Abstract
Background Increasingly, patient decision aids and values clarification methods (VCMs) are being developed to support patients in making preference‐sensitive health‐care decisions. Many VCMs encourage extensive deliberation about options, without solid theoretical or empirical evidence showing that deliberation is advantageous. Research suggests that simple, fast and frugal heuristic decision strategies sometimes result in better judgments and decisions. Durand et al. have developed two fast and frugal heuristic‐based VCMs.
Objective To critically analyse the suitability of the ‘take the best’ (TTB) and ‘tallying’ fast and frugal heuristics in the context of patient decision making.
Strategy Analysis of the structural similarities between the environments in which the TTB and tallying heuristics have been proven successful and the context of patient decision making and of the potential of these heuristic decision processes to support patient decision making.
Conclusion The specific nature of patient preference‐sensitive decision making does not seem to resemble environments in which the TTB and tallying heuristics have proven successful. Encouraging patients to consider less rather than more relevant information potentially even deteriorates their values clarification process. Values clarification methods promoting the use of more intuitive decision strategies may sometimes be more effective. Nevertheless, we strongly recommend further theoretical thinking about the expected value of such heuristics and of other more intuitive decision strategies in this context, as well as empirical assessments of the mechanisms by which inducing such decision strategies may impact the quality and outcome of values clarification.
Keywords: decision quality, deliberation, intuition, patient preferences, theory‐informed design
Introduction
Strategies of care sometimes are equivalent from a standpoint of medical efficacy. Such so‐called preference‐sensitive screening or treatment decisions often are new to patients, entail complicated trade‐offs (e.g. risk of a miscarriage vs. risk of giving birth to a disabled child in prenatal diagnosis), evoke strong emotions and may have significant, sometimes irreversible consequences. 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 , 5 When facing such decisions, patient preferences can be labile or non‐existent 6 , 7 , 8 and need to be clarified. As available alternatives often cannot directly be compared on single quantifiable attributes (i.e. there is no ‘common currency’), 3 , 4 making treatment and screening decisions is challenging.
Increasingly, patient decision aids (PtDAs) are being developed to support patient decision making. Patient decision aids can enhance patients’ knowledge and their satisfaction with the decision‐making process. 9 However, their effect on decision quality and decision process measures, such as feeling clear about one’s values, varies. 10 As Durand et al. and others have underlined, we lack insight into the nature of cognitive processes that might help patients make informed preference‐sensitive decisions. 11 , 12 , 13 , 14 , 15 We underscore their and others’ call for stronger theoretical and conceptual underpinnings for designing PtDAs 12 , 16 , 17 , 18 Empirical tests of theoretically‐based PtDAs will improve our understanding of how to design effective PtDAs.
Mechanisms underlying current values clarification methods
So‐called values clarification methods (VCMs) currently included in PtDAs largely encourage extensive deliberation: analytical, explicit reasoning processes, such as listing pros and cons and assigning decision weights (e.g. 1–5 stars) to them. 19 This reflects a central assumption in the literature that VCMs should encourage extensive deliberation. 20 , 21 However, human reasoning strongly depends on intuition. 22 , 23 , 24 , 25 Over the past 20 years, psychological evidence has accumulated, showing that intuitive decision strategies such as relying on emotional ‘gut feelings’, deciding after a brief period of distraction, or deciding based on mental shortcuts or heuristics sometimes result in better judgments and decisions (i.e. more in line with expert opinion, more accurate, or resulting in higher consumer satisfaction) than extensively considering all information. 26 , 27 , 28 It is as yet unclear to what extent these findings can be translated to patient decision making. Durand et al. provide a first test of the feasibility of VCMs based on ‘fast and frugal heuristics’. Thereby, they make an important contribution to the field of PtDAs. First, they designed ‘theoretically‐informed’ VCMs. 12 , 16 Second, these VCMs are based on more intuitive decision strategies. Their study provides preliminary insight into how decision makers value such tools. 11 However, we see important pitfalls in translating fast and frugal heuristics to the context of PtDAs. Here, we aim to provide a critical analysis of the suitability of these simplifying heuristics in VCMs.
