Skip to main content
NIHPA Author Manuscripts logoLink to NIHPA Author Manuscripts
. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2018 Jul 1.
Published in final edited form as: Annu Rev Sociol. 2017 May 12;43:207–227. doi: 10.1146/annurev-soc-060116-053622

Decision-Making Processes in Social Contexts

Elizabeth Bruch 1, Fred Feinberg 2
PMCID: PMC5543983  NIHMSID: NIHMS876840  PMID: 28785123

Abstract

Over the past half-century, scholars in the interdisciplinary field of Judgment and Decision Making have amassed a trove of findings, theories, and prescriptions regarding the processes ordinary people enact when making choices. But this body of knowledge has had little influence on sociology. Sociological research on choice emphasizes how features of the social environment shape individual behavior, not people’s underlying decision processes. Our aim in this article is to provide an overview of selected ideas, models, and data sources from decision research that can fuel new lines of inquiry on how socially situated actors navigate both everyday and major life choices. We also highlight opportunities and challenges for cross-fertilization between sociology and decision research that can allow the methods, findings, and contexts of each field to expand their joint range of inquiry.

Keywords: heuristics, decision making, micro-sociology, discrete choice

INTRODUCTION

Over the past several decades, there has been an explosion of interest in, and recognition of the importance of, how people make decisions. From Daniel Kahneman’s 2002 Nobel Prize for his work on “Heuristics and Biases,” to the rise in prominence of Behavioral Economics, to the burgeoning policy applications of behavioral “nudges” (Kahneman 2003; Camerer & Loewenstein 2004; Shafir 2013), both scholars and policy makers increasingly focus on choice processes as a key domain of research and intervention. Researchers in the interdisciplinary field of Judgment and Decision Making (JDM)—which primarily comprises cognitive science, behavioral economics, academic marketing, and organizational behavior—have generated a wealth of findings, insights, and prescriptions regarding how people make choices. In addition, with the advent of rich observational data from purchase histories, a related line of work has revolutionized statistical models of decision making that aim to represent underlying choice process.

But for the most part these models and ideas have not penetrated sociology.1 We believe there are several reasons for this. First, JDM research has largely been focused on contrasting how a fully informed, computationally unlimited (i.e., “rational”) person would behave to how people actually behave, and pointing out systematic deviations from this normative model (Loewenstein 2001). Since sociology never fully embraced the rational choice model of behavior, debunking it is less of a disciplinary priority.2 Second, JDM research is best known for its focus on problems that involve risk, where the outcome is probabilistic and the payoff probabilities are known (Kahneman & Tversky 1979, 1982, 1984), and ambiguity, where the outcome is probabilistic and the decision-maker does not have complete information on payoff probabilities (Ellsberg 1961; Einhorn & Hogarth 1988; Camerer & Weber 1992). In both these cases, there is an optimal choice to be made, and the research explores how people’s choices deviate from that answer. But most sociological problems—such as choosing a romantic partner, neighborhood, or college—are characterized by obscurity: there is no single, obvious, optimal, or correct answer.

Perhaps most critically, the JDM literature has by and large minimized the role of social context in decision processes. This is deliberate. Most experiments performed by psychologists are designed to isolate processes that can be connected with features of decision tasks or brain functioning; it is incumbent on researchers working in this tradition to “de-socialize” the environment and reduce it to a single aspect or theoretically predicted confluence of factors. Although there is a rich body of work on how heuristics are matched to particular decision environments (Gigerenzer & Gaissmaier 2011), these environments are by necessity often highly stylized laboratory constructs aimed at exerting control over key features of the environment.3 This line of work intentionally de-emphasizes or eliminates aspects of realistic social environments, which limits its obvious relevance for sociologists.

Finally, there is the challenge of data availability: sociologists typically do not observe the intermediate stages by which people arrive at decision outcomes. For example, researchers can fairly easily determine what college a person attended, what job they chose, or whom they married, but they rarely observe how they got to that decision—that is, how people learned about and evaluated available options, and which options were excluded either because they were infeasible or unacceptable. But such process data can be collected in a number of different ways, as detailed later in this article. Moreover, opportunities to study sociologically relevant decision processes are rapidly expanding, owing to the advent of disintermediated sources like the Internet and smart phones, which allow researchers to observe human behavior at a much finer level of temporal and geographic granularity than ever before. Equally important, these data often contain information on which options people considered, but ultimately decided against. Such activity data provide a rich source of information on sociologically relevant decision processes (Bruch et al. 2016).

We believe that the time is ripe for a new line of work that draws on insights from cognitive science and decision theory to examine choice processes and how they play out in social environments. As we discuss in the next section, sociology and decision research offer complementary perspectives on decision-making and there is much to be gained from combining them. One benefit of this union is that it can deepen sociologists’ understanding of how and why individual outcomes differ across contexts. By leveraging insights on how contextual factors and aspects of choice problems influence decision strategies, sociologists can better pinpoint how, why, and when features of the social environment trigger and shape human behavior. This also presents a unique opportunity for cross-fertilization. While sociologists can draw from the choice literature’s rich understanding of and suite of tools to probe decision processes, work on decision-making can also benefit from sociologists’ insights into how social context enables or constrains behavior.

The literature on judgment and decision-making is enormous; our goal here is to offer a curated introduction aimed at social scientists new to this area. In addition to citing recent studies, we deliberately reference the classic and integrative literature in this field so that researchers can acquaint themselves with the works that introduced these ideas, and gain a comfortable overview to it. We highlight empirical studies of decision making that help address how people make critical life decisions, such as choosing a neighborhood, college, life partner, or occupation. Thus, our focus is on research that is relevant for understanding decision processes characterized by obscurity, where there is no obvious correct or optimal answer. Due to its selective nature, our review does not include a discussion of several major areas of the JDM literature, most notably Prospect Theory, which focuses on how people can distort both probabilities and outcome values when these are known (to the researcher) with certainty; we also do not discuss the wide range of anomalies documented in human cognition, for example mental accounting, the endowment effect, and biases such as availability or anchoring (Tversky & Kahneman 1973; Kahneman & Tversky 1973, 1981; Kahneman et al. 1991).

The balance of the article is as follows. We first explain how decision research emerged as a critique of rational choice theory, and show how these models of behavior complement existing work on action and decision-making in sociology. The core of the paper provides an overview of how cognitive, emotional, and contextual factors shape decision processes. We then introduce the data and methods commonly used to study choice processes. Decision research relies on a variety of data sources, including results from lab and field experiments, surveys, brain scans, and observations of in-store shopping and other behavior. We discuss their relative merits, and provide a brief introduction to statistical modeling approaches. We close with some thoughts about opportunities and challenges for sociologists wanting to incorporate insights and methods from the decision literature into their research programs.

SOCIOLOGICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL PERSEPCTIVES ON DECISION PROCESSES

To understand how sociology and psychology offer distinct but complementary views of decision processes, we begin with a brief introduction to the dominant model of human decision-making in the social sciences: rational choice theory. This model, endemic to neoclassical economic analyses, has permeated into many fields including sociology, anthropology, political science, philosophy, history, and law (Coleman 1991; Gely & Spiller 1990; Satz & Ferejohn 1994; Levy 1997). In its classic form, the rational choice model of behavior assumes that decision makers have full knowledge of the relevant aspects of their environment, a stable set of preferences for evaluating choice alternatives, and unlimited skill in computation (Samuelson 1947; Von Neumann & Morgenstern 2007; Becker 1993). Actors are assumed to have a complete inventory of possible alternatives of action; there is no allowance for focus of attention or a search for new alternatives (Simon 1991, p. 4). Indeed, a distinguishing feature of the classic model is its lack of attention to the process of decision-making. Preference maximization is a synonym for choice (McFadden 2001, p. 77).

Rational choice has a long tradition in sociology, but its popularity increased in the 1980s and 1990s, partly as a response to concern within sociology about the growing gap between social theory and quantitative empirical research (Coleman 1986). Quantitative data analysis, despite focusing primarily on individual-level outcomes, is typically conducted without any reference to—let alone a model of—individual action (Goldthorpe 1996; Esser 1996). Rational choice provides a theory of action that can anchor empirical research in meaningful descriptions of individuals’ behavior (Hedström & Swedberg 1996). Importantly, the choice behavior of rational actors can also be straightforwardly implemented in regression-based models readily available in statistical software packages. Indeed while some scholars explicitly embrace rational choice as a model of behavior (Hechter and Kanazawa 1997; Kroneberg and Kalter 2012), many others implicitly adopt it in their quantitative models of individual behavior.

Beyond Rational Choice

Sociologists have critiqued and extended the classical rational choice model in a number of ways. They have observed that people are not always selfish actors who behave in their own best interests (England 1989; Margolis 1982), that preferences are not fixed characteristics of individuals (Lindenberg and Frey 1993; Munch 1992), and that individuals do not always behave in ways that are purposive or optimal (Somers 1989; Vaughan 1998). Most relevant to this article, sociologists have argued that the focus in classical rational choice on the individual as the primary unit of decision-making represents a fundamentally asocial representation of behavior. In moving beyond rational choice, theories of decision-making in sociology highlight the importance of social interactions and relationships in shaping behavior (Pescosolido 1992; Emirbayer 1997). A large body of empirical work reveals how social context shapes people’s behavior across a wide range of domains, from neighborhood and school choice to decisions about friendship and intimacy to choices about eating, drinking, and other health-related behaviors (Carrillo et al. 2016; Perna and Titus 2005; Small 2009; Pachucki et al. 2011; Rosenquist et al. 2010).

