Abstract
Quantifying evidence is an inherent aim of empirical science, yet the customary statistical methods in psychology do not communicate the degree to which the collected data serve as evidence for the tested hypothesis. In order to estimate the distribution of the strength of evidence that individual significant results offer in psychology, we calculated Bayes factors (BF) for 287,424 findings of 35,515 articles published in 293 psychological journals between 1985 and 2016. Overall, 55% of all analyzed results were found to provide BF > 10 (often labeled as strong evidence) for the alternative hypothesis, while more than half of the remaining results do not pass the level of BF = 3 (labeled as anecdotal evidence). The results estimate that at least 82% of all published psychological articles contain one or more significant results that do not provide BF > 10 for the hypothesis. We conclude that due to the threshold of acceptance having been set too low for psychological findings, a substantial proportion of the published results have weak evidential support.
Introduction
The reliability of evidence published in psychological science recently became a major concern as a high rate of published experiments failed to generate significant results upon replication [1], including some classic textbook studies [2]. While most often this low replicability of statistically significant findings is attributed to publication bias [3], questionable research practices [4] and flawed statistical analyses [5], replicability is also conditional on the degree to which significant results in themselves constitute evidence for an experimental hypothesis. To explore this question, we provide a general overview of the evidential value of significant results in psychological journals.
In general, empirical scientists form hypotheses about the world and collect data to evaluate these hypotheses. In order to quantify their evidence, researchers in psychology and other social sciences use their data to distinguish true effects from random chance. In practice, they overwhelmingly use null-hypothesis significance testing (NHST), which estimates the probability of receiving an observation (or more extreme ones) if the null-hypothesis of no effect is true. If this probability, the p-value, is equal to or less than a preset threshold (customarily 5%) then researchers reject the null-hypothesis and claim support for the effect. Since the development of this procedure in the early 20th century [6], social sciences have been relying on this logic when providing evidence for their theoretical hypotheses.
Nevertheless, it is a common misunderstanding that the NHST method can quantify the evidence for a hypothesis [7]. For example, p = .05 is often misinterpreted as 5% probability that the null-hypothesis is true or that chance alone produced the effect [8]. Unfortunately, however, the NHST approach cannot be used to directly evaluate the hypothesis since it estimates the probability of statistical significance under the assumptions of the null-hypothesis, but ignores the probability of statistical significance under the alternative hypothesis. In fact, the long-term rate of false discovery depends not just on the p ≤ 0.05 rule, but also on the prevalence of the effects and the power of the tests. Taking these into account, the false discovery rate of NHST tests is estimated to be much higher than 5% [9]. In sum, although p < .05 results have been interpreted as convincing evidence in support of psychological effects, statistical logic does not admit such use of the method.
One way to quantify evidence is to assess how much the data support one or a competing hypothesis. The Bayes factor is a tool that can be used to calculate the ratio of the likelihood of the hypotheses in light of the data, thus expressing how much the observation should change our beliefs about the hypotheses. Recent developments in the method [10–12] allow researchers to effectively employ Bayes factor analysis techniques to quantify the strength of the evidence against, as well as for, the null-hypothesis. A major difference from the traditional statistics is that this Bayes factor computation requires specifying what the hypotheses predict, known as the priors. While the choice of prior can be debated and gives the impression of subjectivity, there are two main reasons why this feature of the method should not be a major concern. First, it is important to see that the need to specify the predictions of the theory is not a limitation, but a basic requirement of science [13–14]. Second, applications of the method, such as this work, show that the results are often robust to the choice of reasonable priors [15].
While the Bayes factor is a continuous scale between 0 and positive infinite, customary labels are often used to categorize the strength of evidence [16](Table 1). Assuming the reader has no prior expectations regarding the outcome of the research, by Bayes factor of 1 we can infer that the evidence is equally in favor of the null and alternative hypotheses, a clearly insensitive case. The range of Bayes factors between 1 and 3 has been suggested as a region for anecdotal evidence for the alternative hypothesis, while Bayes factors between 1 and 1/3 indicate anecdotal evidence towards the null [17]. Bayes Factor 3 indicates that the odds are 3:1 for the alternative hypothesis, allowing 75% confidence in the results. The next level is the moderate evidence, which is used for Bayes factors between 3 and 10, and Bayes factors between 1/3 and 1/10. To be able to claim strong support, Bayes factor > 10 and < 1/10 are considered to be the threshold for H1 and H0, respectively [17].
Table 1. Bayes factor evidence categories and the corresponding Bayes factor intervals [16–17].
Bayes factor evidence categories | Value of the Bayes factor |
---|---|
Strong support for H1 | > 10 |
Moderate support for H1 | 3–10 |
Anecdotal support for H1 | 1–3 |
Equal support for the hypotheses | 1 |
Anecdotal support for H0 | 1/3–1 |
Moderate support for H0 | 1/10–1/3 |
Strong support for H0 | < 1/10 |
Different categories have been suggested as a requirement for a result to be taken as evidential. Originally, Jeffrey proposed that Bayes factor 3 mostly correspond with the level of evidence that is usually obtained with conventional significance testing [16]. Others suggested that the conventional threshold is too liberal and Bayes factor 6 is more efficient in correctly capturing the effect [18] and 10 provides more compelling evidence [18–19]. Nevertheless, it is important to emphasize that it would be a misuse to blindly apply Bayes factors as hard cut-off levels. Instead, these indices should inform the reader about the degree to which the observations support one compared to another hypothesis. Although researchers often set expected levels of evidence for their decisions, the relative nature of the support should never be disregarded.