Fast and frugal heuristics
Fast and frugal heuristics are decision strategies that (i) are simple: they exploit evolved or learned human capacities; (ii) are ecologically rational: they are not inherently good or bad, but they are accurate relative to the structure of the environment; and (iii) describe the way people make decisions naturally in those environments. 26 , 28 , 29
Research has shown that using fast and frugal heuristics, and thereby less information and time, sometimes results in more accurate judgments (i.e. more in line with actual facts). 28 Two such heuristics are ‘take the best’ (TTB) and ‘tallying’. The TTB heuristic is member of the ‘one good reason’ family of heuristics. It implies ignoring cues and making inferences based on the first cue encountered which enables one to make the inference. Tallying is a strategy in which information elements are given equal weight in making predictions. Both types of heuristics have been found to be equally or more accurate in making judgments compared to more complex decision strategies in various settings, including estimating which of two cities has a larger population, the number of car accidents on specific stretches of highways, and attractiveness ratings of public figures. 30 , 31
The suitability of fast and frugal heuristics in patient decision aids
Durand et al. 11 have designed a TTB and a tallying heuristic‐based VCM for women facing the decision to undergo or not to undergo amniocentesis. We question the suitability of these heuristics in patient preference‐sensitive decision making for two main reasons: (i) the qualitative difference between making inferences in familiar decisions vs. determining preference in new decisions by integrating information and (ii) decision environments in which information and time resources are limited vs. decision environments in which these are not at stake.
(i) Making inferences vs. determining preference. In the medical field, the use of simple heuristics rather than more complete information has been shown to be equally good or advantageous to physicians who had to choose a strategy of care. 32 , 33 , 34 In such cases, physicians need to assess the validity of information for making inferences about patients’ condition. Also, an external criterion of success exists, which enables decision makers to determine the accuracy of their estimation. This context is similar to those in many of the studies demonstrating the success of fast and frugal heuristics, which involved decision makers who were familiar with the decision context and had experience or gained experience with the structure of the environment before making a particular decision. 28 Decision makers could therefore benefit from their experience regarding the appropriateness of information elements in making inferences and thus learn to use information efficiently. Evidence indeed suggests that experts tend to apply more selective information processing than non‐experts. 35 Durand et al. suggest that compared to more complex interventions, fast and frugal heuristics may, in a similar way, lead to better decisions in patients as decision makers.
However, patients do not make objectively accurate or inaccurate inferences about some external object; they need to integrate and weigh pieces of information to determine their personal preference in new decision situations. Preference‐sensitive options in health care carry benefits and risks. The central task in clarifying one’s preference lies in making trade‐offs between these. Patients need to consider to what extent pieces of information are important to them in their specific situation. They lack the experience with the decision that would have enabled them to know how well relying on specific pieces of information helps them to make a decision they will not regret later on. Also, there is no external criterion for the ‘accuracy’ of preferences, because good patient decisions in health care may lead to bad outcomes. For example, amniocentesis may result in a miscarriage, but was it then a bad decision? In other words, outcome of a specific decision does not teach decision makers about the rightness of their choice, as it would have if there was an external accuracy standard involved.
(ii) Limited information and time resources. In arguing in favour of the suitability of the TTB and tallying heuristics, Durand et al. refer to decision situations in which there is limited knowledge and time and in which these have proven successful. 36 , 37 , 38 , 39 , 40 The success of judgments based on less information is attributed to the ‘bias‐variance dilemma’. By using less information, the variance component in errors of predictions is reduced. However, when information acquisition costs are low, when there is no time pressure and when information is provided simultaneously, compensatory strategies, that is, strategies in which favourable values on some attribute can compensate for unfavourable values on other attributes, predict individuals’ inferences 41 , 42 and preferences 41 better.
Generally, in decisions for which PtDAs are available, information search and potential costs associated with searching are not at stake, as the PtDA offers the relevant information. By definition, decision aids should provide all relevant information about the condition and options. So, patients who have access to PtDAs have access to information, which they can use to evaluate how much they prefer one option over the other.
Also, in cases in which PtDAs are offered, there is often sufficient time available to consider one’s preference regarding the options. In case of deciding about amniocentesis, women usually have 2–3 weeks to decide whether or not they wish to conduct the test – or even more, if we take into account that women may start considering amniocentesis from the moment they know they are pregnant. It is therefore questionable whether the level of time pressure is comparable to the level of time pressure which was present in the studies showing an advantage of fast and frugal strategies.
