Skip to main content
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America logoLink to Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America
. 2005 Jan 5;102(3):945–948. doi: 10.1073/pnas.0408022101

A simple test of expected utility theory using professional traders

John A List a,b,c,d, Michael S Haigh b,e
PMCID: PMC545552  PMID: 15634739

Abstract

We compare behavior across students and professional traders from the Chicago Board of Trade in a classic Allais paradox experiment. Our experiment tests whether independence, a necessary condition in expected utility theory, is systematically violated. We find that both students and professionals exhibit some behavior consistent with the Allais paradox, but the data pattern does suggest that the trader population falls prey to the Allais paradox less frequently than the student population.

Keywords: Allais paradox, experiments, futures traders


Expected utility (EU) theory remains the dominant approach for modeling risky decision-making and has been considered the major paradigm in decision making since World War II, being used predictively in economics and finance, prescriptively in management science, and descriptively in psychology (1). Furthermore, EU is the common economic approach for addressing public policy decision-making: a comparison of the expected costs and benefits of a proposed public policy implicitly assumes that economic agents maximize EU.

The mathematical form of EU stems back to the 17th century during the development of modern probability theory. Mathematicians Blaise Pascal and Pierre de Fermat assumed that the attractiveness of a lottery offering payoff (x1,..., xn) with probabilities (p1,..., pn) was simply given by its expected value = ∑xi pi. However, the fact that individuals evaluate more than expected value was dramatically illustrated by Nicholas Bernoulli in 1728 by using an example known today as the St. Petersburg paradox.f

Daniel Bernoulli (2), who was Nicholas's cousin, offered a solution to this paradox. Specifically, he outlined intuitive reasons why individuals would pay only a small amount for a game with an infinite mathematical expectation. He argued that a $100 gain was not necessarily worth more than twice as much as a gain of $50, suggesting that individuals maximize EU rather than expected monetary value. The utility function U(x) he proposed was logarithmic, which exhibited diminishing increases in utility for equal increments in wealth and did, in fact, show that the EU is indeed finite in such cases. [Bernoulli proposed the following function: U(x) = bln[(α + x)/α]. dU(x)/dx = b/(α + x), which is inversely proportional to wealth. Moreover, d2U(x)/dx2 < 0.]

The work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern (3) proved that several basic axioms guarantee that there exists a utility index such that the ordering of lotteries based on their expected utilities fully coincides with the person's actual preferences.g Although EU represents a convenient and tractable approach to measuring utility, it continues to be the focus of much theoretical, empirical, and experimental research simply because EU theory is often shown to be systematically violated under certain conditions. Indeed, in experimental investigations, the weight of evidence suggests that student subjects make decisions inconsistent with EU theory (see refs. 4-9). Despite finding violations of EU, the theory has been shown to be a “pretty good” approximation to individuals' true preferences. Indeed, according to some researchers, learning and familiarization with the decision tasks are required before true preferences settle on the genuine underlying form (10).

Understanding whether experienced agents, like professional traders, make similar decisions is important in light of some recent studies (e.g. refs. 11 and 12) that find that market anomalies in the realm of riskless decision-making are attenuated among economic players who have intense market experience.h To provide a stringent test of EU theory, we follow Starmer and Sugden (7) and use choice problems that correspond very closely to one of the classic forms of the Allais paradox (18), the “common consequence effect,” a test of the independence assumption in EU theory.i

In our experimental investigation of EU theory (specifically the test of the independence assumption), we find that both students and professional traders from the Chicago Board of Trade (CBOT) exhibit behavior consistent with the Allais paradox (thus violating EU theory), but the data pattern does suggest that the trader population falls prey to the Allais paradox slightly less frequently than the student population. Furthermore, we find that professional traders behave in accordance with the reduction principle (reducing compound lotteries to simple ones via the calculus of probabilities (see ref. 20), whereas students did not exhibit this tendency.

The Allais Paradox

One important violation of EU's independence assumption is the Allais paradox.j Indeed, a survey conducted by Allais in 1952 showed that the majority of real decision makers order risky prospects in a way that is inconsistent with the postulate that choices are independent of irrelevant alternatives, thus casting doubt on the validity of EU theory. However, it is precisely this postulate that permits economists to represent preferences over risky prospects as a linear function of the utilities of the basic outcomes, and hence have the ability to measure utility. A classic paper by Marschak (25) discusses the rationality of this approach by using examples from both statistics and business.

