Skip to main content
Wiley Open Access Collection logoLink to Wiley Open Access Collection
. 2015 Nov 26;40(6):1435–1459. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12277

Is Passive Syntax Semantically Constrained? Evidence From Adult Grammaticality Judgment and Comprehension Studies

Ben Ambridge 1,, Amy Bidgood 1, Julian M Pine 1, Caroline F Rowland 1, Daniel Freudenthal 1
PMCID: PMC4996337  PMID: 26607289

Abstract

To explain the phenomenon that certain English verbs resist passivization (e.g., *£5 was cost by the book), Pinker (1989) proposed a semantic constraint on the passive in the adult grammar: The greater the extent to which a verb denotes an action where a patient is affected or acted upon, the greater the extent to which it is compatible with the passive. However, a number of comprehension and production priming studies have cast doubt upon this claim, finding no difference between highly affecting agent‐patient/theme‐experiencer passives (e.g., Wendy was kicked/frightened by Bob) and non‐actional experiencer theme passives (e.g., Wendy was heard by Bob). The present study provides evidence that a semantic constraint is psychologically real, and is readily observed when more fine‐grained independent and dependent measures are used (i.e., participant ratings of verb semantics, graded grammaticality judgments, and reaction time in a forced‐choice picture‐matching comprehension task). We conclude that a semantic constraint on the passive must be incorporated into accounts of the adult grammar.

Keywords: Child language acquisition, Passive, Verb, Semantics, Autonomy of syntax, Theme‐experiencer, Experiencer‐theme, Agent‐patient

1. Introduction

Language is a defining feature of human cognition. Thus the nature of the representations that underlie adult linguistic competence constitutes a central question in the cognitive sciences. Traditional approaches (e.g., Chomsky, 1993; Newmeyer, 2003) treat at least some of these representations as purely syntactic; context‐free rules or processes that are impervious to semantic content. Rival approaches (e.g., Goldberg, 1995; Pinker, 1989) emphasize the communicative nature of language. On this account, the fundamental representations underlying linguistic competence are inherently meaningful in nature. The goal of the present article is to pit these two positions against one another by means of an empirical investigation of the representation and processing of the English passive — an archetypal example of a phenomenon that is seen as reflecting either context‐free rules under the former account or a meaningful linguistic construction under the latter.

In English, as in many languages, the same event can (in most cases) be described by either an active sentence (1–3a) or an equivalent passive (1–3b).

1a. Wendy kicked Bob 1b. Bob was kicked by Wendy
2a. Wendy frightened Bob 2b. Bob was frightened by Wendy
3a. Wendy saw Bob 3b. Bob was seen by Wendy

But just how do speakers form a passive? Are the representations underlying passive formation purely (morpho‐)syntactic or subject to semantic constraints?

Arguing for the latter possibility, Pinker, Lebeaux, and Frost (1987: 249; see also Pinker, 1989) propose that passivization is restricted to verbs that denote actions or events such that

[B] (mapped onto the surface subject [of a passive]) is in a state or circumstance characterized by [A] (mapped onto the by‐object or an understood argument) having acted upon it.

As a shorthand, in subsequent discussion, we will refer to this constraint as the “affectedness” constraint. Pinker's primary motivation for this constraint appears to be the existence of a number of verbs for which the by‐object does not act upon or affect the surface subject, and which resist passivization altogether (4–5).

4a. The book cost £5 4b. *£5 was cost by the book
5a. This tent sleeps five people 5b. *Five people are slept by this tent

In contrast, most current psycholinguistic approaches treat the passive as a wholly syntactic phenomenon. This is particularly true for theories within the Chomskyan framework (e.g., Boeckx, 1998; Carnie, 2007; Collins, 2005), which eschews passive‐specific rules or processes altogether (Chomsky, 1993: 4):

Constructions such as…[the] passive remain only as taxonomic artifacts, collections of phenomena explained through the interaction of the principles of UG, with the values of the parameters fixed.

Pinker's semantic constraint approach would seem to predict a gradient, such that verbs that are highly consistent with this semantic characterization will be readily passivizable (1–2), with those that are less consistent resisting passivization to a lesser (3) or greater extent (4–5). A purely syntactic approach would seem to predict no such gradient (though completely unpassivizable verbs, e.g., 4–5, could be flagged as such in the lexicon).

At first glance, the findings of a number of forced‐choice comprehension studies appear to provide support for Pinker's approach (Fox & Grodzinsky, 1998; Gordon & Chafetz, 1990; Hirsch & Wexler, 2006; Horgan, 1978; Maratsos, Fox, Becker, & Chalkley, 1985; Meints, 1999; Sudhalter & Braine, 1985). When presented with a passive sentence (e.g., Bob was kicked by Wendy) and asked to select the matching picture (e.g., Wendy kicking Bob or Bob kicking Wendy), children generally show better performance for agent‐patient and theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., kick; frighten) than experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., hear).

On closer inspection, however, these comprehension findings constitute little support for Pinker's approach for two reasons. The first is that all of these studies were conducted with children. Thus the findings are consistent with the possibility that, while children may start out with a semantic passive construction prototype (perhaps based around a few relatively high‐frequency exemplars), adults have a wholly abstract representation, with semantics playing no role. The second, is that a more recent comprehension study found no support for this semantic constraint, for either children or adults (the two groups did not differ significantly). Messenger, Branigan, McLean, and Sorace (2012) replicated the familiar finding of better performance for passive sentences with agent‐patient verbs (bite, carry, hit, pat, pull, squash) and theme‐experiencer verbs (annoy, frighten, scare, shock, surprise, upset) than experiencer‐theme verbs (hear, ignore, like, love, remember, see), but—crucially—found the same pattern for active control sentences. This suggests that participants do not have difficulty with experiencer‐theme PASSIVES, but with experiencer‐theme VERBS. Presumably this difficulty arises because experiencer‐theme verbs reverse the canonical role assignment exemplified by agent‐patient and theme‐experiencer verbs (see Hartshorne, Pogue, & Snedeker, 2015; Hartshorne & Snedeker, 2013; Hartshorne et al., submitted), and are also more difficult to illustrate and interpret in a picture‐matching task. Note that none of the previous comprehension studies reviewed above included these crucial active control sentences. Thus, in summary, the findings of previous comprehension studies do not provide support for Pinker's putative semantic constraint on the English passive.

A similar conclusion can be drawn with regard to structural priming studies, the findings of which would seem to be more consistent with approaches that treat the passive as a purely syntactic phenomenon. Many adult studies (see Pickering & Ferreira, 2008; for a review) have shown that hearing a passive sentence increases the likelihood of subsequently producing a passive sentence, regardless of the particular verb used (and regardless of its consistency with Pinker's proposed semantic constraint). This effect holds when the verbs (and other material) of the prime and target sentences are semantically unrelated (Bock, 1986; Estival, 1985), and even when the two sentences are from different languages (Hartsuiker, Pickering, & Veltkamp, 2004). Various follow‐up studies have ruled out non‐syntactic explanations based on the re‐use of lexical material (Saffran & Martin, 1997), priming of syntactic roles (Bock & Loebell, 1990; Potter & Lombardi, 1998), animacy (Bock, Loebell, & Morey, 1992) and prosodic contours (Bock & Loebell, 1990). Similar effects have also been observed for children (Bencini & Valian, 2008; Crain & Fodor, 1993; Huttenlocher, Vasilyeva, & Shimpi, 2004; Messenger, Branigan, & McLean, 2011; Savage, Lieven, Theakston, & Tomasello, 2003, 2006).