But This focus on social environments and social interactions has inevitably led to less attention being paid to the individual-level processes that underlie decision-making. In contrast, psychologists and decision theorists aiming to move beyond rational choice have focused their attention squarely on how individuals make decisions. In doing so, they have amassed several decades of work showing that the rational choice model is a poor representation of this process.4 Their fundamental critique is that decision-making, as envisioned in the rational choice paradigm, would make overwhelming demands on our capacity to process information (Bettman 1979; Miller 1956; Payne 1976). Decision-makers have limited time for learning about choice alternatives, limited working memory, and limited computational capabilities (Miller 1956; Payne et al.1993) As a result, they use heuristics that keep the information-processing demands of a task within the bounds of their limited cognitive capacity.5 It is now widely recognized that the central process in human problem solving is to apply heuristics that carry out highly selective navigations of problem spaces (Newell & Simon 1972).

However, in their efforts to zero in on the strategies people use to gather and process information, psychological studies of decision-making have focused largely on individuals in isolation. Thus, sociological and psychological perspectives on choice are complementary in that they each emphasize a feature of decision-making that the other field has left largely undeveloped. For this reason, and as we articulate further in the conclusion, we believe there is great potential for cross-fertilization between these areas of research. Because our central aim is to introduce sociologists to the JDM literature, we do not provide an exhaustive discussion of sociological work relevant to understanding decision processes. Rather, we highlight studies that illustrate the fruitful connections between sociological concerns and JDM research.

In the next sections, we discuss the role of different factors—cognitive, emotional, and contextual—in heuristic decision processes.

THE ROLE OF COGNITIVE FACTORS IN DECISION PROCESSES

There are two major challenges in processing decision-related information: first, each choice is typically characterized by multiple attributes, and no alternative is optimal on all dimensions; and, second, more than a tiny handful of information can overwhelm the cognitive capacity of decision makers (Cowan 2010). Consider the problem of choosing among three competing job offers. Job 1 has high salary, but a moderate commuting time and a family-unfriendly workplace. Job 2 offers a low salary, but has a family-friendly workplace and short commuting time. Job 3 has a family-friendly workplace but a moderate salary and long commuting time. This choice would be easy if one alternative clearly dominated on all attributes. But, as is often the case, they all involve making tradeoffs and require the decision maker to weigh the relative importance of each attribute. Now imagine that, instead of three choices, there were ten, a hundred, or even a thousand potential alternatives. This illustrates the cognitive challenge faced by people trying to decide among neighborhoods, potential romantic partners, job opportunities, or health care plans.

We focus in this section on choices that involve deliberation, for example deciding where to live, what major to pursue in college, or what jobs to apply for.6 (This is in contrast to decisions that are made more spontaneously, such as the choice to disclose personal information to a confidant [Small & Sukhu 2016].) Commencing with the pioneering work of Howard & Sheth (1969), scholars have accumulated substantial empirical evidence for the idea that such decisions are typically made sequentially, with each stage reducing the set of potential options (Swait 1984; Roberts & Lattin 1991, 1997). For a given individual, the set of potential options can first be divided into the set that he or she knows about, and those of which he or she is unaware. This “awareness set” is further divided into options the person would consider, and those that are irrelevant or unattainable. This smaller set is referred to as the consideration set, and the final decision is restricted to options within that set.

Research in consumer behavior suggests that the decision to include certain alternatives in the consideration set can be based on markedly different heuristics and criteria than the final choice decision (e.g., Payne 1976; Bettman & Park 1980; Salisbury & Feinberg 2012). In many cases, people use simple rules to restrict the energy involved in searching for options, or to eliminate options from future consideration. For example, a high school student applying to college may only consider schools within commuting distance of home, or schools where someone she knows has attended. Essentially, people favor less cognitively taxing rules that use a small number of choice attributes earlier in the decision process to eliminate almost all potential alternatives, but take into account a wider range of choice attributes when evaluating the few remaining alternatives for the final decision (Liu & Dukes 2013).

Once the decision maker has narrowed down his or her options, the final choice decision may allow different dimensions of alternatives to be compensatory; in other words, a less attractive value on one attribute may be offset by a more attractive value on another attribute. However, a large body of decision research demonstrates that strategies to screen potential options for consideration are non-compensatory; a decision-maker’s choice to eliminate from or include for consideration based on one attribute will not be compensated by the value of other attributes. In other words, compensatory decision rules are “continuous,” while non-compensatory decision rules are discontinuous or threshold (Swait 2001; Gilbride & Allenby 2004).

Compensatory Decision Rules

The implicit decision rule used in statistical models of individual choice and the normative decision rule for rational choice is the weighted additive rule. Under this choice regime, decision-makers compute a weighted sum of all relevant attributes of potential alternatives. Choosers develop an overall assessment of each choice alternative by multiplying the attribute weight by the attribute level (for each salient attribute), and then sum over all attributes. This produces a single utility value for each alternative. The alternative with the highest value is selected, by assumption. Any conflict in values is assumed to be confronted and resolved by explicitly considering the extent to which one is willing to trade off attribute values, as reflected by the relative importance or beta coefficients (Payne et al. 1993, p. 24). Using this rule involves substantial computational effort and processing of information.

A simpler compensatory decision rule is the tallying rule, known to most of us as a “pro and con” list (Alba & Marmorstein 1987). This strategy ignores information about the relative importance of each attribute. To implement this heuristic, a decision maker decides which attribute values are desirable or undesirable. Then she counts up the number desirable versus undesirable attributes. Strictly speaking, this rule forces people to make trade-offs among different attributes. However, it is less cognitively demanding than the weighted additive rule, as it does not require people to specify precise weights associated with each attribute. But both rules require people to examine all information for each alternative, determine the sums associated with each alternative, and compare those sums.

Non-Compensatory Decision Rules

Non-compensatory decision rules do not require decision makers to explicitly consider all salient attributes of an alternative, assign numeric weights to each attribute, or compute weighted sums in one’s head. Thus they are far less cognitively taxing than compensatory rules. The decision maker need only examine the attributes that define cutoffs in order to make a decision (to exclude options for a conjunctive rule, or to include them for a disjunctive one). The fewer attributes that are used to evaluate a choice alternative, the less taxing the rule will be.

Conjunctive rules require that an alternative must be acceptable on one or more salient attributes. For example, in the context of residential choice, a house that is unaffordable will never be chosen, no matter how attractive it is. Similarly, a man looking for romantic partners on an online dating website may only search for women who are within a 25-mile radius and do not have children. Potential partners who are unacceptable on either dimension are eliminated from consideration. So conjunctive screening rules identify “deal-breakers”; being acceptable on all dimensions is a necessary but not sufficient criterion for being chosen.

A disjunctive rule dictates that an alternative is considered if at least one of its attributes is acceptable to chooser i. For example, a sociology department hiring committee may always interview candidates with four or more American Journal of Sociology publications, regardless of their teaching record or quality of recommendations. Similarly (an especially evocative yet somewhat fanciful example), a disjunctive rule might occur for the stereotypical “gold-digger” or “gigolo,” who targets all potential mates with very high incomes regardless of their other qualities. Disjunctive heuristics are also known as “take-the-best” or “one good reason” heuristics that base their decision on a single overriding factor, ignoring all other attributes of decision outcomes (Gigerenzer & Goldstein 1999; Gigerenzer & Gaissmaier 2011; Gigerenzer 2008).

While sociologists studying various forms of deliberative choice do not typically identify the decision rules used, a handful of empirical studies demonstrate that people do not consider all salient attributes of all potential choice alternatives. For example, Krysan and Bader (2009) find that white Chicago residents have pronounced neighborhood “blind spots” that essentially restrict their knowledge of the city to a small number of ethnically homogeneous neighborhoods. Daws and Brown (2002 Daws and Brown (2004) find that, when choosing a college, UK students’ awareness and choice sets differ systematically by socioeconomic status. Finally, in a recent study of online mate choice, Bruch and colleagues (2016) build on insights from marketing and decision research to develop a statistical model that allows for multistage decision processes with different (potentially noncompensatory) decision rules at each stage. They find that conjunctive screeners are common at the initial stage of online mate pursuit, and precise cutoffs differ by gender and other factors.

THE ROLE OF EMOTIONAL FACTORS IN DECISION PROCESSES

Early decision research emphasized the role of cognitive processes in decision-making (e.g., Newell & Simon 1972). But more recent work shows that emotions—not just strong emotions like anger and fear, but also “faint whispers of emotions” known as affect (Slovic et al. 2004, p. 312)—play an important role in decision-making. Decisions are cast with a certain valence, and this shapes the choice process on both conscious and unconscious levels. In other words, even seemingly deliberative decisions, like what school to attend or job to take, may be made not just through careful processing of information, but based on intuitive judgments of how a particular outcome feels (Loewenstein & Lerner 2003; Lerner et al. 2015). This is true even in situations where there is numeric information about the likelihood of certain events (Denes-Raj & Epstein 1994; Windschitl & Weber 1999; Slovic et al. 2000). This section focuses on two topics central to this area: first, that people dislike making emotional tradeoffs, and will go to great lengths to avoid them; and second, how emotional factors serve as direct inputs into decision processes.7

Emotions Shape Strategies for Processing Information

In the previous section, we emphasized that compensatory decision rules that involve tradeoffs require a great deal of cognitive effort. But there are other reasons why people avoid making explicit tradeoffs on choice attributes. For one, some tradeoffs are more emotionally difficult than others, for example the decision whether to stay at home with one’s children or put them in day care. Some choices also involve attributes that are considered sacred or protected (Baron & Spranca 1997). People prefer not to make these emotionally difficult tradeoffs, and that shapes decision strategy selection (Hogarth 1991; Baron 1986; Baron & Spranca 1997). Experiments on these types of emotional decisions have shown that, when facing emotionally difficult decisions, decision-makers avoid compensatory evaluation and instead select the alternative that is most attractive on whatever dimension is difficult to trade off (Luce et al. 2001; Luce et al. 1999). Thus, the emotional valence of specific options shapes decision strategies.