Should fast and frugal heuristics be encouraged as decision processes?
We argued above that we have reason to expect that the structure of the patient decision‐making context differs from the structure of environments in which the TTB and tallying heuristics have been shown to result in accurate judgments. We further expect that heuristic decision strategies are not accurate descriptions of patients’ natural decision processes. Specifically, we expect that patients will rather use compensatory decision strategies because of patients’ lack of expertise with the decision, 35 their personal involvement, 43 the relatively small number of options (e.g. undergoing or not undergoing amniocentesis) and attributes that distinguish the options (e.g. risk of miscarriage, gain in certainty about chromosomal problems), 44 , 45 , 46 and because the decision is made under uncertainty. 47 Yet, an appealing aspect of heuristic‐based VCMs is their apparent simplicity in use. It is an empirical question whether TTB and/or tallying heuristic‐based VCMs may be helpful in supporting patients in clarifying their values. Empirical evidence suggests that active processing of information, and of probabilistic information in particular, is useful in understanding information. 48 Therefore, heuristic tools may be helpful because they help patients to actively engage with the information, that is, to think about reasons to choose or not to choose an option. This may support patients in determining the importance of information to their preference. An important issue here is the assumption that patient preferences will often at least partly be constructed when patients face a preference‐sensitive decision. There is evidence showing that people apply either compensatory or non‐compensatory decision strategies depending on the preference elicitation method 49 , 50 and that strategy use affects outcomes. 50 , 51 If patients are encouraged to consider less rather than more relevant information, it is questionable whether this will improve the values clarification process. It may even deteriorate that process by drawing attention to a single attribute that may be easiest to evaluate, but may not necessarily be the most important in determining preference. 27
Of note, Durand et al. characterize their tools as ‘intuitive’. Intuition serves as a broad umbrella term for highly diverse decision strategies, which share the feature of not being analytical. Some of these may be more suitable for VCMs than others. Heuristic‐based tools as Durand et al. describe may be less complex in use than more conventional VCMs but still rely on considering attributes of options. They do not encourage holistic evaluations of options, such as relying on emotional ‘gut feelings’ or deciding after a brief period of distraction. Such intuitive preferences have been argued to be based on more comprehensive processes and to represent balanced, intuitive summary judgments of well‐integrated information elements. 3 , 4 , 23 , 24 , 26 , 52 Future research could provide tests of the suitability of specific intuitive processes in VCMs. 15
Conclusion
Many VCMs encourage individuals who are considering preference‐sensitive health‐care options to deliberate extensively, without a solid theoretical and empirical basis for the assumption that deliberation is advantageous. The TTB and tallying heuristics are examples of more intuitive decision strategies that have been proven advantageous in decision tasks other than patient preference‐sensitive decision making. The specific nature of patient values clarification does not seem to resemble environments in which these heuristics have proven to do well. Moreover, encouraging patients to consider less rather than more relevant information potentially deteriorates their decision processes. Values clarification methods supporting patients to use more intuitive decision strategies may sometimes be more effective, but the evidence is still very limited. We strongly recommend further theoretical thinking about the expected value of fast and frugal heuristics and other intuitive decision strategies in this context as well as empirical assessments of the mechanisms by which inducing such decision strategies may impact the quality and outcome of values clarification.
Funding
Arwen Pieterse is supported by a postdoctoral fellowship from the Dutch Cancer Society.
Conflict of interest
None.
Acknowledgements
We thank Wilbert van den Hout and Anne Stiggelbout for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper.