Indeed, in addition to the comprehension study discussed above, Messenger et al. (2012) also conducted a syntactic priming study that looked specifically at the issue of by‐verb semantic differences. For neither adults nor children (again, the two groups did not differ significantly) did agent‐patient verbs (e.g., kick), theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., frighten) or experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., see) differ in their propensity to prime the production of passive sentences (all with agent‐patient verbs), even though these three classes differ along Pinker's affectedness gradient (from greatest to least).

Thus, at present, the available experimental data constitute no evidence for—and perhaps even direct evidence against—Pinker's affectedness constraint on the passive in the adult grammar. We suggest, however, that three features of previous studies may have worked against the possibility of observing such an effect.

The first is that these studies used a relatively coarse measure of verb semantics: a categorical division into agent‐patient, theme‐experiencer and experiencer‐theme verbs. It may be that this measure is insufficiently fine‐grained to capture the relevant by‐verb semantic difficulties. The present studies address this possibility by using instead composite ratings of 10 semantic properties chosen to capture in detail the nature of the putative semantic constraint.

The second is that these studies used online measures (forced‐choice comprehension and production priming) that monitor the language system as it processes language in real time. Such measures might miss a fine‐grained probabilistic semantic constraint, because minor semantic infelicities are relatively unimportant, provided that they do not interfere with the system's ability to arrive at a parse that is “good enough” (in the sense of Ferreira, Bailey, & Ferraro, 2002). It may be that an offline judgment task is more suited to detecting very subtle instances of infelicity, such as passives that violate a semantic constraint. Indeed, many sentences that are rated as ungrammatical in judgment tasks (e.g., *The key to the cabinets are missing) frequently pass unnoticed in online tasks (Bock & Miller, 1991; Clifton, Frazier, & Deevy, 1999; Pearlmutter, Garnsey, & Bock, 1999; see Lewis & Phillips, 2015).

Further suggestive evidence for this possibility comes from a study of fully grammatical but implausible passives (Ferreira, 2003). On around 25% of trials, participants incorrectly interpreted implausible passives (e.g., The dog was bitten by the man) by reversing the roles (e.g., as “The man was bitten by the dog”). Again, the processing mechanism arrives at a plausible interpretation, sometimes bypassing a full parse altogether, and so misses violations (here, of plausibility rather than syntactic or semantic constraints) that are (presumably) readily noticed in an offline judgment task. The present studies address this possibility by using both a time‐sensitive online comprehension measure and an offline graded judgment measure, with the same stimuli.

The use of these dependent measures also addresses a third feature of previous studies that may have worked against the possibility of observing fine‐grained by‐verb semantic differences on passivizability. Both forced‐choice comprehension and production priming yield a binary dependent measure: On each trial, a passive sentence is either comprehended/produced or it is not, there is no half‐way house. Thus even a passive that violates a semantic constraint may be sufficient to tip the scales in favor of the correct picture in a comprehension task, and of the passive construction (as opposed to the active) in a priming task. Indeed, given that even highly ungrammatical sentences (e.g., *Me fell over; *Lisa poured the rug with juice; *£5 was cost by the book) are often readily interpretable, it would be surprising if much more minor infelicities (e.g., ?Bob was seen by Wendy) interfered with adults' ability to select the matching picture in a comprehension study, or to show syntactic priming in a production study. The present studies address this possibility by using continuous dependent measures: a 5‐point scale in the grammaticality judgment task and a reaction time measure in the forced‐choice comprehension task.

In summary, while previous studies do not provide support for the existence of a semantic affectedness constraint on the English passive, it would seem premature to reject this possibility without first addressing some of the features of previous studies that may count against the possibility of observing such an effect. We begin (Study 1) by obtaining a fine‐grained measure of the proposed semantic constraint: adult ratings of the extent to which a large number of verbs (= 475, chosen to represent all of the relevant verb types listed by Pinker, 1989; and Levin, 1993), exhibit each of 10 semantic properties pertaining to “affectedness” (Pinker, 1989; Pinker et al., 1987). Following a similar logic to Messenger et al. (2012)—that is, using active sentences as a control—we then investigate whether the resulting composite semantics measure is a better predictor of the relative acceptability of each of these verbs in the passive than the active construction (Study 2). Next, we investigate whether the pattern of findings observed across all 475 verbs (some of which cannot be grammatically passivized at all) holds when looking only at a core set of 72 verbs that are (in a binary sense) all passivizable. Finally, we use the same set of 72 verbs to investigate whether the composite semantics measure is a better predictor of performance with passive than active sentences in a time‐sensitive forced‐choice animated picture‐matching task. Because the aim is to investigate the nature of passive representations in the adult grammar, all studies are conducted with native‐speaking adults (unlike most studies in this domain, which generally focus on children).

2. Study 1: Semantic feature ratings

The aim of this study was simply to derive a composite verb‐by‐verb measure of semantic “affectedness” for use in the subsequent studies.

2.1. Participants

Participants were 16 native‐speaking adults (university students) who did not take part in any of the other studies. Participants were paid £50 for completing the semantic rating task.

2.2. Verbs

We first selected an extended set of 475 verbs (for use in Experiment 2), by consulting lists of passivizable and non‐passivizable verbs given in Pinker et al. (1987: 250–6) and Levin (1993), making sure that we included all the verbs used in the previous studies of Sudhalter and Braine (1985), Maratsos et al. (1985), Gordon and Chafetz (1990) and Messenger et al. (2012). (This latter constraint entailed including particle verbs such as cheer up, partly against our better judgment, given that the syntactic status of these verbs is not entirely clear.) The verbs (see Data S1) were chosen to ensure a good spread along the continuum of “completely passivizable” to “completely non‐passivizable” verbs. A subset of 72 verbs—24 agent‐patient, 24 theme‐experiencer and 24 experiencer‐theme (including all the verbs used by Messenger et al., 2012)—were designated the core set, for use in Experiments 3–4:

  1. agent‐patient: avoid, bite, call, carry, chase, cut, dress, drop, eat, follow, help, hit, hold, hug, kick, kiss, lead, pat, pull, push, shake, squash, teach, wash.

  2. theme‐experiencer: amaze, amuse, anger, annoy, bother, calm, cheer up, disgust, distract, disturb, entertain, frighten, impress, irritate, please, sadden, scare, shock, startle, surprise, tease, terrify, upset, worry.

  3. experiencer‐theme: admire, believe, dislike, fear, forget, hate, hear, ignore, know, like, listen to, look at, love, miss, notice, overhear, recognize, remember, see, smell, spot, trust, understand, watch.

These verbs were selected to be passivizable, reversible and relatively easy to illustrate in animations (again, the decision to match the stimuli from previous studies necessitated the inclusion of three particle verbs—cheer up, listen to, and look at—which, ideally, we would have preferred to avoid).