Emotions concerning the set of all choice alternatives—specifically, whether they are perceived as overall favorable or unfavorable—also affects strategy selection. Early work with rats suggests that decisions are relatively easy when choosing between two desirable options with no downsides (Miller 1959). However, when deciding between options with both desirable and undesirable attributes, the choice becomes harder. When deciding between two undesirable options, the choice is hardest of all. Subsequent work reveals that this finding extends to human choice. For instance, people invoke different choice strategies when forced to choose “the lesser of two evils.” In their experiments on housing choice, Luce and colleagues (2000) found that when faced with a set of substandard options, people are far more likely to engage in “maximizing” behavior and select the alternative with the best value on whatever is perceived as the dominant substandard feature. In other words, having a suboptimal choice set reduces the likelihood of tradeoffs on multiple attributes. Extending this idea to a different sociological context, a woman confronted with a dating pool filled with what she perceives as arrogant men may focus her attention on selecting the least arrogant of the group.

Emotions as Information

Emotions also serve as direct inputs into the decision process. A large body of work on perceptions of risk shows that a key way people evaluate the risks and benefits of a given situation is through their emotional response (Slovic et al. 2004; Slovic and Peters 2006; Loewenstein et al. 2001). In a foundational and generative study, Fischhoff et al. (1978) discovered that people’s perceptions of risks decline as perceived benefits increase. This is puzzling, because risks and benefits tend to be positively correlated. The authors also noted that the attribute most highly correlated with perceived risk was the extent to which the item in question evoked a feeling of dread. This finding has been confirmed in many other studies (e.g., McDaniels et al. 1997). Subsequent work also showed that this inverse relationship is linked to the strength of positive or negative affect associated with the stimulus. In other words, stronger negative responses led to perception of greater risk and lower benefits (Alhakami & Slovic 1994; Slovic & Peters 2006).

This has led to a large body of work on the affect heuristic, which is grounded in the idea that people have positive and negative associations with different stimuli, and they consult this “affect pool” when making judgments. This shortcut is often more efficient and easier than cognitive strategies such as weighing pros and cons or even disjunctive rules for evaluating the relative merits of each choice outcome (Slovic et al. 2004). Affect— particularly how it relates to decision-making—is rooted in dual process accounts of human behavior. The basic idea is that people experience the world in two different ways: one that is fast, intuitive, automatic, and unconscious, and another that is slow, analytical, deliberate, and verbal (Evans 2008; Kahneman 2011). A defining characteristic of the intuitive, automatic system is its affective basis (Epstein 1994). Indeed, affective reactions to stimuli are often the very first reactions people have. Having determined what is salient in a given situation, affect thus guides subsequent processes, such as information processing, that are central to cognition (Zajonc 1980).

Over the past two decades, sociologists—particularly in the study of culture—have incorporated insights from dual process theory to understand how actions may be both deliberate and automatic (e.g., Vaisey 2009). Small and Sukhu (2016) argue that dual processes may play an important role in the mobilization of support networks. Kroneberg and Esser (Kroneberg 2014; Esser and Kroneberg 2015) explore how automatic and deliberative processes shape how people select the “frame” for making sense of a particular situation. Although some scholars debate whether automatic and deliberative processes are more like polar extremes or a smooth spectrum (for an example of this critique within sociology, see Leschziner and Green 2013), the dual process model remains a useful framework for theorizing about behavior.

THE ROLE OF CONTEXTUAL FACTORS IN DECISION PROCESSES

Sociologists have long been interested in how social environments—for example, living in a poor neighborhood, attending an affluent school, or growing up in a single-parent household—shape life outcomes such as high school graduation, non-marital fertility, and career aspirations (Sharkey and Faber 2014; Lee et al. 1993; Astone and McLanahan 1991). Social environments shape behavior directly through various forms of influence such as peer pressure and social learning, and indirectly by dictating what opportunities or social positions are available (Blalock 1984; Manski 2000; Schelling 1971). But while the sociological literature on contextual effects is vast, the subset of that work which focuses on decisions emphasizes the causes or consequences of those decisions more than the processes through which they are made.

Decision researchers devote considerable attention to contextual effects, but typically “context” in this field refers to architectural features of choice environments such as the number of alternatives; whether time pressures limit the effort that can be put into a decision; and what option is emphasized as the default. (In the world, of course, these features are socially determined. But this is less emphasized in decision research, much of which occurs in a laboratory setting.) The overwhelming finding from these studies is that people’s choices are highly sensitive to context. This insight has led to an influential literature on the “Construction of Preferences” (see Sidebar) as well as a great deal of interest in policy interventions that manipulate features of choice environments (Thaler and Sunstein 2008; Shafir 2013). Recently, decision researchers have begun to look at how decisions are shaped by more explicitly social environments such as poverty (e.g., Mullainathan and Shafir 2013). In this section, we discuss how four aspects of social context—what opportunities are available, the importance of the “default” option, time pressure and constrained resources, and the choices of others—shape decision processes.

Choice Sets and Defaults

A classic assumption of conventional choice models is that the ratio of choice probabilities for any two options is independent of what other options are available (Luce 1959). (In the literature on statistical models of choice, this is known as the principle of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives [IIA].) But it is well established that people’s choices depend heavily on the relative merits of a particular set of options rather than their absolute values (Tversky & Simonson 1993). For example, people tend to avoid more extreme values in alternatives (the “compromise effect”); thus, adding a new option to the mix can lead choosers to shift their views about what constitutes a reasonable choice (Simonson 1989; Simonson & Tversky 1992). In a similar vein, a robust finding is that adding a new “asymmetrically dominated” alternative – one dominated by some items in the set but not by others – can actually increase the choice probabilities of the items that dominate it. Such a “decoy effect” (Huber et al. 1982) should be impossible under IIA, and in fact violates regularity (i.e., new items cannot increase probabilities of existing ones). Both of these effects have been attributed to the fact that people making choices are trying to justify them based on reasons (Simonson 1989; Dhar et al. 2000); changing the distribution of options may alter how compelling a particular reason might be.

Choice outcomes are also highly influenced by what option is identified as the “default.” Defaults are whatever happens in a decision if the chooser “decides not to decide” (Feinberg & Huber 1996). Defaults exert a strong effect on people’s choices, even when the stakes of the decision are high (Johnson et al. 1993; Johnson & Goldstein 2013). Defaults also tap into other, well-established features of human decision making: procrastination, bias for the status quo, and inertial behavior (Samuelson & Zeckhauser 1988; Kahneman et al. 1991). In recent years, manipulating the default option—for example making retirement savings or organ donation something people opt out of rather than opt into—has been identified as a potentially low cost, highly impact policy intervention (Shafir 2013). Defaults are also of potentially great sociological interest. A number of sociological studies have theorized about how people “drift” into particular outcomes or situations (e.g., Matza 1967); defaults exist in part because choices are embedded in specific environments that emphasize one set of options over others.8

Scarcity and Social Influence

A number of recent studies examine how conditions of scarcity—with regard to time, resources, and energy—shape decision-making. Consistent with studies of cognitive effort and decision-making, a variety of experimental results demonstrate that time pressure reduces people’s tendency to make tradeoffs (Wright & Weitz 1977; Edland 1989; Rieskamp & Hoffrage 2008). This finding is especially interesting in light of recent line of work by Shah et al. (2015), who show via experiments that resource scarcity forces people to make tradeoffs, e.g., “If I buy dessert, I can’t afford to take the bus home.” Weighing tradeoffs is cognitively costly; they deplete people’s resources for other decision tasks, which overall reduces their ability to engage in deliberative decision-making (Pocheptsova et al. 2009). Given the fact that people living in conditions of extreme scarcity are typically limited in both time and financial resources, a cognitive perspective suggests that they are “doubly taxed” in terms of cognitive effort, and offers important insights in understanding how conditions of poverty shape, and are shaped by, people’s choices (Bertrand et al. 2004). In short, the context of poverty depletes people’s cognitive resources in an environment where mistakes are costly (Mullainathan & Shafir 2013, Gennetian & Shafir 2015).

There are also a small number of studies that examine how the actions of other people influence decision processes. They focus on the role of descriptive norms (Cialdini 2003; Cialdini & Goldstein 2004), which are information about what other people are doing. The key finding is that people are more likely to adopt a particular behavior—such as conserving energy in one’s home or avoiding changing sheets and towels at a hotel—if they learn that others are doing the same (Goldstein et al. 2008; Nolan et al. 2008). The more similar the comparison situation is to one’s own, the more powerful the effect of others’ behavior on one’s own. For instance, people are more likely to be influenced if the descriptive norm references their neighbors or others who share social spaces (Schultz et al. 2007). The finding that descriptive norms are most powerful when they are immediate is reinforced by a study of charitable giving, which shows that people’s behavior is disproportionately influenced by information about what others have given, especially the most recent, non-specified donor (Shang & Croson 2009).