As presented by Allais (18), a person chooses between lotteries a1 and a2, and between lotteries a3 and a4, where a1,a2,a3, and a4 are: a1, 1.00 chance of $1,000,000; a2, .10 chance of $5,000,000, 0.89 chance of $1,000,000, and 0.01 chance of $0; a3, 0.10 chance of $5,000,000, 0.90 chance of $0; and a4, 0.11 chance of $1,000,000; 0.89 chance of $0.

In this example, if an agent prefers a1 to a2 and a4 to a3, (or a2 to a1 and a3 to a4), the individual does not violate the independence axiom and the evidence is consistent with the agent having indifference curves that are parallel straight lines (as surmised by EU theory) (this is illustrated pictorially in refs. 6 and 19). Laboratory experimentation, however, has shown that agents commonly choose a1 and a3, violating the independence assumption. To understand the nature of the paradox, note that the expected value of a1 is $1 million and the expected value of a2 is $1.39 million. By preferring a1 to a2, an agent is presumably maximizing EU, not expected value. If a1 > a2, then u (1) > 0.1u (5) + 0.89u (1) + 0.01u (0), implying that 0.11u (1) > 0.1u (5) + 0.1u (0), which in turn [adding 0.89u (0) to each side] implies 0.11u (1) + 0.89u (0) > 0.1u (5) + 0.90u (0). This suggests that an EU-maximizing agent must prefer a4 to a3. Of course, the expected value of a4 is $110,000, whereas the expected value of a3 is $500,000, so if the agent is maximizing expected value, he should in fact prefer a4 to a3. However, his choice in the first stage is inconsistent with his choice in the second stage, and thus the paradox emerges.

Experimental Design

Our experimental design is a slightly different example of the Allais paradox most commonly referred to as the “common consequence effect.” [Other examples include “the certainty effect” and the “Bergen paradox.” See Machina (6, 19) or Thaler (9) for a more in-depth treatment of these cases and the literature involving independence violations.] In our example, we ask subjects to make simple lottery choices. We make use of a straightforward 2 × 3 experimental design (see Table 1). Because one important purpose of our research is to explore whether agents who are professional traders exhibit behavior in line with EU, we use undergraduate students as our experimental control group.k Using a between-person experimental design, we include both undergraduate students and professional traders in two distinct treatments: treatments 1 and 2. In a third treatment, we had a different student group participate, but had the same 54 traders who participated in treatments 1 and 2 complete treatment 3. (See Fig. 1 for our experimental instructions for treatment 3. Instructions for the other two treatments are similar, with the necessary adjustments.) The traders first took part in treatment 1 or 2 (determined randomly) and then proceeded through some unrelated experiments for ≈1 h, and then participated in treatment 3 at the end of the session.l

Table 1. Experimental design.

Subject type Treatment 1 Treatment 2 Treatment 3
Students 32 32 30
Traders 27 27 54

Data represent sample sizes. Treatment 1 (2) had subjects choosing between R1 and S1 (R2 and S2). Treatment 3 had subjects choosing between R1 and S1 and then R2 and S2, where it was understood that one of the choices would be carried out for real earnings.

Fig. 1.

Fig. 1.

Experimental instructions for treatment 3 given to traders.

In treatment 1, subjects were confronted with a simple one-shot choice question (following Starmer and Sugden (7), S (R) represents “safer” (“riskier”) choice): R1, 0.05 chance of zero winnings, 0.20 chance of winning $10, 0.75 chance of winning $7.00; S1, $7 with certainty. In treatment 2, the choice was over a different pair: R2, 0.80 chance of zero winnings, 0.20 chance of winning $10; S2, 0.75 chance of zero winnings, 0.25 chance of winning $7.

In this case, EU theory predicts that if R1 (S1) is chosen instead of S1 (R1), then R2 (S2) should be chosen instead of S2 (R2). Alternatively, the Allais paradox and several other decision-making theories predict that subjects will “switch” by choosing S1 and R2 (see ref. 7). This paradoxical choice has been termed the “common consequence effect,” and is a classic form of the Allais paradox.