2.3. Semantic ratings

Raters were given the following instructions: “On the following sheet is a list of 475 verbs. Each describes an event involving two people (or things, ideas, etc.), denoted by A and B. For example, if the verb is damage, the event would be A damaged B. Each column lists a statement. Your task is to rate the extent to which each statement is appropriate for each verb, on a scale of 1–9.” The statements rated corresponded to a set of 10 semantic properties listed by Pinker (1989) as characteristic of the passive construction (on the basis of previous work in theoretical linguistics):

(a) A causes (or is responsible for) some effect/change involving B, (b) A enables or allows the change/event, (c) A is doing something to B, (d) A is responsible, (e) A makes physical contact with B, (f) B changes state or circumstances, (g) B is responsible [predicted to have a negative relationship with passivizability], (h) It would be possible for A to deliberately [VERB] B, (i) The event affects B in some way, (j) The action adversely (negatively) affects B.

Note that these raters did not encounter any passive sentences, or any mention of passives, throughout the rating task. Thus it is extremely unlikely that they would have spontaneously adopted a strategy of using passivizability as a criterion for any of these semantic feature ratings.

For each verb, the mean rating across all 10 raters was taken as the score for the relevant semantic feature. Principle Components Analysis (PCA) was used to reduce these 10 semantic predictor variables to a composite measure of (putative) passive‐consistent semantics. PCA works by collapsing across questionnaire statements to which participants showed a similar pattern of responses across items (here, verbs).

2.4. Results

The factor loadings are shown in Table 1, 1.

Table 1.

Original semantic feature measures and derived predictor (A affects B)

Original Feature Rated Semantic Predictor A Affects B
A causes (or is responsible for) some effect/change involving B 0.916
A enables or allows the change/event 0.762
A is doing something to B 0.874
A is responsible 0.635
A makes physical contact with B 0.714
B changes state or circumstances 0.903
B is responsible −0.320
It would be possible for A to deliberately [VERB] B 0.642
The event affects B in some way 0.893
The action adversely (negatively) affects B 0.720
Eigenvalue 5.74
% variance explained 57.4

All but one of the 10 original semantic features (“B is responsible,” −0.32) had a large positive loading (≥ 0.64) on a single composite predictor, which we named A affects B. This composite predictor accounted for 57% of by‐verb variance; that is, for the variance explained by around 6 of the original 10 predictors (Eigenvalue = 5.74). According to Pinker's proposed affectedness constraint, this variable is predicted to have a positive relationship with passivizability in the subsequent studies (recall that “B” denotes the patient, the subject of the passive). Two further components explained a much smaller amount of additional variance (12% and 10% respectively) and so were not retained.

Fig. 1 shows the values of each verb on the derived composite semantic predictor (note that the values on the X axis are arbitrary). It is clear that while all of the verbs with very high affectedness scores are agent‐patient verbs (and all denote acts of violence; slay, assassinate, kill, stab, strangle, murder, suffocate), a number of theme‐experiencer verbs (frighten, terrorize, scare, terrify) are not far behind, and indeed score higher on this measure than the majority of agent‐patient verbs. While this makes intuitive sense—theme‐experiencer verbs, by definition, describe an event in which the patient is affected—it suggests that a categorical division between agent‐patient and theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., Messenger et al., 2012) is unlikely to be able to capture the types of gradient semantic effects predicted by Pinker's account. In contrast, experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., fear, hear, see and like) are so non‐affecting that they are intermingled with non‐passivizable verbs such as cost, sleep, fit and total). Thus to the extent that a categorical division can capture the semantic differences between passivizable verbs (which is not a great extent), the appropriate division is between agent‐patient + theme‐experiencer verbs on the one hand and experiencer‐theme verbs on the other. In particular, note that the distinction between “actional” (i.e., agent‐patient) and “psychological” or “mental state” verbs (theme‐experiencer + experiencer‐theme)—e.g., Maratsos et al. (1985)—is a red herring: theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., frighten) are semantically more akin to agent‐patient verbs (e.g., kick) than to experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., hear).

Figure 1.

Figure 1

Mean semantic ratings for all 475 verbs. Higher values on the Y axis indicate higher ratings of “affectedness” (i.e., of putative passive‐consistent semantics). The distribution of verbs along the X axis is arbitrary.

Having established that, as we speculated in the introduction, a coarse distinction between agent‐patient, theme‐experiencer and experiencer‐theme verbs is not sufficient to characterize Pinker's proposed “affectedness” constraint on the passive, we now proceed to our main question of interest: whether a fine‐grained, continuous measure of affectedness can predict the relative passivizability of verbs in judgment tasks (Studies 2–3) and a comprehension task (Study 4).

3. Study 2: Grammaticality judgments (475 verbs)

The aim of this study was to test the prediction that the composite semantic affectedness predictor (see Study 1) will be a better predictor of the by‐verb pattern of acceptability in the passive than the active construction (indicated by an interaction of semantics by sentence type). Recall that we would still expect the measure of affectedness to predict some variance in judgments for actives, given that many of the verbs that score low for affectedness (i.e., experiencer‐theme verbs such as hear, ignore, like, love, remember, see) reverse the canonical role assignment exemplified by agent‐patient and theme‐experiencer verbs, even in active sentences.

3.1. Method

3.1.1. Participants

Participants were 20 adults recruited from the same population as Study 1. None took part in any of the other studies, and each received £20 for their participation.

3.2. Materials and procedure

For each of the 475 verbs in the extended set, we created a spreadsheet‐based grammaticality judgment questionnaire containing one active and one passive sentence with the same NPs (e.g., Homer amused Marge; Marge was amused by Homer). We then created a second version of the questionnaire by reversing all reversible passives (e.g., Marge amused Homer; Homer was amused by Marge) (unlike in the subsequent studies, not all verbs were reversible). We then repeated the entire procedure to create third and fourth versions of the questionnaire with different NPs (e.g., Bob amused Wendy; Wendy was amused by Bob; Wendy amused Bob; Bob was amused by Wendy). Participants were randomly allocated to one of the four questionnaires. Within each questionnaire, the order of sentences was randomized on a participant‐by‐participant basis. Participants rated the acceptability of sentences using a 5‐point numerical Likert scale, and were given the following instructions.

In this study, you will rate 950 sentences for grammatical acceptability.

For each sentence, enter a whole number between 1 (completely unacceptable) and 5 (completely acceptable). People tend to differ in their judgments of how acceptable sentences are. Therefore this should not be considered a “test” of your grammar. Acceptability is a sliding scale and not a yes/no judgment. It is therefore very important that you try to use the WHOLE of the scale—do NOT just put 1 or 5 for every answer.

Before completing the task, participants completed a training phase consisting of five sentences: one fully acceptable, one fully unacceptable, and three in between (i.e., that typically receive ratings of 2/5, 3/5 and 4/5 in adult studies); see Ambridge, Pine, Rowland, and Young (2008) for details.