References
- 1. Epstein RM, Peters E. Beyond information: exploring patients’ preferences. JAMA: The Journal of the American Medical Association, 2009; 302: 195–197. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2. Pieterse AH, Stiggelbout AM, Baas‐Thijssen MC, van de Velde CJ, Marijnen CA. Benefit from preoperative radiotherapy in rectal cancer treatment: disease‐free patients’ and oncologists’ preferences. British Journal of Cancer, 2007; 97: 717–724. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3. Kerstholt JH, van der Zwaard F, Bart H, Cremers A. Construction of health preferences: a comparison of direct value assessment and personal narratives. Medical Decision Making, 2009; 29: 513–520. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4. Peters E, Lipkus I, Diefenbach MA. The functions of affect in health communications and the construction of health preferences. Journal of Communication, 2006; 56: S140–S162. [Google Scholar]
- 5. Power TE, Swartzman LC, Robinson JW. Cognitive‐emotional decision making (CEDM): a framework of patient medical decision making. Patient Education and Counseling, 2010; 83: 163–169. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6. Fischhoff B. Value elicitation: is there anything in there? American Psychologist, 1991; 46: 835–847. [Google Scholar]
- 7. Simon D, Krawczyk DC, Bleicher A, Holyoak KJ. The transience of constructed preferences. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 2008; 21: 1–14. [Google Scholar]
- 8. Slovic P. The construction of preference. American Psychologist, 1995; 50: 364–371. [Google Scholar]
- 9. O’Connor AM, Bennett CL, Stacey D et al. Decision aids for people facing health treatment or screening decisions. Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews, 2009; 3: CD001431. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10. O’Connor AM, Bennett C, Stacey D et al. Do patient decision aids meet effectiveness criteria of the international patient decision aid standards collaboration? A systematic review and meta‐analysis Medical Decision Making, 2007; 27: 554–574. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11. Durand MA, Wegwarth O, Boivin J, Elwyn G. Information and decision support needs of parents considering amniocentesis: interviews with pregnant women and health professionals. Health Expectations, 2011. DOI:10.1111/j.1369‐7625.2010.00651.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12. Nelson WL, Han PK, Fagerlin A, Stefanek M, Ubel PA. Rethinking the objectives of decision aids: a call for conceptual clarity. Medical Decision Making, 2007; 27: 609–618. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13. Bekker HL. The loss of reason in patient decision aid research: do checklists damage the quality of informed choice interventions? Patient Education and Counseling, 2010; 78: 357–364. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14. Charles C, Gafni A, Whelan T, O’Brien MA. Treatment decision aids: conceptual issues and future directions. Health Expectations, 2005; 8: 114–125. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15. Scherer LD, Fagerlin A, Witteman H, De Vries M. Intuition and deliberation in patient decision aids: from evidence in psychological science to empirical questions in medical decision making. Resubmitted, 2011.
- 16. Elwyn G, Stiel M, Durand MA, Boivin J. The design of patient decision support interventions: addressing the theory‐practice gap. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 2010; 17: 565–574. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17. Stiggelbout AM, Timmermans DR. Revisiting decision aids: about definitions and classifications. Medical Decision Making, 2010; 30: 696–698. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18. Pieterse AH, De Vries M, Stiggelbout AM, Feldman‐Stewart D. Theory‐informed design of values clarification methods: A cognitive psychological perspective on patient treatment decision making. Submitted. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19. Llewellyn‐Thomas H. Values clarification In: Edwards A, Elwyn G. (eds) Shared Decision‐Making in Health Care. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009: 123–133. [Google Scholar]
- 20. Elwyn G, Miron‐Shatz T. Deliberation before determination: the definition and evaluation of good decision making. Health Expectations, 2010; 13: 139–147. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21. O’Connor A. Using patient decision aids to promote evidence‐based decision making. ACP Journal Club, 2001; 135: A11–A12. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22. Bargh JA. The automaticity of everyday life In: Wyer RS. (ed.) The automaticity of everyday life. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1997: 1–62. [Google Scholar]
- 23. Damasio AR. Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: G.P. Putnam’s Sons, 1994. [Google Scholar]
- 24. Dijksterhuis A. Think different: the merits of unconscious thought in preference development and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 2004; 87: 586–598. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25. Wilson TD. Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconscious. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2002. [Google Scholar]