In treatment 3, subjects were confronted with the two identical choice questions and informed that they should make a choice for both questions, but that only one of the questions would be binding, i.e., carried out for real money. This treatment, which is commonly referred to as the “random payment” or “random lottery” procedure in experimental economics, was used to provide information on whether subjects use the “reduction principle,” reducing compound lotteries to simple ones via the calculus of probabilities (see ref. 20). Under our design the lotteries reduce as follows: (R1R2) = ($10, 0.20; $7, 0.375; 0, 0.425); (R1S2) = ($10, 0.10; $7, 0.50; 0, 0.40); (S1R2) = ($10, 0.10; $7, 0.50; 0, 0.40); (S1S2) = ($7, 0.625; 0, 0.375).

For example, the choices of R1 and R2 in treatment 3 provide $10 with 20% chance, $7 with 37.5% chance, and $0 with 42.5% chance. In this case, (R1S2) and (S1R2) should be chosen with equal probability if the reduction principle holds because these pairs are isomorphic in reduced form. It seems intuitive to us that, if two options are identical, they will be chosen with equal probability. We should stress that a test of the reduction principle relies on this proposition.

We recruited 94 subjects for our student treatments from the undergraduate student body at the University of Maryland (College Park). Each treatment was run in a large classroom on the College Park campus. To ensure that decisions remained anonymous, the subjects were seated far apart from each other. The trader subject pool included 54 professional traders from the CBOT. Each of the trader treatments was run in a large room on site at the CBOT. As in the case of the students, communication between the subjects was prohibited and the traders were seated such that no subject could observe another individual's decision (and payoffs).

Before moving to a discussion of the experimental results, a few noteworthy aspects of our experimental design merit further consideration. First, all treatments were run with pencil and paper. After subjects made their decisions and the lottery results were realized, experimenters circulated to ensure that individual payoffs were calculated correctly. Second, in treatment 3, we varied the order in which the questions were given with no apparent ordering effect in the results, so we pooled the data. Third, in the student treatments, the exchange rate was 1:1 (1 cent for each unit), and in the trader treatments the exchange rate was 4:1 (4 cents for each unit). Our decision to quadruple the stakes for traders was based on a detailed discussion with CBOT officials about trader earnings. However, we should highlight that all conclusions should be viewed in light of this technical qualification.

Results

Table 2 provides a summary of our data. Data in the treatment 1 and treatment 2 columns of Table 2 represent the number of subjects making each choice. For example, in the student treatment 1 data, 17 subjects chose R1 and 15 subjects chose S1. In treatment 3, data represent the patterns of choice. For example, 10R1R2 shows that 10 students chose R1 in the first question and R2 in the second question.

Table 2. Experimental results summary.

Subject type Treatment 1 Treatment 2 Treatment 3
Students 17R1 15S1 24R2 8S2 10R1R2 3R1S2 13S1R2 4S1S2
Traders 19R1 8S1 24R2 3S2 30R1R2 9R1S2 7S1R2 8S1S2

Data represent the number of subjects making each choice. For example, in the student treatment 1, 17 subjects chose R1 and 15 chose S1. In treatment 3, data represent the patterns of choice. For example, 10R1R2 shows that 10 students chose R1 in the first question and R2 in the second.

The major issue at hand is whether subjects' choices are in line with the Allais paradox. We examine this question with a null hypothesis of Pr(R1) = Pr(R2) and with a one-sided “common consequence effect” alternative: Pr(R2) > Pr(R1). Among students, 17 of 32 (53%) chose R1, whereas 24 of 32 (75%) chose R2. Traders show a preference in a similar direction: 19 of 27 (70%) chose R1, whereas 24 of 27 (89%) chose R2. Although these differences are both statistically significant at the P < 0.05 level when a Fischer's exact test is used, suggesting that both traders and students' behavior is line with the Allais paradox, the data pattern does suggest that the trader population falls prey to the Allais paradox less frequently than the student population.