This work on social influence is consistent with a classic literature in sociology that emphasizes how people’s beliefs about the sort of situation they are in shape their behavior (e.g., Thomas & Znaniecki 1918; Goffman 1974). Social cues provide information about what choices are consistent with desired or appropriate behavior. For example, a classic study demonstrates that whether a Prisoner’s dilemma game was presented to research subjects as a simulated “Wall Street” or “Community” shaped subsequent playing decisions (Liberman et al. 2004; Camerer & Thaler 1993). In other words, there is an interpretive component to decision-making that informs one’s views about the kind of response that is appropriate.

STUDYING DECISION PROCESSES

Psychologists have devised a number of techniques to shed light on human decision processes in conjunction with targeted stimuli. Process tracing is a venerated suite of methods broadly aimed at extracting how people go about acquiring, integrating, and evaluating information, as well as physiological, neurological, and concomitants of cognitive processes (Svenson 1979; Schulte-Mecklenbeck et al. 2010). (Note that this approach is quite different from what political scientists and sociologists typically refer to as process tracing [Mahoney 2012; Collier 2011].) In a classic study, Lohse & Johnson (1996) examine individual-level information acquisition using both computerized tracing and eye-tracking across multiple process measures (e.g., total time, number of fixations, accuracy, etc.)

More recently, the use of unobtrusive eye-trackers has allowed researchers to discern which information is being sought and assimilated in the sort of stimuli-rich environments that typify online interactions, without querying respondents’ knowledge or intermediate goals (Duchowski 2007, Wedel & Pieters 2008). Also, it has recently become possible to use neuroimaging techniques like PET, EEG, and fMRI (Yoon et al. 2006) to observe decision processes in vivo, although at a high cost of invasiveness. Such studies offer the benefit of sidestepping questions about, for example, the emotional reactions experienced by decision-makers, by observing which portions of the brain are active when information is being accessed and processed, as well as final decisions arrived at.

Stated and Revealed Preferences

While not directly focused on the process of decision-making (i.e., in terms of identifying decision strategies), a large literature assumes a linear compensatory model and aims to capture the weights people ascribe to different choice attributes (see Louviere et al. 1999 for a broad overview; also Train 2009). These methods, long known to social scientists (Samuelson 1948; Manski and McFadden 1981; Bruch and Mare 2012), rely on both field data—where the analyst records decision-makers’ “revealed preferences” as reflected in their actions—and choice experiments, where analysts enact control over key elements of the decision environment through vignettes. Stated choice experiments have two advantages that are relevant in modeling choice processes: their ability to (1) present decision-makers with options unavailable in practice or outside their usual purview; and (2) record multiple (hypothetical) choices for each decision-maker, even for scenarios like mate choice or home purchase that are made few times in a lifespan. The downside is that they are difficult to fully contextualize or make incentive-compatible; for example, experiment participants are routinely more willing to spend simulated experimental money than their own hard-won cash (Carlsson & Martinsson 2001).

Among the main statistical methods for enacting choice experiments is conjoint analysis (Green and Srinivasan 1978, Green et al. 2001), a broad suite of techniques, implemented widely in dedicated software (e.g., Sawtooth), to measure stated preferences and how they vary across a target population. Conjoint works by decomposing options into their attributes, each of which can have several levels. For example, housing options each provide cooking facilities, sleeping quarters, bathrooms, among other attributes, and each of these varies in terms of their quality levels (e.g., larger vs. smaller; number overall; and categorical attributes like type of heating, color, location, etc.) The goal of conjoint is to assign a utility or part-worth to each level of each attribute, with higher numbers representing more preferred attribute levels; for example, one might say that, for families with several children, a home with four bedrooms has a much higher utility than one with two. Conjoint approaches can be—and have been (Wittink & Cattin 1989; Wittink et al. 1994)—applied to a wide range of settings where it is useful to measure the importance of specific choice attributes.

Field data such as residential, work, or relationship histories have the advantage of reflecting actual choices made in real contexts (Louviere et al. 1999). However, such data suffer from several drawbacks: (1) variables necessarily covary (i.e., higher neighborhood prices correlate with levels of many attributes at once); (2) we cannot infer how people would respond to possible novel options, like affordable, diverse neighborhoods that may not yet exist; and (3) each person typically makes just one choice. Such problems are exacerbated when researchers cannot in principle know the entire “consideration set” of options available and actively mulled over by each decision-maker, which is typically the case in sociological applications.9 When such confounds are present in field data, conjoint and other experimental methods allow researchers to control and “orthogonalize” the attributes and levels used in choice experiments, to achieve maximal efficiency and avoid presenting each participant with more than a couple of dozen hypothetical choice scenarios (Chrzan & Orme 2000).10

Two other choice assessment methods deserve brief mention, as they leverage some of the best features of experimental and field research: natural experiments and field experiments. In a natural experiment, an event exogenous to the outcome of interest affects only certain individuals, or affects different individuals to varying degrees. One example is the effect of natural disasters, like the 2005 flooding of New Orleans in the aftermath of Hurricane Katrina, on migration decisions (Kirk 2009). In field experiments, researchers exert control over focal aspects of people’s choice environments. Although it may seem difficult to study sociologically relevant choice processes this way, the use of web sites as search tools enables a nontrivial degree of experimental control over choice environments (see, for example, Bapna et al. 2016).

Statistical Models of Choice Processes

The bedrock formulation of statistical analyses of choice is the random utility model, which posits that each option available to a decision-maker affords a certain value (“utility”), which can be decomposed into that explicable by the analyst and a (“random”) error (Ben-Akiva & Lerman 1985; Train 2009).11 The former can be related through regression-based techniques to other observed covariates on the options, decision-maker, and environment, whereas the latter can be due to systematically unavailable information (e.g., income or education) or intrinsic unobservables (e.g., the mood of the decision-maker). Of particular importance is McFadden’s conditional logit model (McFadden 1973),12 which allows attributes of options to vary across choice occasions (e.g., prices or waiting times for different transportation modes; neighborhoods or room sizes for renting vs. buying a home; etc.) Because this model is supported in much commercial statistical software, and converges rapidly even for large data sets, it is by far the most widely deployed in choice applications.

Statistical models of choice have been grounded primarily in rational utility theory, with concessions towards efficient estimation. As such, the utility specifications underlying such models have tended to be linear, to include all available options, and incorporate full information on those options. Much research reveals not only the psychological process accuracy, but the statistical superiority, of relaxing these assumptions by incorporating limits on information, cognitive penalties, and nonlinear/noncompensatory utility. For example, the formal incorporation of consideration sets into choice modeling (Horowitz, & Louviere 1995; Louviere, Hensher, & Swait 2000, section 10.3) has demonstrated superior fit and predictive accuracy for explicit models of exclusion of certain options from detailed processing, with some analyses (see Hauser & Wernerfelt 1990) attributing in excess of 75% of the choice model’s fit to such restrictions. Similarly, lab studies have confirmed that decision-makers wish to conserve cognitive resources, and formal statistical models (e.g., Shugan 1980, Roberts & Lattin 1991) have attempted to account for and measure a “cost of thinking” or consideration from real-world data.

However, despite a decades-deep literature on noncompensatory evaluation processes (Einhorn 1970), the practical estimation of such models is largely in its infancy, due to complexities of specification and data needs (e.g., Elrod et al. 2004). Although nonlinearity can be captured using polynomial functions of covariates, these impose smoothness of response; by contrast, conjunctive and disjunctive processes impose cutoffs beyond which evaluation is either wholly positive or insurmountably negative (Bruch et al., 2016). We view the development of this area as critical to the widespread acceptance of formal choice models to social scientists and sociologists in particular, who typically wish to know which neighborhoods we would never live in, jobs we would never take, etc.

CHALLENGES AND OPPORTUNITIES FOR FUTURE RESEARCH

Sociology has long been interested in individuals’ choices and their implications for social life, and there is renewed interest in theories that can explain human action (e.g., Kroneberg 2014; Gross 2009). Our hope is that this review enables interested scholars to pursue a more nuanced and structurally accurate representation of the choice process. Greater insight into human behavior will also allow for greater insights into the dynamic relationship between micro- and meso-level processes and their larger-scale implications (Hedstrom and Bearman 2009). Consider how choice sets are constructed in the first place. People may rule out certain options due to preferences, affordability and/or time constraints—classic cognitive, temporal, and economic variables—but also the anticipation of unfair treatment or discrimination. For example, a high school student searching for colleges may eliminate those that are too expensive, too far from home, or are perceived as unwelcoming. Identifying the criteria through which people rule themselves (or others) out can illuminate more precise mechanisms through which people’s actions shape, and are shaped by, larger-scale inequality structures.

We also believe that many of the data limitations that hampered sociologists’ ability to study decision processes in the past are becoming far less of an issue. This is due at least in part to increasingly available data sources that can aid sociologists in studying choice processes. These so-called “big data” are often behavioral data: specific actions taken by individuals that can shed light on processes of information search, assimilation, and choice. Moreover, the online environments through which we increasingly communicate and interact enable not only observational “field” data, but also targeted, unobtrusive experiments where the decision environment is directly altered. The latter possibility offers greater precision than ever before in isolating both idiosyncratic and potentially universal features of behavior, as well as better understanding the interplay between context and human action.

However, existing approaches from marketing and psychology are often not suited to sociological inquiry directly out of the box, creating both challenges and opportunities for future work. For example, most extant models were designed to capture more prosaic decisions, like supermarket shopping, where attributes are known, options are stable, and “stakes” are modest. Although some choices of sociological interest may fit this pattern, most do not. For example, many pivotal life decisions—purchasing a home (where sellers and buyers must agree on terms); college admissions; dating and marriage decisions; employment offers—require a partnership, wherein each decision maker must “choose you back.” Sociologists must therefore be circumspect in applying models developed for choice among “inert” options (such as flavors of yogurt) to the data they most commonly analyze.