3.2.1. Frequency counts

When estimating the influence of a verb's semantic properties on its passivizability, it is important to control for overall verb frequency, on the assumption that participants will show better general task performance for more frequent verbs. It is also important to control for verb frequency in the passive construction. Otherwise, we have no way of knowing whether participants show better processing and/or greater acceptance of passive uses of a particular verb because (a) it is consistent with a semantic constraint on the passive or (b) that particular verb simply happens to have occurred frequently in the passive for unrelated reasons (e.g., a pragmatic bias makes passives particularly frequent for verbs such as sting, bite and run‐over, where humans tend to be the patient, but discourse‐focal). Of course, if there are indeed by‐verb semantic differences in passivizability, one would expect these differences to be reflected to some degree in passive frequency counts (i.e., that semantically passivizable verbs will appear in passive constructions more often). Thus, when looking for by‐verb semantic differences in passivizability, controlling for frequency in the passive constitutes a particularly stringent and conservative control.

Counts of overall and passive frequency were obtained from the British National Corpus (BNC). Passive counts were obtained using a computer program (written by the final author) that searched the corpus for candidate passive sentences. For each verb, the second author hand‐coded 20 candidate passives in order to obtain a by‐verb hit rate that was prorated to yield the final passive count for that verb. All counts were log (+ 1) transformed. Although the BNC includes both written (80%) and spoken texts, this does not constitute a problem, on the assumption that the grammar of literate adult speakers is affected by language encountered in either form.

3.3. Results and discussion (Experiment 2)

Many grammaticality judgment studies use difference‐score data, which, in this case, would be calculated by subtracting the rating for each passive sentence from the rating for its active equivalent (e.g., Pinker et al., 1987). However, such a measure would not be appropriate in the present study, given that our goal is to investigate whether the semantic predictor has differential effects on ratings of active and passive sentences. We therefore analyzed the raw ratings for active and passive sentences together including sentence type and its interactions as a factor.

All analyses—for this and subsequent studies—consisted of linear mixed effects regression models, calculated using the lmer function of the lme4 package in R (R Core Team, 2012). Participant and verb were included as random effects. Each model included as many by‐participant random slopes as possible without causing convergence failure (by‐verb random slopes are not meaningful given the design). All models included the following predictor variables, which were standardized using a z‐score transformation: (a) Overall verb frequency, (b) Verb frequency in the passive construction, (c) Semantic feature measure: A affects B. In accordance with the recommendations of a recent paper (Wurm & Fisicaro, 2014), we used simultaneous regression models with no residualization. P values were obtained using the backwards model‐comparison procedure, performed automatically using the step feature from the lmerTest package (Kuznetsova, Brockhoff & Christensen, 2013). The analysis is summarized in Table 2. Figs. 2a and 2b plot acceptability judgments on the 5‐point scale, for actives and passives respectively, as a function of the semantic predictor (A affects B).

Table 2.

Experiment 1: Grammaticality judgments for 475 verbs in active and passive sentences

B SE t Sum Sq Mean Sq F p
(Intercept) 4.73 0.08 58.09
Sentence type (P vs. A) −0.65 0.01 −60.65 1,981.61 1,981.61 3,678.94 .000***
Total verb freq 0.06 0.02 2.63 0.85 0.85 7.10 .008**
Passive verb freq 0.03 0.02 1.11 21.06 21.06 45.89 .000***
Semantics 0.08 0.02 3.65 41.95 41.95 77.14 .000***
Stype × Total verb freq −0.24 0.01 −17.30 67.33 67.33 299.23 .000***
Stype × Pass verb freq 0.27 0.01 19.68 303.57 303.57 387.33 .000***
Stype × Semantics 0.22 0.01 19.10 198.29 198.29 364.65 .000***

Note. *p < 0.05, **p < 0.01, ***p < 0.001.

Figure 2.

Figure 2

Mean grammaticality judgment score for (a) actives and (b) passives as a function of the semantic predictor (475 verbs; Study 2).

All main effects were significant, indicating that grammatical acceptability increases with sentence type (passive < active), total verb frequency, passive verb frequency and semantic affectedness. The interactions indicate that (a) total verb frequency has a greater effect for actives than passives, while both (b) passive verb frequency and—crucially— (c) semantic affectedness have a greater effect for passives than actives (see Fig. 2).

Thus while there is some evidence to suggest a general dispreference for verbs that reverse canonical marking, even for active sentences (e.g., Messenger et al., 2012), the finding of a significant interaction, such that the by‐verb effect of passive‐consistent semantics is greater for passive than active sentences, constitutes support for Pinker's proposed semantic constraint on the passive.

4. Study 3: Grammaticality judgments (core set of 72 passivizable verbs)

A possible objection to the conclusion above is that the semantic effect observed could be driven mainly or entirely by the non‐passivizable verbs (e.g., cost, weigh) which constitute clear outliers (see Fig. 2). On this interpretation, all that our “semantic” predictor is doing is picking out verbs that are non‐passivizable, perhaps even for syntactic reasons. For example, Newmeyer (2015: 22) argues that “Passives [such as] *A lot of money was cost by the book and *180 pounds was weighed by John are impossible because the post‐verbal phrases are not arguments of the verb. The “prototypicality” of the verb does not enter directly into the explanation” (scare quotes in original). One way to rule out this objection would be to show that the verb semantics measure predicts the relative acceptability of passives—to a greater extent than actives—even when looking across a set of passivizable verbs.

4.1. Method

4.1.1. Participants

Participants were 16 adults recruited from the same population as Studies 1 and 2. None took part in any of the other studies, and each received either course credit or £10 for their participation.

4.1.2. Stimuli

This study used the core set of 72 verbs (see Study 1): 24 agent‐patient verbs (e.g., bite, carry, hit, pat, pull, squash), 24 theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., annoy, frighten, scare, shock, surprise, upset) and 24 experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., hear, ignore, like, love, remember, see). Importantly, all of these verbs are passivizable in a binary sense, with even the least acceptable passive (with believe) receiving a mean rating of 3.5/5. Syntactically, all verbs clearly select two argument NPs (c.f., Newmeyer, 2015). For each verb, we created two active and two passive sentences with the same NPs (e.g., Homer amused Marge, Marge was amused by Homer; Marge amused Homer, Homer was amused by Marge) and suitable animations (e.g., Homer causing Marge to laugh and vice versa). Participants rated a single active‐passive sentence pair, matched for participant roles, for all 72 verbs (e.g., half rated Homer amused Marge and Marge was amused by Homer; half rated Marge amused Homer and Homer was amused by Marge), for a total of 144 trials per participant. The full set of verbs (S1) and animations (S2) can be found in the Supplementary Material available online.

4.1.2. Procedure

The sentences and accompanying animations were presented in random order (different for each participant), using iTunes (www.apple.com/itunes). Participants supplied their ratings using a 5‐point “smiley‐face” scale, originally designed for use with children (see Ambridge et al., 2008, for details). The scale consists of a color‐coded horizontal array of five faces, ranging from saddest (ungrammatical) to happiest. The two saddest faces are red, the two happiest green, and the middle face half red, half green. Participants marked their answers in a booklet containing 144 copies of the scale. The same practice trials as for Study 2 were used to demonstrate the use of the scale.

4.2. Results

The data were analyzed in the same way as for Study 2, and showed exactly the same pattern (see Table 3 and Fig. 3).

Table 3.