Our next exploration concerns whether the reduction principle holds. In this case, the null hypothesis is that Pr(R1S2) = Pr(S1R2), and for a common consequence effect to be evident it must be the case that Pr(S1R2) > Pr(R1S2). In the student data, 3 of 30 (10%) subjects chose R1S2 and 13 of 30 (43%) subjects chose S1R2, providing strong evidence of the common consequence effect, and inconsistent with the reduction conjecture. This result is consonant with Starmer and Sugden's (7) results using University of East Anglia (Norfolk, U.K.) students. Among traders, however, 9 of 54 (17%) chose R1S2 and only 7 of 54 (13%) chose S1R2. This difference, which is in the opposite direction of the student results and the common consequence prediction, is not statistically significant, and therefore we cannot reject the null hypothesis that traders behave according to the reduction principle. Also, the amount of “switching” for dealers (16 of 54) is less than that for students (16 of 30), suggesting again that the trader population falls prey to the Allais paradox less than the student population.

Concluding Remarks

In this study, we recruited futures and options floor traders from the CBOT to participate in an experiment involving choice over risky outcomes. Making use of undergraduate students as our experimental control group, we find some evidence that both students and professional traders behave in accordance with the Allais paradox. However, we find that the trader population falls prey to the Allais paradox slightly less frequently than the student population. A few caveats are in order. First, it is important to note that traders were making decisions over higher financial stakes. Second, we should highlight that our findings do not necessarily conflict with those of previous authors who have found that experienced marketers do not fall prey to behavioral anomalies. In many of those cases, subject decision-making was observed in natural settings in which the agents have experience with the good, the task, the institution, the environment, etc. In our experimental design, it may be the case that all of the important design parameters, even the task, is foreign to the professional traders, leading to the observed results. A next step in our research agenda is to explore the comparative static effects of adding/removing context and observing behavior in/out of the natural setting.

Acknowledgments

Marc Nerlove and three sharp reviewers provided astute comments on an earlier version of this paper. We thank John Di Clemente, former Managing Director of Research at the Chicago Board of Trade, for authorizing the study. Chicago Board of Trade officials Frederick Sturm, Dorothy Ackerman Anderson, and Keith Schap also provided incredible support on site. We thank Jonathan Alevy for research assistance and the University of Maryland for funding this research.

Author contributions: J.A.L. and M.S.H. designed research, performed research, analyzed data, and wrote the paper.

Abbreviations: EU, expected utility; CBOT, Chicago Board of Trade.

Footnotes

f

The St. Petersburg paradox is as follows: Imagine someone offers to toss a coin repeatedly until it comes up tails, and to reward you $1 if this happens on the very first toss, $2 if it takes two tosses, $4 if it takes three tosses, $8 for four tosses, etc. What is the largest sure gain you would be willing to forego in order to undertake a single play of the game? Because the gamble offers 1/2 chance of winning $1, 1/4 of winning $2, etc., the expected value is (1/2) × $1 + (1/4) × $2 + (1/8) × $4 = 1/2 + 1/2 + 1/2 + · · ·. + 1/2 = $∞, so it should be preferred to any finite gain. However, it is clear that very few individuals would forego more than a moderate amount for a one-shot play.

g

Specifically, if a person's preferences satisfy three axioms (ordering, continuity, and independence), it is appropriate to model his behavior as if he were maximizing EU. For a more complete discussion of the origin of EU theory and a discussion of the axioms, see Schoemaker (1).

h

Christensen-Szalanski and Beach (13) make an even stronger argument, noting that the experimental literature using students is biased (see also ref. 14). Their main contention is that experimental findings of major anomalies have largely used student subjects, whereas those few studies that have employed professionals have usually reported performance more in line with mainstream theory. This point is strengthened given that there are numerous reasons to suspect that professional behavior may differ from non-professional behavior due to training, regulation, etc. (15, 16). Also, see List (17) for the use of experienced players in field experiments testing market theory.

i

Because the only difference between pair wise sets of safe and risky options that are presented to agents (the usual set up for testing the “common consequence effect”) are common to each respective lottery, EU theory suggests that either all safe lotteries, or all risky lotteries, are picked in all lottery choices (or indifference is shown). A common consequence effect is manifest if choices switch systematically between the riskier and safer options. Readers are directed to Machina's (6, 19) pictorial representation of this scenario. Indeed, Machina's use of probability triangles popularized the concept to the extent that the representation is sometimes referred to as the “Machina Triangle.”