The fact that so many sociological choices are characterized by obscurity (i.e., there is no obvious or single optimal choice to be made) is also a good reason to proceed with caution in applying ideas from JDM to sociological research. Take, for example, the literature discussed earlier on interventions that manipulate people’s default option. It is one thing to encourage healthier eating by putting apples before chocolate cake in the cafeteria line; it is quite another to nudge someone towards a particular neighborhood or school. Sociologists rarely have a clear sense of what choice will be optimal for a group of people, let alone particular individuals. On the other hand, few would argue that growing up surrounded by violence isn’t universally harmful (Harding 2009; Sharkey et al. 2013). Policies can only be improved by a more nuanced understanding of how choices unfold in particular environments, and how the default options are shaped by contextual factors.

Thus, this challenge also creates the opportunity to build knowledge on how heuristics operate under conditions of obscurity. JDM research has largely focused on documenting whether and how heuristics fall short of some correct or optimal answer. In sociology, by contrast, we typically lack a defensible metric for the “suboptimality” of decisions. While some decisions may be worse than others, it is impossible to know, for example, whether one has chosen the “right” spouse or peer group, or how to set up appropriate counterfactual scenarios as yardsticks against which specific decisions could be dispassionately assessed. By branching into decision domains where the quality or optimality of outcomes cannot be easily quantified (or in some cases even coherently conceptualized), sociologists can not only actively extend the range of applications of decision research, but also break new theoretical ground.

SIDEBAR 1: THE CONSTRUCTION OF PREFERENCES.

Decision researchers have amassed several lines of evidence to suggest that, rather than being stable constructs that are retrieved on demand, preferences are constructed in the moment of elicitation (Lichtenstein & Slovic 2006; Bettman, Luce, and Payne 1998). This finding is echoed in studies of judgments and attitudes, which are also sensitive to contextual cues (Ross and Nisbett 1991; Schwarz 1999, 2007). Preference variation can be generated from simple anchors or changes in question wording (e.g., Mandel & Johnson 2002). A classic finding is that people exhibit preference reversals when making multiattribute choices; in one context they indicate a preference of A over B, but in another context they indicate they prefer B over A (e.g., Cox & Grether 1996; Seidl 2002). Several theories have been put forward to explain this effect (see Lichtenstein & Slovic 2006, Chapter 1 for a review and synthesis). One explanation is that people’s preferences, attitudes, judgments reflect what comes to mind; and what is salient at one time point may not be salient at another (Higgins 1996; Schwarz, Strack, and Mai 1991).

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Scott Rick Mario Small, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful feedback on this manuscript. This work was supported by a training grant (K01-HD-079554) from the National Institute of Child and Human Developent

Footnotes

1

A notable exception is Herb Simon’s concept of “satisficing,” which many influential sociological works—especially in the subfield of economic sociology—have incorporated into models of action and behavior (e.g., Baker 1984; Granovetter 1985; Uzzi 1997; Beckert 1996).

2

Although rational choice has had a strong influence sociological research—for example, Coleman’s (1994) Foundations of Social Theory has almost 30,000 citations and there is a journal, Rationality and Society, devoted to related topics—this framework never overtook the discipline as it did economics.

3

While this is accurate as a broad characterization, there are studies that examine decision-making “in the wild” through observation or field experiments (e.g., Camerer 2004; Barberis 2013).

4

The best-known critique of the rational choice model within JDM comes from the “Heuristics and Biases” school of research (Tversky 1972; Kahneman & Tversky 1979; Tversky & Kahneman 1981). Their studies show that decision makers: (1) have trouble processing information; (2) use decision-making heuristics that do not maximize preferences; (3) are sensitive to context and process; and (4) systematically misperceive features of their environment. Since then, a large body of work provides convincing evidence that individuals are “limited information processing systems” (Newell & Simon 1972; Kahneman 2003).

5

Heuristics are “problem-solving methods that tend to produce efficient solutions to difficult problems by restricting the search through the space of possible solutions, on the basis of some evaluation of the structure of the problem” (Braunstein 1972, p. 520).

6

The decision strategies presented in this section are sometimes known as “reasons” heuristics (c.f., Gigerenzer 2004) because they are the reasons people give for why they chose the way that they did. As such, they are less applicable in situations where people have few if any options. For example, a person evicted from their home may have a single alternative to homelessness: staying with a family member. In this case, the difficulty of the decision is not information processing.

7

There is a rich literature in sociology on how emotions are inputs to and outcomes of social processes (e.g., Hochschild 1975; Scheff 1988). While this work has not historically been integrated with psychology (Turner and Stets 2014, p. 2), this may be a fruitful direction for future research.

8

We are grateful for conversations with Rob Sampson and Mario Small that led to this insight.

9

Newer online data sources—for example, websites for housing search and dating—generate highly granular, intermediate data on consideration sets. This parallels a revolution that occurred among choice modelers in marketing 30 years ago: the introduction of in-store product code scanners and household panels whose longitudinal histories provided information not only on which options were eventually chosen, but also which were actually available at the time of purchase, but rejected.

10

A review of the vast choice experiment design literature is beyond the scope of this article, but turnkey solutions for designing, deploying, and estimating discrete choice models for online panels are commercially available (e.g., Sawtooth Software’s “Discover”).

11

There is an enormous literature on the analysis of discrete choice data—items chosen from a known array with recorded attributes. Our treatment here is necessarily brief and highly selective. For more comprehensive introductions to this topic, we refer the reader to the many treatments available (e.g., Ben-Akiva & Lerman 1985, Hensher et al. 2005, Louviere et al. 2000, Train 2009).

12

Empirical work typically refers to this as the multinomial logit model, although economists often distinguish the latter as applicable to when attributes change for the decision-maker (e.g., age, income), not the options themselves.

Contributor Information

Elizabeth Bruch, Department of Sociology and Complex Systems.

Fred Feinberg, Ross School of Business and Statistics.