Experiment 3 grammaticality judgments for 72 verbs in active and passive sentences

Judgments: Core Set (72 Verbs)
B SE t Sum Sq Mean Sq F p
(Intercept) 4.78 0.07 71.46
Sentence type (P vs A) −0.41 0.02 −17.53 135.63 135.63 307.28 .000***
Total verb freq 0.03 0.03 0.78 0.80 0.80 6.87 .011*
Passive verb freq 0.03 0.03 0.79 5.86 5.86 14.70 .000***
Semantics 0.01 0.03 0.55 1.96 1.96 5.68 .021*
Stype × Total verb freq −0.21 0.03 −6.70 14.31 14.31 44.86 .000***
Stype × Pass verb freq 0.16 0.03 5.62 13.28 13.28 31.59 .000***
Stype × semantics 0.08 0.02 4.05 5.67 5.67 16.39 .000***

Note. *p < 0.05, **p < 0.01, ***p < 0.001.

Figure 3.

Figure 3

Mean grammaticality judgment score for (a) actives and (b) passives as a function of the semantic predictor (72 passivizable verbs; Study 3).

All main effects were significant, indicating that grammatical acceptability increases with sentence type (passive < active), total verb frequency, passive verb frequency and semantic affectedness. The interactions indicate that (a) total verb frequency has a greater effect for actives than passives, while both (b) passive verb frequency and—crucially— (c) semantic affectedness have a greater effect for passives than actives (see Fig. 3).

Thus, exactly as for Study 2, the finding of a significant interaction, such that the by‐verb effect of passive‐consistent semantics is greater for passive than active sentences, constitutes support for Pinker's proposed semantic constraint on the passive. Crucially, since all verbs were passivizable, and all NPs were syntactic arguments of the verb, this finding cannot be due to a confound introduced by the use of non‐passivizable verbs for which the (would be) passive subject is not an argument of the verb (Newmeyer, 2015).

5. Study 4: Forced‐choice comprehension with RT measure (core set of 72 passivizable verbs)

The findings of Studies 2–3 constitute support for the claim of a probabilistic semantic constraint on the passive construction in the adult grammar. This raises the issue of why the forced‐choice comprehension study of Messenger et al. (2012) failed to find such an effect for adults (or children). Are “fast” online measures inherently unsuited to detecting such subtle effects, or could other features of the design of this previous study—in particular the categorical nature of both the semantic predictor variable and the binary (correct/incorrect) outcome variable—be responsible?

In order to investigate this issue, we conducted a timed forced‐choice animated picture‐matching study. On each trial, the participant heard a sentence (e.g., Marge was amused by Homer) and was asked to indicate, as quickly as possible, whether the description matched the animation on the left‐ or right‐hand side of the screen (e.g., Marge amusing Homer / Homer amusing Marge), by pressing one of two computer keys aligned with the left‐ and right‐hand sides of the screen, respectively.

5.1. Method

5.1.1. Participants

Participants were 16 adults recruited from the same population as Studies 1–3. None took part in any of the other studies, and each received either course credit or £10 for their participation.

5.1.2. Stimuli

The sentences and animations were the same as those used in Study 3 (based on the core set of 72 passivizable verbs). Participants completed one active and one passive trial for each of 36 verbs (half of the total), for a total of 72 trials per participant. Testing was carried out over 2 days. For half of the verbs, participants heard the passive sentence on Day 1 and the active sentence on Day 2, with this pattern reversed for the other half (the two batches were created at random on a participant‐by‐participant basis). Trials were counterbalanced for (a) whether the target was on the left‐ or right‐hand side for the active trial, (b) whether the target for the passive trial was on the same or opposite side to the target for the active trial with the same verb and (c) whether the participant roles were the same for the active and passive sentence for each verb (e.g., Homer amused Marge / Marge was amused by Homer) or different (e.g., Homer amused Marge / Homer was amused by Marge). The direction in which the action unfolded was not counterbalanced but standardized: right‐to‐left in the left‐hand video and left‐to‐right in the right‐hand video. In order to further aid disambiguation, the left‐ and right‐hand videos had beige and white backgrounds, respectively, and the left‐hand video was slightly higher on the screen.

5.1.3. Procedure

Trials were presented in random order (different for each participant) using the software package Processing. The procedure for each trial was as follows. First the participant placed one finger of each hand on the response keys. Next, the animations were previewed; first the left‐hand animation, accompanied by the audio “Look at these two. I wonder what's happening here,” then the right‐hand animation, accompanied by the audio “Oh look! Now it's the other way around.” Then both animations played together, with the movements of the two agents and two patients synchronized.

When the animations ended, freeze‐frames of the end‐point of the animations remained on screen. The animations were designed such that these freeze‐frames alone, in principle, provided sufficient information to allow participants to choose the correct referent for the audio, even without the animation. For example, where the motion of one character is key (e.g., Marge avoided Homer) an arrow indicating the direction of the now‐completed motion remained on screen. The intention was to ensure that the task had all the advantages of a standard still‐picture‐matching task, while using animations to provide additional information.

Once the freeze frame picture was on screen, sentence playback began. The audio recordings were standardized so that the disambiguation point (the onset of the main verb) always occurred exactly 7 s after the start of the target animations. At the disambiguation point, the timer started and ran until the participant pressed either the left‐ or right‐hand key. When the key was pressed, a cartoon hand appeared on screen to indicate the participant's choice (any further presses were not recorded). The screen then went blank, ready for the participant to initiate the next trial.

5.2. Results

The dependent measure was participants' reaction time, excluding any trials with RTs > 10 s and/or incorrect responses (although, in practice, the majority of participants performed at ceiling for both actives and passives). Because mean RTs for the passives and actives might be expected to differ, with longer RTs for passives, we standardized the RTs into z‐scores for passives and actives separately. This ensures that any larger effect for passives than actives is not a simple consequence of the fact that it is easier to take a fixed amount (e.g., 500 ms) off a longer than shorter reaction time. The data were analyzed in the same way as for Studies 2–3 (see Table 4 and Fig. 4).

Table 4.

RT for correct picture‐choices for 72 verbs in active and passive sentences

B SE t Sum Sq Mean Sq F p sig
(Intercept) −0.09 0.17 −0.56
Sentence type (P vs A) 0.01 0.04 0.20 0.01 0.01 0.04 .839 n.s
Total verb freq −0.08 0.04 −2.19 0.03 0.03 1.50 .228 n.s
Semantics −0.11 0.04 −2.67 10.49 10.49 22.00 .000 ***
Stype × Total verb freq 0.09 0.04 2.06 4.53 4.53 4.25 .040 *
Stype × Semantics −0.10 0.04 −2.25 2.45 2.45 5.04 .025 *
Eliminated
Stype × Pass verb freq NA 0.00 0.00 0.08 .775 n.s
Passive verb freq NA 1.31 1.31 2.54 .117 n.s

Notes. n.s = not significant.

*p < 0.05, **p < 0.01, ***p < 0.001.

Figure 4.

Figure 4

Mean reaction time for (a) actives and (b) passives as a function of the semantic predictor (72 passivizable verbs; Study 3).

Focusing first on the control predictors, both the main effect of passive verb frequency and its interaction with sentence type were non‐significant, and so were eliminated by the backwards model‐comparison procedure. The main effects of sentence type and total verb frequency were also non‐significant, but were not eliminated, due to their involvement in significant interactions. The significant interaction of sentence type by total verb frequency indicates that verb frequency has a greater effect on speeding up reaction times for active than passive sentences.