- 26. Dijksterhuis A, Bos MW, Nordgren LF, Van Baaren RB. On making the right choice: the deliberation‐without‐attention effect. Science, 2006; 311: 1005–1007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27. Wilson TD, Schooler JW. Thinking too much: introspection can reduce the quality of preferences and decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1991; 60: 181–192. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28. Gigerenzer G, Brighton H. Homo Heuristicus: why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2009; 1: 107–143. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29. Gigerenzer G. Fast and frugal heuristics: the tools of bounded rationality In: Koehler D, Harvey N. (eds) Blackwell Handbook of Judgment and Decision Making. Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 2004: 62–88. [Google Scholar]
- 30. Gigerenzer G, Goldstein DG. Reasoning the fast and frugal way: models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 1996; 103: 650–669. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31. Czerlinski J, Gigerenzer G, Goldstein DG. How good are simple heuristics? Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press, 1999: 97–118. [Google Scholar]
- 32. Wegwarth O, Gaissmaier W, Gigerenzer G. Smart strategies for doctors and doctors‐in‐training: heuristics in medicine. Medical Education, 2009; 43: 721–728. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33. Fischer JE, Steiner F, Zucol F et al. Use of simple heuristics to target macrolide prescription in children with community‐acquired pneumonia. Archives of Pediatrics and Adolescent Medicine, 2002; 156: 1005–1008. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 34. Green L, Mehr DR. What alters physicians’ decisions to admit to the coronary care unit? Journal of Family Practice, 1997; 45: 219–226. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35. Shanteau J. How much information does an expert use – is it relevant. Acta Psychologica, 1992; 81: 75–86. [Google Scholar]
- 36. Bröder A. Assessing the empirical validity of the “take‐the‐best” heuristic as a model of human probabilistic inference. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 2000; 26: 1332–1346. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37. Bröder A. Decision making with the “adaptive toolbox”: influence of environmental structure, intelligence, and working memory load. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 2003; 29: 611–625. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38. Newell BR, Weston NJ, Shanks DR. Empirical tests of a fast‐and‐frugal heuristic: not everyone “takes‐the‐best”. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 2003; 91: 82–96. [Google Scholar]
- 39. Rieskamp J, Hoffrage U. Inferences under time pressure: how opportunity costs affect strategy selection. Acta Psychologica, 2008; 127: 258–276. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40. Gigerenzer G, Todd PM, the ABC Research Group . Simple Heursitics That Make Us Smart. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- 41. Ayal S, Hochman G. Ignorance or integration: the cognitive processes underlying choice behavior. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 2009; 22: 455–474. [Google Scholar]
- 42. Rieskamp J, Otto PE. SSL: a theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General, 2006; 135: 207–236. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43. Gensch DH, Javalgi RG. The influence of involvement on disaggregate attribute choice models. Journal of Consumer Research, 1987; 14: 71–82. [Google Scholar]
- 44. Ford JK, Schmitt N, Schechtman SL, Hults BM, Doherty ML. Process tracing methods – contributions, problems, and neglected research questions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 1989; 43: 75–117. [Google Scholar]
- 45. Biggs SF, Bedard JC, Gaber BG, Linsmeier TJ. The effects of task size and similarity on the decision behavior of bank loan officers. Management Science, 1985; 31: 970–987. [Google Scholar]
- 46. Sundström GA. Information search and decision making: the effects of information displays In: Montgomery AA, Svenson O. (eds) Process and Structure in Human Decision Making. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, 1989: 209–223. [Google Scholar]
- 47. Glockner A, Betsch T. Do people make decisions under risk based on ignorance? An empirical test of the priority heuristic against cumulative prospect theory Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 2008; 107: 75–95. [Google Scholar]
- 48. Natter HM, Berry DC. Effects of active information processing on the understanding of risk information. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 2005; 19: 123–135. [Google Scholar]
- 49. Dieckmann A, Dippold K, Dietrich H. Compensatory versus noncompensatory models for predicting consumer preferences. Judgment and Decision Making, 2009; 4: 200–213. [Google Scholar]
- 50. Nowlis SM, Simonson I. Attribute‐task compatibility as a determinant of consumer preference reversals. Journal of Marketing Research, 1997; 34: 205–218. [Google Scholar]
- 51. Dhar R. The effect of decision strategy on deciding to defer choice. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 1996; 9: 265–281. [Google Scholar]
- 52. De Vries M, Holland RW, Witteman CLM. In the winning mood: affect in the Iowa gambling task. Judgment and Decision Making, 2008; 3: 42–50. [Google Scholar]