LITERATURE CITED

  1. Alba J, Marmorstein H. The effects of frequency knowledge on consumer decision making. Journal of Consumer Research. 1987;14:14–25. [Google Scholar]
  2. Alhakami A, Slovic P. A psychological study of the inverse relationship between perceived risk and perceived benefit. Risk analysis. 1994;14:1085–1096. doi: 10.1111/j.1539-6924.1994.tb00080.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  3. Aribarg A, Arora N, Bodur H. Understanding the role of preference revision and concession in group decisions. Journal of Marketing Research. 2002;39:336–349. [Google Scholar]
  4. Astone N, McLanahan S. Family structure, parental practices and high school completion. American Sociological Review. 1991;56:309–320. [Google Scholar]
  5. Baker W. The social structure of a national securities market. American Journal of Sociology. 1984;89:775–811. [Google Scholar]
  6. Barberis N. Thirty years of prospect theory in economics: A review and assessment. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2013;27:173–95. [Google Scholar]
  7. Baron J, Spranca M. Protected values. Organizational behavior and human decision processes. 1997;70:1–16. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1999.2839. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  8. Baron J. Tradeoffs among reasons for action. Journal for the theory of social behavior. 1986;16:173–195. [Google Scholar]
  9. Beckert J. What is sociological about economic sociology? Uncertainty and the embeddedness of economic action. Theory and Society. 1996;25:803–840. [Google Scholar]
  10. Ben-Akiva M, Lerman S. Discrete Choice Analysis: Theory and Application to Travel Demand. Cambridge: MIT Press; 1985. [Google Scholar]
  11. Bertrand M, Mullainathan S, Shafir E. A behavioral-economics view of poverty. The American Economic Review. 2004;94:419–423. [Google Scholar]
  12. Bettman J, Luce M, Payne J. Constructive consumer choice processes. Journal of Consumer Research. 1998;25:187–217. [Google Scholar]
  13. Bettman J, Park C. Effects of prior knowledge and experience and phase of the choice process on consumer decision processes: A protocol analysis. Journal of Consumer Research. 1980;7:234–248. [Google Scholar]
  14. Blalock H. Contextual-effects models: theoretical and methodological issues. Annual Review of Sociology. 1984;10:353–372. [Google Scholar]
  15. Boudon R. Beyond rational choice theory. Annual Review of Sociology. 2003;29:1–21. [Google Scholar]
  16. Braunstein M. Perception of rotation in depth: A process model. Psychological Review. 1972;79:510–524. doi: 10.1037/h0033459. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  17. Brownstone D, Bunch D, Train K. Joint mixed logit models of stated and revealed preferences for alternative-fuel vehicles. Transportation Research Part B: Methodological. 2000;34:315–338. [Google Scholar]
  18. Bruch E, Feinberg F, Lee K. Extracting Multistage Screening Rules from Online Dating Activity Data. Published online before print at Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2016 doi: 10.1073/pnas.1522494113. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Camerer C, Weber M. Recent developments in modeling preferences: Uncertainty and ambiguity. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1992;5:325–370. [Google Scholar]
  20. Camerer C, Thaler R. Anomalies: Ultimatums, dictators and manners. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1995;9:209–219. [Google Scholar]
  21. Camerer C, Loewenstein G. Behavioral economics: Past, present, future. In: Camerer C, Loewenstein G, Rabin M, editors. Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2004. pp. 3–51. [Google Scholar]
  22. Camerer C. Prospect theory in the wild: Evidence from the field. In: Camerer C, Loewenstein G, Rabin M, editors. Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2004. pp. 148–61. [Google Scholar]
  23. Carrillo L, Pattillo M, Hardy E, Acevedo-Garcia D. Housing Decisions Among Low-Income Hispanic Households in Chicago. Cityscape. 2016;18:109–137. [Google Scholar]
  24. Carlsson F, Martinsson P. Do hypothetical and actual marginal willingness to pay differ in choice experiments? Application to the valuation of the environment. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management. 2001;41:179–192. [Google Scholar]
  25. Cerulo K. Culture in mind: Toward a sociology of culture and cognition. New York: Routledge; 2002. [Google Scholar]
  26. Chrzan K, Orme B. An overview and comparison of design strategies for choice-based conjoint analysis. Sawtooth software research paper series 2000 [Google Scholar]
  27. Cialdini R. Crafting normative messages to protect the environment. Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2003;12:105–109. [Google Scholar]
  28. Cialdini R, Goldstein N. Social influence: Compliance and conformity. Annual Review of Psychology. 2004;55:591–621. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142015. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  29. Coleman J. Foundations of Social Theory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1994. [Google Scholar]
  30. Coleman J. Social theory, social research, and a theory of action. American journal of Sociology. 91:1309–1335. [Google Scholar]
  31. Collier D. Understanding process tracing. Political Science & Politics. 2011;44:823–830. [Google Scholar]
  32. Cowan N. The magical mystery four how is working memory capacity limited, and why? Current directions in psychological science. 2010;19:51–57. doi: 10.1177/0963721409359277. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  33. Cox J, Grether D. The preference reversal phenomenon: Response mode, markets and incentives. Economic Theory. 1996;7:381–405. [Google Scholar]
  34. Dawes P, Brown J. Determinants of awareness, consideration, and choice set size in university choice. Journal of Marketing for Higher Education. 2002;12:49–75. [Google Scholar]
  35. Dawes P, Brown J. The composition of consideration and choice sets in undergraduate university choice: An exploratory study. Journal of Marketing for Higher Education. 14:37–59. [Google Scholar]
  36. Dhar R, Nowlis S, Sherman S. Trying hard or hardly trying: An analysis of context effects in choice. Journal of Consumer Psychology. 2000;9:189–200. [Google Scholar]
  37. Denes-Raj V, Epstein S. Conflict between intuitive and rational processing: when people behave against their better judgment. Journal of personality and social psychology. 1994;66:819. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.66.5.819. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. Dimaggio P. Culture and Cognition. Annual Review of Sociology. 1997;23:263–287. [Google Scholar]
  39. Duchowski A. Eye tracking methodology: Theory and Practice. Springer Science & Business Media; 2007. [Google Scholar]
  40. Edland A. On cognitive processes under time stress: A selective review of the literature on time stress and related stress. Department [Psykologiska inst., Stockholms univ.]; 1989. [Google Scholar]
  41. Einhorn H. The use of nonlinear, noncompensatory models in decision-making. Psychological bulletin. 1970;73:221. doi: 10.1037/h0028695. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  42. Einhorn H, Hogarth R. Decision making under ambiguity: A note. In: Munier B, editor. Risk, Decision and Rationality. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel; 1988. pp. 327–336. [Google Scholar]
  43. Ellsberg D. Risk Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1961;75:643–669. [Google Scholar]
  44. Elrod T, Johnson R, White J. A new integrated model of noncompensatory and compensatory decision strategies. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 2004;95:1–19. [Google Scholar]
  45. Emirbayer M. Manifesto for a relational sociology. American Journal of Sociology. 1997;103:281–317. [Google Scholar]
  46. England P. A feminist critique of rational-choice theories: Implications for sociology. The American Sociologist. 1989;20:14–28. [Google Scholar]
  47. Epstein S. Integration of the cognitive and the psychodynamic unconscious. American Psychologist. 1994;49:709. doi: 10.1037//0003-066x.49.8.709. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  48. Esser H, Kroneberg C. An Integrative Theory of Action: The Model of Frame Selection. In: Lawler E, Thye S, Yoon J, editors. Order at the Edge of Chaos: Social Psychology and the Problem of Social Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2015. pp. 63–85. [Google Scholar]
  49. Evans J. Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology. 2008;59:255–78. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  50. Feinberg F, Huber J. A theory of cutoff formation under imperfect information. Management Science. 1996;42:65–84. [Google Scholar]
  51. Fischhoff B, Slovic P, Lichtenstein S, Read S, Combs B. How safe is safe enough? A psychometric study of attitudes towards technological risks and benefits. Policy Sciences. 1978;9:127–152. [Google Scholar]
  52. Gely R, Spiller P. A Rational Choice Theory of Supreme Court Statutory Decisions with Applications to the State Farm and Grove City Cases. Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization. 1990;6:263–300. [Google Scholar]
  53. Gennetian L, Eldar S. The Persistence of Poverty in the Context of Financial Instability: A Behavioral Perspective. Journal of Policy Analysis and Management. 2015;34:904–936. [Google Scholar]
  54. Gigerenzer G, Gaissmaier W. Heuristic decision making. Annual Review of Psychology. 2011;62:451–82. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-120709-145346. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  55. Gigerenzer G, Brighton H. Homo heuristicus: Why biased minds make better inferences. Topics in Cognitive Science. 2009;1:107–143. doi: 10.1111/j.1756-8765.2008.01006.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Gigerenzer G, Goldstein D. Betting on one good reason: The take the best heuristic. In: Gigerenzer G, Todd P, editors. Simple Heuristics that Make Us Smart. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1999. pp. 75–95. [Google Scholar]
  57. Gigerenzer G, Todd P. Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford University Press; USA: 1999. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Gigerenzer G. Fast and frugal heuristics: The tools of bounded rationality. Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making. 2004:62–88. [Google Scholar]
  59. Gigerenzer G. Why heuristics work. Perspectives on Psychological Science. 2008;3:20–29. doi: 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00058.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  60. Gilbride T, Allenby G. A choice model with conjunctive, disjunctive, and compensatory screening rules. Marketing Science. 2004;23:391–406. [Google Scholar]
  61. Goffman E. Frame analysis: An essay on the organization of experience. Cambridge: Harvard University Press; 1974. [Google Scholar]
  62. Goldstein D, Johnson E, Herrmann A, Heitmann M. Nudge your Customers towards Better Choices. Harvard Business Review. 2008:100–105. [Google Scholar]
  63. Goldstein N, Cialdini R, Griskevicius V. A room with a viewpoint: Using social norms to motivate environmental conservation in hotels. Journal of Consumer Research. 2008;35:472–82. [Google Scholar]
  64. Goldthorpe J. The quantitative analysis of large-scale data-sets and rational action theory: for a sociological alliance. European Sociological Review. 1996;12:109–26. [Google Scholar]
  65. Granovetter M. Economic action and social structure: The problem of embeddedness. American Journal of Sociology. 1985;91:481–510. [Google Scholar]
  66. Green P, Srinivasan V. Conjoint analysis in consumer research: issues and outlook. Journal of consumer research. 1978;5:103–123. [Google Scholar]