Turning now to the findings of interest, the main effect of semantics was significant, indicating that—for active and passive sentences alike—reaction time decreases as semantic affectedness increases. Thus again, the findings are indicative of a general dispreference for verbs that reverse canonical marking (i.e., experiencer‐theme verbs), even for active sentences (e.g., Messenger et al., 2012; Hartshorne & Snedeker, 2013; Hartshorne et al., in press; Hartshorne, O'Donnell, Sudo, Uruwashi & Snedeker, submitted). Crucially, however, the significant interaction of the semantic predictor by sentence type indicates that affectedness has a greater effect on speeding up reaction times for passive than active sentences.

Thus, exactly as for Studies 2–3, the finding of a significant interaction, such that the by‐verb effect of passive‐consistent semantics is greater for passive than active sentences (even when all passives are grammatical), constitutes support for Pinker's proposed semantic constraint on the passive. This finding suggests that the previous null finding of Messenger et al. (2012) could be due to the use of an insufficiently sensitive semantic measure (i.e., verb class) and/or dependent measure (i.e., correct/incorrect picture choice).

6. General discussion

The aim of the present study was to investigate the psychological reality of a semantic constraint on the passive in the adult grammar, originally proposed by Pinker et al. (1987; see also Pinker, 1989). This “affectedness” constraint was posited to explain the phenomenon that certain verbs appear to resist passivization altogether (e.g., *£5 was cost by the book). However, the findings of several previous comprehension and production priming studies cast doubt on the existence of this constraint: Passives with experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., see), which score low for affectedness, did not differ from either agent‐patient (e.g., kick) or theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., frighten) in their propensity to prime the production of passive sentences, and—relative to actives—did not show any particular decrement in picture‐choice tasks.

The present study investigated whether these null effects could result in part from the paradigms used in these previous studies. These involved (a) a categorical measure of verb semantics (agent‐patient / theme‐experiencer / experiencer‐theme verbs), (b) a “fast” online task (comprehension or production priming) and (c) a binary outcome variable (passive comprehended/produced or not). In contrast, the present study used (a) a graded measure of verb semantics (semantic ratings from adult native speakers), (b) a “slow” offline judgment task, as well as a “fast” online comprehension task and (c) graded outcome variables (grammatical acceptability on a 5‐point scale / comprehension reaction time).

With these modifications in place, all three studies—(a) grammaticality judgments with 475 verbs, (b) grammaticality judgments with 72 passivizable verbs and (c) forced‐choice animated picture matching with the same 72 verbs—found evidence for Pinker's proposed semantic constraint on the passive. Although, in each study, the semantic measure predicted performance across both actives and passives (presumably because experiencer‐theme verbs, which reverse canonical marking, are just difficult in general), a significant interaction was observed, such that the facilitatory effect of passive‐consistent semantics (“affectedness”) was greater for passive than active sentences.

The conclusion is that Pinker's semantic constraint on the passive (or something very like it) is psychologically real, and must therefore be incorporated into any account of the underlying adult grammar. This does not necessarily require us to adopt any one theoretical standpoint with regard to the nature of this grammar. For example, the semantic constraint could be implemented as a graded constraint on a lexical non‐movement rule relating actives and passives, as in frameworks such as Lexical Functional Grammar or Head Driven Phrase Structure Grammar (Bresnan, 2001; Pinker, 1989; Pollard & Sag, 1994).

Alternatively, under construction grammar approaches (e.g., Croft, 2001; Goldberg, 1995; Goldberg & Bencini, 2005), the semantic constraint could be implemented at the construction level, whereby the passive construction itself (or its verb slot) has the relevant semantic properties, which the learner acquires by abstracting across concrete utterances that instantiate these properties. An advantage of this approach is that it brings the passive into line with the findings of our recent research on other constructions such as the locative (Ambridge, Pine, & Rowland, 2012), dative (Ambridge, Pine, Rowland, Freudenthal, & Chang, 2014) and reversative un‐ prefixation (Ambridge, 2013; Blything, Ambridge, & Lieven, 2014). Indeed, while maintaining that “lexical rules are needed, and…meaning‐to‐construction mappings are not enough,” Pinker (2013: xv) himself notes that

the analyses in Learnability and Cognition (Pinker, 1989)…are upward compatible with [both] current versions of…Lexical Functional Grammar…and the various versions of Construction Grammar, such as those developed by Ronald Langacker, Adele Goldberg and William Croft. Indeed, my notion of the “thematic core” of an argument structure, which delineates the “conflation class” of verbs compatible with that argument structure [apparently including the passive—BA], is very close to the idea of a “construction meaning” invoked by theories of construction grammar.

Thus the idea of a semantic constraint on the passive—one that is strongly supported by the findings of the present study—is compatible with a variety of different approaches to the adult grammar. One possible exception is more traditional approaches such as Chomskyan X‐bar theory and its descendents (e.g., Minimalism; Chomsky, 1995). The existence of a semantic constraint on the passive is not necessarily incompatible with these approaches. However, the challenge would be to find a way of incorporating some index of relative passivizability in the verb's lexical entry, given that the framework eschews both constructions in general (which Chomsky, 1989:43; dismisses as “taxonomic epiphenomena”), and any passive‐specific construction, rule or process in particular (see quotation from Chomsky, 1993:4; in the Introduction). One possibility might be to posit that underlying passivizability (in a binary sense) is a core grammatical feature listed in a verb's lexical entry, but that the ease of applying this procedure in real time depends on the extent to which the verb's semantics are typical of those that are often used in the passive (or, as Newmeyer, 2003, puts it “grammar is grammar, and usage is usage”). The counterargument is that if one can derive the present results from a unitary process—i.e., compatibility with a semantic construction prototype—it seems unparsimonious to posit a two‐level (i.e., grammar + usage) account.

An assumption that has been implicit thus far is that what determines a verb's passivizability is its lexical meaning (in a kind of fixed dictionary‐definition sense). An alternative possibility that is also consistent with the present findings is that the acceptability of a passive is instead determined by the semantics of the event: a passive is grammatical to the extent that the event is construed as one in which the surface subject is affected (indeed, the instructions given were deliberately ambiguous as to whether participants were rating the semantics of the verb per se, or the types of event typically denoted by that verb). This alternative is appealing, as it captures the intuition that the grammaticality of a sentence such as ?Homer was seen by Marge is much improved in a context in which Homer is affected by being seen (e.g., Homer was intending to go to the pub instead of his daughter's recital, but had his plans ruined when he was seen by Marge en route to the pub). Future studies could test this possibility by having participants rate sentences such as Homer was seen by Marge in an “affected” context (as in the example above) and a “neutral” but otherwise similar context (e.g., Homer had agreed to meet Marge in the pub, and so was not particularly affected by her seeing him there when she came to join him).

In the meantime, suggestive evidence comes from the corpus study of Grafmiller (2013). Focusing on theme‐experiencer verbs, Grafmiller (2013:202) showed that the probability of a verb occurring in a passive versus an active is correlated with the extent to which the causer is usually something “about which people tend to direct longer lasting attitudes or evaluations”. For example, the verbs for which passives outnumber actives (fascinate, captivate, concern, horrify, astonish, upset and amaze) are those for which (usually non‐animate) theme causes a semi‐permanent state‐change in the (usually animate) experiencer. While the present study attempted to control out such factors (i.e., by using relatively neutral contexts and two human NPs wherever possible), we agree that the construal of the event—affected, amongst other things, by the nature of the NPs—is likely to affect the relative acceptability of a passive sentence. Future research is necessary to clarify this issue.

