.18,19

It is not enough to make a normative claim: the normative demands will be frustrated unless there is a viable pre-trial plan to ensure access to proven interventions. Tough contract negotiations are crucial. Collaboration is essential for a sustainable flow of the intervention.20 Ad hoc approaches are ineffective.

Conclusion

The motivating spirit of the Declaration is clear from Paragraphs 15 (about compensation), 33 (which frowns on placebos) and 20 (which enshrines the principle of distributive justice and evinces the concern, evident from the birth of the Declaration, with the protection of the vulnerable). Paragraph 34 is more problematic. We do not doubt its intentions: it intends to ensure ethical post-trial provision of benefits, and in deciding on the ruling ethics it relies on the principles of beneficence and distributive justice that have consistently motivated it. But Paragraph 34 is drafted rather strangely: it may be that its eccentricities will frustrate some of its good intentions.

The changes are real: they indicate a steady, incremental evolution towards a holistic code for the regulation of research on human participants. Patient autonomy, crucial though that is, is no longer the sole concern of the Declaration. There is now much more than a nod to distributive justice: the principle is, increasingly, a motivating force. The draftsmen have learned, and will no doubt continue to learn, about the practical problems of implementing philosophical abstracts in hot and poor places. The new version of Paragraph 33 indicates an awareness of those realities. While the Declaration is aware of the need to facilitate research, where that facilitation clashes with the need to protect the vulnerable, the vulnerable win. That has, often to the frustration of sponsors/researchers, been (with a few faltering moments) the case throughout the life of the Declaration. The new version seems to have even more resolve than its forebears.

Declarations

Competing interests

None declared

Funding

None declared

Ethical approval

Not applicable

Guarantor

AYM

Contributorship

AYM conceived the idea and wrote the first draft, tables and appendix. CF made substantial changes to the draft. Both AYM and CF contributed to the revisions and approved the final version.

Acknowledgements

The authors acknowledge the helpful comments by the reviewers to the submitted article.

Provenance

Not commissioned; peer-reviewed by Manuel Villarreal and Giridhara R Babu

References

  • 1.Emanuel EJ. Reconsidering the Declaration of Helsinki. Lancet 2013; 381: 1532–1533. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Williams JR. Revising the Declaration of Helsinki. World Med J 2008; 54: 120–122. [Google Scholar]
  • 3.WMA, World Medical Association. Declaration of Helsinki. J Am Med Assoc 2013; 227: 925–926. [Google Scholar]
  • 4.Macklin R. The Declaration Of Helsinki: another revision. Ind J Med Ethics 2009; VI: 2–4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Wolinsky H. The battle of Helsinki: two troublesome paragraphs in the Declaration of Helsinki are causing a furore over medical research ethics. Eur Mol Biol Org Rep 2006; 7: 670–672. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Dal-Ré R, Jha V, Lv J, et al. International trials in middle-income countries: different local scenarios require different ethical approaches. J R Soc Med 2016; 109: 47–51. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Ndebele P. The Declaration of Helsinki, 50 years later. JAMA 2013; 310: 2145–2146.. [DOI] [PubMed]
  • 8.Millum J, Wendler D and Emanuel EJ. The 50th anniversary of the Declaration of Helsinki: progress but many remaining challenges. JAMA 2013; 310: 2143–2144. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  • 9.Hurst SA. Declaration of Helsinki and protection for vulnerable research participants. JAMA 2014; 311: 1252–1252. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 10.Foster C, Malik AY. The elephant in the (board) room: the role of contract research organizations in international clinical research. Am J Bioeth 2012; 12: 49–50. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 11.Countries P.i.c.o.E.A.o.R.i.D.c. Fair benefits for research in developing countries. Science 2002; 298: 2133–2134. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 12.Munshi R, Thatte U. Compensation for research related injury. Perspect Clin Res 2013; 4: 61–69. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Malik AY. Physician-researchers’ experiences of the consent process in the sociocultural context of a developing country. AJOB Primary Res 2011; 2: 38–46. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Padela AI, Malik AY, Curlin F, et al. [Re]considering respect for persons in a globalizing world. Develop World Bioeth 2015; 15: 98–106. [DOI] [PubMed]
  • 15.Dal-Ré R, Ndebele P, Higgs E, et al. Protections for clinical trials in low and middle income countries need strengthening not weakening. BMJ 2014; 349: g4254–g4254. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 16.NBAC N.B.A.C. Ethical and Policy Issues in International Research: Clinical Trials in Developing Countries Volume II 2001, http://bioethics.georgetown.edu/nbac/clinical/Vol2.pdf (accessed 19 March 2016).
  • 17.EGE E.G.o.E.i.S.a.N.T. Ethical aspects of clinical research in developing countries, in opinion of the European group on ethics in science and new technologies to the European commission. Eur Group Ethics Sci New Technol 2003.
  • 18.Sofaer N, Thiessen C, Goold SD, et al. Subjects’ views of obligations to ensure post-trial access to drugs, care and information: qualitative results from the experiences of participants in clinical trials (EPIC) study. J Med Eth 2009; 35: 183–188. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Shaffer DN, Yebei VN, Ballidawa JB, et al. Equitable treatment for HIV/AIDS clinical trial participants: a focus group study of patients, clinician researchers, and administrators in western Kenya. J Med Ethics 2006; 32: 55–60. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Bhutta ZA. Ethics in international health research: a perspective from the developing world. Bull World Health Org 2002; 80: 114–120. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine are provided here courtesy of Royal Society of Medicine Press

RESOURCES