  67. Green P, Krieger A, Wind Y. Thirty years of conjoint analysis: Reflections and prospects. Interfaces. 2001;31:S56–S73. [Google Scholar]
  68. Grether D, Plott C. Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review. 1979;69:623–638. [Google Scholar]
  69. Gross N. A pragmatist theory of social mechanisms. American Sociological Review. 2009;74:358–79. [Google Scholar]
  70. Guadagni P, Little J. A logit model of brand choice calibrated on scanner data. Marketing Science. 1983;2:203–238. [Google Scholar]
  71. Hauser J, Wernerfelt B. An evaluation cost model of consideration sets. Journal of Consumer Research. 1990;16:393–408. [Google Scholar]
  72. Hechter M, Kanazawa S. Sociological rational choice theory. Annual Review of Sociology. 1997;23:191–214. [Google Scholar]
  73. Hedström P, Swedberg R. Rational Choice, Empirical Research, and the Sociological tradition. European Sociological Review. 1996;12:127–146. [Google Scholar]
  74. Hedstrom P. Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2005. [Google Scholar]
  75. Hedström P, Bearman P. The Oxford handbook of analytical sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2009. [Google Scholar]
  76. Henrich J, Heine S, Norenzayan A. The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 2010;33:61–83. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X0999152X. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  77. Hensher D, Rose J, Greene W. Applied Choice Analysis: A Primer. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2005. [Google Scholar]
  78. Higgins E. Knowledge activation: Accessibility, applicability, and salience. In: Higgins E, Kruglanski A, editors. Social Psychology: Handbook of Basic Principles. New York: Guilford Press; 1996. pp. 133–68. [Google Scholar]
  79. Hogarth R. Judgment and choice: The psychology of decision. Chichester: Wiley; 1991. [Google Scholar]
  80. Hochschild A. The Second Shift: Working Families and the Revolution at Home. New York: Penguin Books; [Google Scholar]
  81. Horowitz J, Louviere J. What is the role of consideration sets in choice modeling? International Journal of Research in Marketing. 1995;12:39–54. [Google Scholar]
  82. Howard J, Jagdish N. The theory of buyer behavior. New York: Wiley; 1969. [Google Scholar]
  83. Huber J, Payne J, Puto C. Adding asymmetrically dominated alternatives: Violations of regularity and the similarity hypothesis. Journal of Consumer Research. 1982;9:90–98. [Google Scholar]
  84. Johnson E, Goldstein D. Do defaults save lives? Science. 2003;302:1338–1339. doi: 10.1126/science.1091721. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  85. Johnson E, Goldstein D. Decisions by Default. In: Shafir E, editor. The Behavioral Foundations of Public Policy. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2013. pp. 417–427. [Google Scholar]
  86. Johnson E, Payne J. Effort and accuracy in choice. Management science. 1985;31(4):395–414. [Google Scholar]
  87. Johnson E, Hershey J, Meszaros J, Kunreuther H. Making Decisions About Liability And Insurance. Springer; Netherlands: 1993. Framing, probability distortions, and insurance decisions; pp. 35–51. [Google Scholar]
  88. Jones D. A WEIRD view of human nature skews psychologists’ studies. Science. 2010;328:1627–1627. doi: 10.1126/science.328.5986.1627. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  89. Kahneman D, Tversky A. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica. 1979:263–291. [Google Scholar]
  90. Kahneman D, Tversky A. Variants of uncertainty. Cognition. 1982;11:143–57. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(82)90023-3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  91. Kahneman D, Tversky A. Choices, Values, and Frames. American Psychologist. 1984;39:341–350. [Google Scholar]
  92. Kahneman D. Maps of bounded rationality: Psychology for behavioral economics. American economic review. 2003;93:1449–75. [Google Scholar]
  93. Kahneman D. Thinking, fast and slow. Macmillan; 2011. [Google Scholar]
  94. Kahneman D, Knetsch J, Thaler R. Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1991;5:193–206. [Google Scholar]
  95. Kroneberg C. Frames, Scripts, and Variable rationality: An integrative Theory of Action. In: Manzo G, editor. Analytical Sociology. Chichester, UK: John Wiley and Sons; 2014. pp. 95–123. [Google Scholar]
  96. Kroneberg C, Kalter F. Rational choice theory and empirical research: Methodological and theoretical contributions in Europe. Annual Review of Sociology. 2012;38:73–92. [Google Scholar]
  97. Krysan M, Bader M. Racial blind spots: Black-white-Latino differences in community knowledge. Social Problems. 2009;56:677–701. [Google Scholar]
  98. Lee V, Bryk A, Smith J. The organization of effective secondary schools. Review of Research in Education. 1993;19:171–267. [Google Scholar]
  99. Leschziner V, Green A. Thinking about Food and Sex: Deliberate Cognition in the Routine Practices of a Field. Sociological Theory. 2013;31:116–144. [Google Scholar]
  100. Lerner J, Li Y, Valdesolo P, Kassam K. Emotion and decision making. Annual Review of Psychology. 2015;66:799–823. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115043. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  101. Levy J. Prospect theory, rational choice, and international relations. International Studies Quarterly. 1997;41:87–112. [Google Scholar]
  102. Liberman V, Samuels S, Ross L. The name of the game: Predictive power of reputations versus situational labels in determining prisoner’s dilemma game moves. Personality and social psychology bulletin. 2004;30:1175–1185. doi: 10.1177/0146167204264004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  103. Lichtenstein S, Slovic P. The construction of preference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2006. [Google Scholar]
  104. Lindenberg S, Frey B. Alternatives, frames, and relative prices: A broader view of rational choice theory. Acta Sociologica. 1993;36:191–205. [Google Scholar]
  105. Liu L, Dukes A. Consideration set formation with multiproduct firms: The case of within-firm and across-firm evaluation costs. Management Science. 2013;59:1871–1886. [Google Scholar]
  106. Lizardo O. Beyond the Comtean Schema: The Sociology of Culture and Cognition Versus Cognitive Social Science. Sociological Forum. 2014;29:983–989. [Google Scholar]
  107. Loewenstein G, Lerner J. The role of affect in decision making. Handbook of affective science. 2003;619:3. [Google Scholar]
  108. Loewenstein G. The creative destruction of decision research. Journal of Consumer Research. 2001;28:499–505. [Google Scholar]
  109. Loewenstein G, Weber E, Hsee C, Welch N. Risk as feelings. Psychological bulletin. 2001;127:267. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.127.2.267. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  110. Lohse G, Johnson E. A comparison of two process tracing methods for choice tasks. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 1996;68(1):28–43. [Google Scholar]
  111. Louviere J, Hensher D, Swait J. Stated choice methods: analysis and applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2000. [Google Scholar]
  112. Louviere J, Meyer R, Bunch D, Carson R, Dellaert B, Hanemann W, Hensher D, Irwin J. Combining sources of preference data for modeling complex decision processes. Marketing Letters. 1999;10:205–217. [Google Scholar]
  113. Luce R. Individual Choice Behavior: A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Wiley; 1959. [Google Scholar]
  114. Luce M, Bettman J, Payne J. Emotional decisions: Tradeoff difficulty and coping in consumer choice. Monographs of the Journal of Consumer Research. 2001;1:1–209. [Google Scholar]
  115. Luce M, Payne J, Bettman J. Emotional trade-off difficulty and choice. Journal of Marketing Research. 1999:143–159. [Google Scholar]
  116. Luce M, Payne J, Bettman J. Coping with unfavorable attribute values in choice. Organizational behavior and human decision processes. 81:274–99. doi: 10.1006/obhd.1999.2872. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  117. Mahoney J. The logic of process tracing tests in the social sciences. Sociological Methods & Research. 2012;41:570–597. [Google Scholar]
  118. Mandel N, Johnson E. When web pages influence choice: Effects of visual primes on experts and novices. Journal of consumer research. 2002;29:235–245. [Google Scholar]
  119. Manski C. Economic Analysis of Social Interactions. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 14:115–136. [Google Scholar]
  120. Manzo G. Is rational choice theory still a rational choice of theory? A response to Opp. Social Science Information. 2013;52:361–382. [Google Scholar]
  121. Margolis H. Selfishness and Altruism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1982. [Google Scholar]
  122. Matza D. Delinquency and Drift. Transaction Publishers; 1967. [Google Scholar]
  123. McDaniels T, Axelrod L, Cavanagh N, Slovic P. Perception of ecological risk to water environments. Risk analysis. 1997;17:341–352. doi: 10.1111/j.1539-6924.1997.tb00872.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  124. McFadden D. Conditional Logit Analysis of Qualitative Choice Behavior. In: Zarembka P, editor. Frontiers in Econometrics. New York: Academic Press; 1973. pp. 105–142. [Google Scholar]
  125. McFadden D. Rationality for economists? Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 1999;19:73–105. [Google Scholar]
  126. McFadden D. Economic Choices. The American Economic Review. 2001;91:351–378. [Google Scholar]
  127. Miller G. The magical number seven, plus or minus two: Some limits on our capacity for processing information. Psychological review. 1956;63:81. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  128. Miller N. Liberalization of Basic SR Concepts: Extensions to Conflict Behavior, Motivation, and Social Learning. McGraw-Hill Company; 1959. [Google Scholar]
  129. Munch R. Rational Choice Theory: A Critical Assessment of Its Explanatory Power. In: Coleman J, Fararo T, editors. Rational Choice Theory: Advocacy and Critique. London: Sage Publications; 1992. pp. 137–161. [Google Scholar]
  130. Mullainathan S, Shafir E. Scarcity: Why having too little means so much. New York: Times Books; 2013. [Google Scholar]
  131. Newell A, Simon H. Human Problem Solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall; 1972. [Google Scholar]
  132. Nolan J, Schultz P, Cialdini R, Goldstein N, Griskevicius V. Normative social influence is underdetected. Personality and social psychology bulletin. 2008;34:913–923. doi: 10.1177/0146167208316691. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  133. Pachucki M, Jacques P, Christakis N. Social network concordance in food choice among spouses, friends, and siblings. American Journal of Public Health. 2011;101:2170–2177. doi: 10.2105/AJPH.2011.300282. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  134. Payne J, Bettman J. Walking with the scarecrow: The information-processing approach to decision research. In: Koehler D, Harvey N, editors. Blackwell handbook of judgment and decision making. Malden, MA: Blackwell; 2004. pp. 110–132. [Google Scholar]
  135. Payne J. Task complexity and contingent processing in decision making: An information search and protocol analysis. Organizational behavior and human performance. 1976;16:366–387. [Google Scholar]
  136. Payne J, Bettman J, Johnson E. The adaptive decision maker. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1993. [Google Scholar]
  137. Perna L, Titus M. The relationship between parental involvement as social capital and college enrollment: An examination of racial/ethnic group differences. Journal of Higher Education. 2005;76:485–518. [Google Scholar]