j

Alternative theories to EU that can accommodate the Allais paradox include: Generalized Expected Utility Theory (19); Rank Dependent Theory (21, 22), and Prospect Theory (23). However, despite their ability to accommodate the paradox, all theories produce divergent predictions in certain cases (24).

k

We refer to all subjects recruited from the CBOT as traders. However, the 54 traders recruited consisted of locals, brokers, clerks, and exchange employees (e.g., floor managers or market reporters) who worked in the open outcry environment. We found no statistical difference between floor participant types; therefore, we pool participants and collectively call them “traders.” Note that this finding is intuitive because the average non-local/broker had accumulated ≈9 years of floor experience, and many reported to have had several years of experience as either a local or broker. Finally, the average trader (including non-locals/brokers) was involved with ≈537 traded contracts daily.

l

For comparability purposes with respect to treatment 3 data, we also ran an experiment with 46 students that mirrored the trader treatment: these students first took part in treatment 1 or 2 (determined randomly), proceeded through some unrelated experiments for ≈1 h, and then participated in treatment 3 at the end of the session. This procedure produced similar data patterns as those gained from the treatments without learning possibilities, so we suppress further discussion.

References

  • 1.Schoemaker, P. (1982) J. Econ. Lit. 20 529-563. [Google Scholar]
  • 2.Bernoulli, D. (1738) Commentarii Acad. Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae 5 175-192; [Google Scholar]; English translation (1954) Econometrica 22 23-36. [Google Scholar]
  • 3.von Neumann, J. & Morgenstern, O. (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton).
  • 4.Lichtenstein, S., Slovic, P., Fischhoff, B., Layman, M. & Combs, B. (1978) J. Exp. Psychol. 4 551-578. [Google Scholar]
  • 5.Tversky, A. & Kahneman D. (1981) Science 211 453-458. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 6.Machina, M. (1987) J. Econ. Perspect. 1 121-154. [Google Scholar]
  • 7.Starmer, C. & Sugden, R. (1991) Am. Econ. Rev. 81 971-978. [Google Scholar]
  • 8.Baron, J. (1992) Thinking and Deciding (Cambridge Univ. Press, New York).
  • 9.Thaler, R. (1992) The Winner's Curse (Free Press, New York).
  • 10.Plott, C. R. (1996) in The Rational Foundations of Economic Behavior, eds., Arrow, K. J. Colombatto, E., Perlman, M. & Schmidt, C. (MacMillan, Basingstoke, U.K.).
  • 11.List, J. A. (2002) Am. Econ. Rev. 92 1636-1643. [Google Scholar]
  • 12.List, J. A. (2003) Q. J. Econ. 118 41-71. [Google Scholar]
  • 13.Christensen-Szalanski, J. J. & Beach, L. R. (1984) Am. Psychol. 39 75-78. [Google Scholar]
  • 14.Bonner, S. & Pennington, N. (1991) J. Acc. Lit. 10 1-50. [Google Scholar]
  • 15.Burns, P. (1985) in Research in Experimental Economics (JAI Press, Greenwich, CT), pp. 139-157.
  • 16.Holt, C. A. & Villamil, A. P. (1986) in Laboratory Market Research, ed. Moriarity, S. (Univ. of Oklahoma Press, Norman), pp. 80-85.
  • 17.List, J. A. (2002) Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 99 15827-15830. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 18.Allais, M. (1953) Econometrica 21 503-546. [Google Scholar]
  • 19.Machina, M. (1982) Econometrica 50 277-323. [Google Scholar]
  • 20.Holt, C. A. (1986) Am. Econ. Rev. 76 508-515. [Google Scholar]
  • 21.Quiggin, J. (1982) J. Econ. Beh. Org. 3 323-343. [Google Scholar]
  • 22.Yarri, M. (1987) Econometrica 55 95-115. [Google Scholar]
  • 23.Kahneman, D. & Tversky, A. (1979) Econometrica 42 263-291. [Google Scholar]
  • 24.Starmer, C. (1992) Rev. Econ. Stud. 59 813-830. [Google Scholar]
  • 25.Marschak, J. (1951) in Proceedings of the Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability (Univ. of California Press, Berkeley), pp. 493-506.

Articles from Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America are provided here courtesy of National Academy of Sciences

RESOURCES