Given that the present study focused on adults, future research will also be needed to mediate between different accounts of the acquisition of the passive by young children (e.g., Borer & Wexler, 1987, 1992; Crain & Fodor, 1993; Brooks & Tomasello, 1999; Israel, Johnson, & Brooks, 2000; Savage et al., 2003, 2006; Huttenlocher et al., 2004; Abbot‐Smith & Behrens, 2006; Bencini & Valian, 2008; Messenger et al., 2011, 2012; Dittmar, Abbot‐Smith, Lieven, & Tomasello, 2013). Particularly relevant is the possibility that children start out with a passive construction that is lexically restricted to prototypical agent‐patient verbs (e.g., kick), and that gradually broadens to additionally encompass, first, theme‐experiencer verbs (e.g., frighten) and, later, experiencer‐theme verbs (e.g., see, hear). A related claim that has been made by authors from otherwise‐opposing theoretical perspectives (e.g., Borer & Wexler, 1987; Israel et al., 2000), is that children start out with adjectival short passives that denote affected states (e.g., It's wet/got wet; She's scared/got scared) and only later—as a result of either A‐chain maturation or gradual abstraction respectively—acquire the ability to produce full passives.

Given that we studied only adults, the present findings do not address either of these claims directly. They do, however, count against the possibility that any semantic prototype is an early stepping‐stone that is discarded when children's knowledge becomes more abstract. Rather, they suggest that whether or not a semantic constraint on the passive is operational for young children (and we agree with Messenger et al., 2012, that there is currently no convincing evidence that it is), such a constraint is operational for adults. In future work, we plan to investigate the possibility of an early semantic constraint by adapting the present paradigms for use with young children, and adopting others, such as production priming.

In conclusion, the findings of the present study suggest that passive syntax is indeed semantically constrained in adults. Across three studies, an independent measure of the extent to which individual verbs instantiate semantic properties relevant to the constraint (“affectedness”) significantly predicted the relative acceptability of passive sentences to a greater extent than active sentences. This pattern of findings suggests that any successful model of adults' linguistic knowledge, of whatever theoretical persuasion, will have to incorporate—in some form or other—this probabilistic semantic constraint.

Supporting information

Data S1. Extended set of 475 verbs.

Data S2. Animations.

Acknowledgments

The authors are members of the ESRC International Centre for Language and Communicative Development (LuCiD) at the University of Liverpool. The support of the Economic and Social Research Council [ES/L008955/1] is gratefully acknowledged. This research was partly funded by Leverhulme Trust Grant RPG‐158 to BA, JMP and CFR.

The copyright line for this article was changed on June 22, 2016 after original online publication.

Note

1

A data file containing the raw semantic ratings for each verb is available from the first author's website: www.benambridge.com