  138. Pescosolido B. Beyond rational choice: The social dynamics of how people seek help. American Journal of Sociology. 1992;97:1096–1138. [Google Scholar]
  139. Pocheptsova A, Amir O, Dhar R, Baumeister R. Deciding without resources: Resource depletion and choice in context. Journal of Marketing Research. 2009;46:344–55. [Google Scholar]
  140. Rieskamp J, Hoffrage U. Inferences under time pressure: How opportunity costs affect strategy selection. Acta psychological. 2008;127:258–76. doi: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2007.05.004. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  141. Rieskamp J, Otto P. SSL: a theory of how people learn to select strategies. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. 2006;135:207. doi: 10.1037/0096-3445.135.2.207. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. Roberts J, Lattin J. Development and testing of a model of consideration set composition. Journal of Marketing Research. 1991:429–440. [Google Scholar]
  143. Roberts J, Lattin J. Consideration: Review of research and prospects for future insights. Journal of Marketing Research. 1997:406–410. [Google Scholar]
  144. Rosenquist N, Murabito J, Fowler J, Christakis N. The spread of alcohol consumption behavior in a large social network. Annals of Internal Medicine. 2010;152:426–433. doi: 10.1059/0003-4819-152-7-201004060-00007. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  145. Nisbett R, Ross L. The person and the situation. New York: McGraw Hill; 1991. [Google Scholar]
  146. Rossi P, Allenby G, McCulloch R. Bayesian Statistics and Marketing. Wiley, Chichester; 2005. [Google Scholar]
  147. Salisbury L, Feinberg F. All things considered? The role of choice set formation in diversification. Journal of Marketing Research. 2012;49(3):320–335. [Google Scholar]
  148. Sampson R, Morenoff J, Gannon-Rowley T. Assessing Neighborhood Effects: Social Processes and New Directions in Research. Annual Review of Sociology. 2002;28:443–478. [Google Scholar]
  149. Samuelson P. Some Implications of Linearity. The Review of Economic Studies. 1947;15:88–90. [Google Scholar]
  150. Samuelson P. Consumption theory in terms of revealed preference. Economica. 1948;15:243–253. [Google Scholar]
  151. Samuelson W, Zeckhauser R. Status quo bias in decision making. Journal of risk and uncertainty. 1988;1:7–59. [Google Scholar]
  152. Satz D, Ferejohn J. Rational choice and social theory. The Journal of Philosophy. 1994;91:71–87. [Google Scholar]
  153. Scheff T. Shame and conformity: The deference-emotion system. American Sociological Review. 1988;53:395–406. [Google Scholar]
  154. Schelling T. Dynamic models of segregation. Journal of Mathematical Sociology. 1971;1:143–186. [Google Scholar]
  155. Schneider S. Framing and conflict: aspiration level contingency, the status quo, and current theories of risky choice. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. 1992;18:1040. doi: 10.1037//0278-7393.18.5.1040. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  156. Schulte-Mecklenbeck M, Kuehberger A, Ranyard R. A Handbook of Process Tracing Methods for Decision Research: A Critical Review and User’s Guide (The Society for Judgment and Decision Making Series) Psychology Press; 2010. [Google Scholar]
  157. Schultz P, Wesley J, Nolan M, Cialdini R, Goldstein N, Griskevicius V. The Constructive, Destructive, and Reconstructive Power of Social Norms. Psychological science. 2007;18:429–434. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01917.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  158. Schwarz N. Self-reports: how the questions shape the answers. American Psychologist. 1999;54:93–105. [Google Scholar]
  159. Schwarz N. Attitude construction: Evaluation in context. Social Cognition. 2007;25:638–56. [Google Scholar]
  160. Schwarz N, Strack F, Mai H. Assimilation and contrast effects in part-whole question sequences: A conversational logic analysis. Public Opinion Quarterly. 1991;55:3–23. [Google Scholar]
  161. Seidl C. Preference reversal. Journal of Economic Surveys. 2002;16:621–55. [Google Scholar]
  162. Shafir E. The Behavioral Foundations of Public Policy. Princeton: Princeton University Press; 2013. [Google Scholar]
  163. Shah A, Shafir E, Mullainathan S. Scarcity frames value. Psychological Science. 2015;26:402–412. doi: 10.1177/0956797614563958. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  164. Shang J, Croson R. A field experiment in charitable contribution: The impact of social information on the voluntary provision of public goods. The Economic Journal. 2009;119:1422–39. [Google Scholar]
  165. Sharkey P, Faber J. Where, when, why, and for whom do residential contexts matter? Moving away from the dichotomous understanding of neighborhood effects. Annual Review of Sociology. 2014;40:559–579. [Google Scholar]
  166. Shugan S. The Cost of Thinking. Journal of consumer Research. 1980;7:99–111. [Google Scholar]
  167. Simon H. Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review. 1956;63:129. doi: 10.1037/h0042769. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  168. Simon H. Models of bounded rationality: Empirically grounded economic reason. MIT press; [Google Scholar]
  169. Simon H. Invariants of human behavior. Annual review of psychology. 1991;41:1–20. doi: 10.1146/annurev.ps.41.020190.000245. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  170. Simonson I. Choice based on reasons: The case of attraction and compromise effects. Journal of Consumer Research. 1989;16:158–174. [Google Scholar]
  171. Simonson I, Tversky A. Choice in context: Tradeoff contrast and extremeness aversion. Journal of Marketing Research. 1992;29:281–95. [Google Scholar]
  172. Slovic P. Perception of Risk. Science. 1987;236:280–285. doi: 10.1126/science.3563507. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  173. Slovic P. The Construction of Preference. American Psychologist. 1995;50:364. [Google Scholar]
  174. Slovic P. The Perception of Risk. Earthscan Publications; 2000. [Google Scholar]
  175. Slovic P, Monahan J, MacGregor D. Violence risk assessment and risk communication: the effects of using actual cases, providing instruction, and employing probability versus frequency formats. Law and human behavior. 2000;24:271. doi: 10.1023/a:1005595519944. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  176. Slovic P, Peters E. Risk perception and Affect. Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2006;15:322–325. [Google Scholar]
  177. Slovic P, Finucane M, Peters E, MacGregor D. Risk as analysis and risk as feelings: Some thoughts about affect, reason, risk, and rationality. Risk analysis. 2004;24:311–322. doi: 10.1111/j.0272-4332.2004.00433.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  178. Small M. Unanticipated gains: Origins of Network Inequality in Everyday Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2009. [Google Scholar]
  179. Small M, Sukhu C. Because they were there: Access, deliberation, and the mobilization of networks for support. Social Networks. 2016;47:73–84. [Google Scholar]
  180. Somers M. “We’re No Angels”: Realism, Rational Choice, and Relationality in Social Science. American Journal of Sociology. 1998;104:722–784. [Google Scholar]
  181. Stets J, Turner J. Handbook of the Sociology of Emotions: Volume II. New York: Springer; 2014. [Google Scholar]
  182. Stigler G. The development of utility theory. I and II. The Journal of Political Economy. 1950:307–327. [Google Scholar]
  183. Strough J, Karns T, Schlosnagle L. Decision-making heuristics and biases across the life span. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 2011;1235:57–74. doi: 10.1111/j.1749-6632.2011.06208.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  184. Svenson O. Process descriptions of decision making. Organizational behavior and human performance. 1979;23(1):86–112. [Google Scholar]
  185. Swait J. A non-compensatory choice model incorporating attribute cutoffs. Transportation Research Part B: Methodological. 2001;35(10):903–928. [Google Scholar]
  186. Swait J. Doctoral dissertation. Massachusetts Institute of Technology; 1984. Probabilistic choice set generation in transportation demand models. [Google Scholar]
  187. Thaler R, Sunstein C. Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth, and Happiness. New York: Penguin Books; 2009. [Google Scholar]
  188. Thomas W, Znaniecki F. The Polish peasant in Europe and America: Monograph of an immigrant group. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1918. [Google Scholar]
  189. Train K. Discrete Choice Methods with Simulation. 2nd. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2009. [Google Scholar]
  190. Tversky A, Kahneman D. Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology. 1973;5:207–32. [Google Scholar]
  191. Tversky A, Kahneman D. The Framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science. 1981;211(4481):453–458. doi: 10.1126/science.7455683. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  192. Tversky A, Kahneman D. Rational choice and the Framing of Decisions. Journal of Business. 1986:S251–S278. [Google Scholar]
  193. Tversky A, Sattath S, Slovic P. Contingent Weighting in Judgment and Choice. Psychological Review. 1988;95:371–384. [Google Scholar]
  194. Tversky A, Simonson I. Context-dependent preferences. Management Science. 1993;39:1179–1189. [Google Scholar]
  195. Uzzi B. Social Structure and Competition in Interfirm Networks: The Paradox of Embeddedness. Administrative Science Quarterly. 1997;1:35–67. [Google Scholar]
  196. Vaisey S. Motivation and Justification: a Dual-Process Model of Culture in Action. American Journal of Sociology. 2009;114:1675–1715. doi: 10.1086/597179. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  197. Vaughan D. Rational choice, situated action, and the social control of organizations. Law and Society Review. 1998:23–61. [Google Scholar]
  198. Von Neumann J, Morgenstern O. Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton university press; 2007. [Google Scholar]
  199. Ward A, Ross L, Reed E, Turiel E, Brown T. Naive realism in everyday life: Implications for social conflict and misunderstanding. Values and knowledge. 1997:103–135. [Google Scholar]
  200. Weber E, Johnson E. Mindful judgment and decision making. Annual review of psychology. 2009;60:53. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.60.110707.163633. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  201. Wedel M, Pieters R. A review of eye-tracking research in marketing. Review of marketing research. 2008;4:123–147. [Google Scholar]
  202. Windschitl P, Weber E. The interpretation of likely depends on the context, but 70% is 70%—right? The influence of associative processes on perceived certainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. 1999;25:1514. doi: 10.1037//0278-7393.25.6.1514. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  203. Wittink D, Cattin P. Commercial use of conjoint analysis: An update. The Journal of Marketing. 1989:91–96. [Google Scholar]
  204. Wittink D, Vriens M, Burhenne W. Commercial use of conjoint analysis in Europe: Results and critical reflections. International journal of Research in Marketing. 1994;11:41–52. [Google Scholar]
  205. Yoon C, Gutchess A, Feinberg F, Polk T. A functional magnetic resonance imaging study of neural dissociations between brand and person judgments. Journal of Consumer Research. 2006;33(1):31–40. [Google Scholar]
  206. Wright P, Weitz B. Time Horizon Effects on Product Evaluation Strategies. Journal of Marketing Research. 1977;14:429–443. [Google Scholar]
  207. Zajonc R. Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American psychologist. 1980;35:151. [Google Scholar]

RESOURCES