References

  1. Ambridge, B. (2013). How do children restrict their linguistic generalizations?: An (un‐) grammaticality judgment study. Cognitive Science, 37(3), 508–543. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  2. Ambridge, B. , Pine, J. M. , & Rowland, C. F. (2012). Semantics versus statistics in the retreat from locative overgeneralization errors. Cognition, 123(2), 260–279. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Ambridge, B. , Pine, J. M. , Rowland, C. F. , Freudenthal, D. , & Chang, F. (2014). Avoiding dative overgeneralization errors: Semantics, statistics or both? Language, Cognition and Neuroscience, 29(2), 218–243. [Google Scholar]
  4. Ambridge, B. , Pine, J. M. , Rowland, C. F. , & Young, C. R. (2008). The effect of verb semantic class and verb frequency (entrenchment) on children's and adults' graded judgements of argument‐structure overgeneralization errors. Cognition, 106(1), 87–129. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Bencini, G. M. L. , & Valian, V. V. (2008). Abstract sentence representations in 3 year‐olds: Evidence from language production and comprehension. Journal of Memory and Language, 59, 97–113. [Google Scholar]
  6. Blything, R. P. , Ambridge, B. , & Lieven, E. V. (2014). Children use statistics and semantics in the retreat from overgeneralization. PLoS ONE, 9(10), e110009. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Bock, J. K. (1986). Syntactic persistence in language production. Cognitive Psychology, 18, 355–387. [Google Scholar]
  8. Bock, K. , & Loebell, H. (1990). Framing sentences. Cognition, 35(1), 1–39. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  9. Bock, K. , Loebell, H. , & Morey, R. (1992). From conceptual roles to structural relations: Bridging the syntactic cleft. Psychological Review, 99(1), 150. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  10. Bock, K. , & Miller, C. A. (1991). Broken agreement. Cognitive Psychology, 23(45), 93. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  11. Boeckx, C. (1998). A minimalist view on the passive. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  12. Borer, H. , & Wexler, K. (1987). The Maturation of Syntax In Roeper T., & Williams E. (Eds.), Parameter setting (pp. 123–172). Dortrecht: D. Reidel. [Google Scholar]
  13. Borer, H. , & Wexler, K. (1992). Bi‐unique relations and the maturation of grammatical principles. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 10(2), 147–189. [Google Scholar]
  14. Bresnan, J. (2001). Lexical functional syntax. New York: Wiley. [Google Scholar]
  15. Brooks, P. J. , & Tomasello, M. (1999). Young children learn to produce passives with nonce verbs. Developmental Psychology, 35(1), 29–44. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  16. Carnie, A. (2007) Syntax: A generative introduction (3rd ed.). Oxford, England: Wiley Blackwell. [Google Scholar]
  17. Chomsky, N. (1989). Some notes on economy of derivation and representation. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 10: 43–74. [Google Scholar]
  18. Chomsky, N. (1993). A minimalist program for linguistic theory In Hale K. & Keyser S. J. (Eds.), The view from building 20 (pp. 1–52). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  19. Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
  20. Clifton, C., Jr , Frazier, L. , & Deevy, P. (1999). Feature manipulation in sentence comprehension. Rivista di Linguistica, 11, 11–39. [Google Scholar]
  21. Collins, C. (2005). A Smuggling approach to the passive in English. Syntax, 8(2), 81–120. [Google Scholar]
  22. Crain, S. , & Fodor, J. (1993). Competence and performance in child language In Dromi E. (Ed.), Language and cognition: A developmental perspective (pp. 141–171). Norwood, NJ: Ablex. [Google Scholar]
  23. Croft, W. (2001). Radical construction grammar: Syntactic theory in typological perspective. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
  24. Dittmar, M. , Abbot‐Smith, K. , Lieven, E. , & Tomasello, M. (2013). Familiar verbs are not always easier than novel verbs: How German pre‐school children comprehend active and passive sentences. Cognitive science, 38, 128–151. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Estival, D. (1985). Syntactic priming of the passive in English. Text, 5, 7–21. [Google Scholar]
  26. Ferreira, F. (2003). The misinterpretation of noncanonical sentences. Cognitive Psychology, 47(2), 164–203. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  27. Ferreira, F. , Bailey, K. G. , & Ferraro, V. (2002). Good‐enough representations in language comprehension. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11(1), 11–15. [Google Scholar]
  28. Fox, D. , & Grodzinsky, Y. (1998). Children's passive: A view from the by‐phrase. Linguistic Inquiry, 29, 311–332. [Google Scholar]
  29. Goldberg, A. E. (1995). Constructions: A construction grammar approach to argument structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
  30. Goldberg, A. E. , & Bencini, G. M. L. (2005). Support from processing for a constructional approach to grammar In Tyler A., Takada M., Kim Y., & Marinova D. (Eds.), Language in use: Cognitive and discourse perspectives on language and language learning (pp. 3–18). Washington DC: Georgetown University Press. [Google Scholar]
  31. Gordon, P. , & Chafetz, J. (1990). Verb‐based versus class‐based accounts of actionality effects in children's comprehension of passives. Cognition, 36(3), 227–254. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Grafmiller, J. (2013). The semantics of syntactic choice: An analysis of English emotion verbs. Unpublished PhD thesis, Stanford University.
  33. Hartshorne, J. K. , O'Donnell, T. J. , Sudo, Y. , Uruwashi, M. , Lee, M. , & Snedeker, J. (submitted). Psych verbs, the linking problem, and the acquisition of language. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
  34. Hartshorne, J. K. , Pogue, A. , & Snedeker, J. (2015). Love is hard to understand: The relationship between transitivity and caused events in the acquisition of emotion verbs. Journal of Child Language, 42(3), 467–504. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  35. Hartshorne, J. K. , & Snedeker, J. (2013). Verb argument structure predicts implicit causality: The advantages of finer‐grained semantics. Language and Cognitive Processes, 28(10), 1474–1508. [Google Scholar]
  36. Hartsuiker, R. J. , Pickering, M. J. , & Veltkamp, E. (2004). Is syntax separate or shared between languages? Cross‐linguistic syntactic priming in Spanish‐English bilinguals. Psychological Science, 15(6), 409–414. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Hirsch, C. , & Wexler, K. (2006). Children's passives and their resulting interpretation In Ud Deen Kamil, Nomura Jun, Schulz Barbara, Schwartz Bonnie D. (Eds.), The Proceedings of the Inaugural Conference on Generative Approaches to Language Acquisition–North America, University of Connecticut Occasional Papers in Linguistics (Vol. 4, pp. 125–136). Storrs, CT: University of Connecticut. [Google Scholar]
  38. Horgan, D. (1978). Development of full passive. Journal of Child Language, 5(1), 65–80. [Google Scholar]
  39. Huttenlocher, J. , Vasilyeva, M. , & Shimpi, P. (2004). Syntactic priming in young children. Journal of Memory and Language, 50(2), 182–195. [Google Scholar]
  40. Israel, M. , Johnson, C. , & Brooks, P. J. (2000). From states to events: The acquisition of English passive participles. Cognitive Linguistics, 11, 1–2. [Google Scholar]
  41. Levin, B. (1993). English verb classes and alternations: A preliminary investigation. Vol. 348. Chicago: University of Chicago press. [Google Scholar]
  42. Kuznetsova, A. , Brockhoff, P. B. , & Christensen, R. H. B. (2013). lmerTest: Tests for random and fixed effects for linear mixed effect models (lmer objects of lme4 package). R package version, 2(6). [Google Scholar]
  43. Lewis, S. , & Phillips, C. (2015). Aligning grammatical theories and language processing models. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 44(1), 27–46. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  44. Maratsos, M. P. , Fox, D. E. , Becker, J. A. , & Chalkley, M. A. (1985). Semantic restrictions on children's passives. Cognition, 19(2), 167–191. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Meints, K. (1999). Protoypes and the acquisition of passives In Kokinov B. (Ed.), Perspectives on cognitive Science, 4 (pp. 67–77). Sofia: NBU Press. [Google Scholar]
  46. Messenger, K. , Branigan, H. P. , & McLean, J. F. (2011). Evidence for (shared) abstract structure underlying children's short and full passives. Cognition, 121(2), 268–274. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  47. Messenger, K. , Branigan, H. P. , McLean, J. F. , & Sorace, A. (2012). Is young children's passive syntax semantically constrained? Evidence from syntactic priming. Journal of Memory and Language, 66(4), 568–587. [Google Scholar]
  48. Newmeyer, F. J. (2003). Grammar is grammar and usage is usage. Language, 79(4), 682–707. [Google Scholar]
  49. Newmeyer, F. J. (2015). Generative Grammar and Functional Explanation. Unpublished class handout. Available at: http://faculty.washington.edu/fjn/Newmeyer_handouts.pdf. Accessed 4th August 2015
  50. Pearlmutter, N. J. , Garnsey, S. M. , & Bock, K. (1999). Agreement processes in sentence comprehension. Journal of Memory and Language, 41, 427–456. [Google Scholar]
  51. Pickering, M. J. , & Ferreira, V. S. (2008). Structural priming: A critical review. Psychological Bulletin, 134(3), 427. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  52. Pinker, S. (1989). Learnability and cognition: The acquisition of argument structure. Cambridge, MA; London: MIT. [Google Scholar]
  53. Pinker, S. (2013). Learnability and cognition: The acquisition of argument structure. Cambridge, MA; London: MIT. [Google Scholar]
  54. Pinker, S. , Lebeaux, D. S. , & Frost, L. A. (1987). Productivity and constraints in the acquisition of the passive. Cognition, 26(3), 195–267. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Pollard, C. , & Sag, I. A. (1994). Head‐Driven phrase structure grammar. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
  56. Potter, M. C. , & Lombardi, L. (1998). Syntactic priming in immediate recall of sentences. Journal of Memory and Language, 38(3), 265–282. [Google Scholar]
  57. R Core Team (2014). R: A language and environment for statistical computing. R Foundation for Statistical Computing, Vienna, Austria. ISBN 3‐900051‐07‐0, URL http://www.R-project.org/.
  58. Saffran, E. M. , & Martin, N. (1997). Effects of structural priming on sentence production in aphasics. Language and Cognitive Processes, 12(5–6), 877–882. [Google Scholar]
  59. Savage, C. , Lieven, E. , Theakston, A. , & Tomasello, M. (2003). Testing the abstractness of children's linguistic representations: Lexical and structural priming of syntactic constructions in young children. Developmental Science, 6(5), 557–567. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Savage, C. , Lieven, E. , Theakston, A. , & Tomasello, M. (2006). Structural priming as implicit learning in language acquisition: The persistence of lexical and structural priming in 4‐year‐olds. Language Learning and Development, 2, 27–50. [Google Scholar]
  61. Sudhalter, V. , & Braine, M. D. S. (1985). How does comprehension of passives develop—a comparison of actional and experiential verbs. Journal of Child Language, 12(2), 455–470. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  62. Wurm, L. H. , & Fisicaro, S. A. (2014). What residualizing predictors in regression analyses does (and what it does not do). Journal of Memory and Language, 72, 37–48. [Google Scholar]

Associated Data

This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.

Supplementary Materials

Data S1. Extended set of 475 verbs.

Data S2. Animations.


Articles from Cognitive Science are provided here courtesy of Wiley

RESOURCES