While there is a functional correspondence between p-values and Bayes factors [20], the question remains as to how much evidence is provided by individual significant results in psychology. A previous investigation compared all p-values and the computed Bayes factors of 855 t-tests published in two experimental journals in 2007 [21]. Those results demonstrated that if p-values are misinterpreted as evidence then they mostly agree with the Bayes factor results about the direction of their support, yet they systematically overestimate the strength of the evidence against the null-hypothesis. It is a question, however, whether this sample of the two journals can be generalized to all domains of psychology. To extend this analysis and assess the overall picture about the strength of evidence in psychological science, we computed Bayes factors with additional robustness analyses for 287,424 significant t- and F-tests using a text-mined dataset of 35,515 psychological articles published between 1985 and 2016 [22]. This dataset contains all reported t- and F-tests from 293 psychological journals from this period of time, representing a substantial corpus of all published research of the field. Here, we use this sample to estimate the strength of evidence that individual significant results provide for the alternative hypothesis.
Methods
The analysis plan of this study was preregistered on osf.io/5rf2x prior the conduct of all the reported analyses. For the analyses, we used a dataset collected by Hartgerink [22]. This dataset contains the metadata and statistical parameters of 688,112 null-hypothesis test results text-mined from 50,845 articles published in 321 psychology journals between 1985 and 2016.
For our main analysis, we limited our database to the t, and F statistics which are the most frequently used statistics in psychology [22] and we assumed an independent sample design, the most lenient condition for supporting the alternative hypothesis. First, we selected 403,929 test statistics (the 169,984 t-tests, the 233,945 F-tests where the value of the first degrees of freedom was one). Using the recalculated p-values we excluded the non-significant test statistics (109,470 results), as the question of our interest was to calculate the degree of evidence behind the significant results. To exclude ambiguous cases from our analyses, we filtered out those results which did not provide the exact values of the test statistics (374 results), as well as the one-sided tests (4878 results), having no information about the direction of the hypotheses of those tests. Furthermore, we removed those test statistics where the recalculated p-values changed whether or not the results were statistically significant using the 0.05 decision threshold (705 results). Next, we rounded up all of the non-integer degrees of freedoms of the t-tests as we assumed that these scores were reduced by a correctional process (e.g., Welch t-test). We calculated the square root of the F-values and analyzed them as t statistics thereafter. Afterward, we calculated the sample sizes of the results from the reported degrees of freedom assuming independent-sample design. Finally, we took out the results where the overall sample size did not exceed 5 to exclude the extreme cases (486 t-tests, 592 F-tests). After these selections, 114,272 t-tests and 173,152 F-tests remained in our dataset.
To compute the Bayes factors corresponding to the t- and F-tests, we employed the ttest.tstat function of the BayesFactor R package [23]. The calculation of the Bayes factors requires specification of the predictions (prior distribution) of the null- and the alternative models [15, 24]. In cases where the effect size of the alternative model can be high, it is suggested to employ a two-tailed Cauchy distribution centered on zero as a prior distribution of the alternative hypothesis [15]. The scaling of this prior distribution can influence the calculated value of the Bayes factors, and so the level of evidence favoring the hypotheses. Accordingly, for smaller effects a high-scaled prior distribution can underestimate the degree of positive evidence compared to a low-scaled prior. To determine the scaling factor of the Cauchy distribution, we applied the median effect size (d = 0.93) of a collection of 100,000 significant statistical tests, extracted from 10,000 psychology articles, as a rough estimate [25]. As this calculated value could be influenced by a small number of extremely high effect sizes, we decided to employ the so called default JZS prior (√2/2) for our main analyses, which is more lenient towards smaller effect sizes [26]. This value is the default scaling factor of the ttest.tstat function and is considered a ‘medium’ scaling factor [23]. To explore the robustness of our results, we repeated the analyses with different sizes and shapes of the prior distribution (See S1 Supplementary methods and results). Using the resulting Bayes factor values, we categorized each test result into the corresponding Bayes factor evidence category of Table 1.
Results
The results show that overall only 54.7% of all analyzed results provide strong evidence (B = 10) for the alternative hypothesis, while half of the remaining results do not pass the level of even anecdotal evidence (B = 3) (Table 2). As illustrated in Figs 1 and 2, due to the functional relationship between p-values and Bayes factors [20, 26], there is an upper bound on the potential Bayes factors corresponding to p-values. As a result, findings with p > 0.005, cannot provide strong evidence for the alternative hypothesis. Of note, even among those results with p < 0.005, 6% still fail to reach the level of strong evidence. Results remain robust with different prior distribution settings and when assuming paired sample tests (see S1 Supplementary methods and results). Repeating the same analyses on the significant correlation findings in the collection (N = 15,026), the pattern of results differed only slightly, with 59.6% of results reaching the level of strong evidence, half of which remained in the anecdotal evidence region (S1 Supplementary methods and results). Considering just the t-, and F- statistics, the results indicate that at least 82% of all psychological articles contain at least one significant result which does not provide strong evidence. This result highlights that the rejection of the null-hypothesis based on significant p-values gives only ambiguous support for the alternative hypothesis.
Table 2. The proportion of significant t- and F-test results in the different Bayes factor evidence categories.
Strength of evidence | |||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Strong H1 | Moderate H1 | Anecdotal H1 | Anecdotal H0 | Moderate H0 | Strong H0 | Total | |
N/row total (%) | 54.7% | 21.4% | 22.9% | 1.0% | 0.0% | 0.0% | 100.0% |
N | 157,184 | 61,579 | 65,677 | 2,861 | 116 | 7 | 287,424 |
Discussion
As Figs 1 and 2 depict, the strength of evidence that significant results provide vary greatly. While there is an upper bound to the Bayes factors corresponding to the p-values, regardless the value of p, the evidence can be very minimal or even supporting for the null-hypothesis [27]. These results demonstrate that without the computation of Bayes factors the interpretation of psychological results remains fairly limited.
It is to be noted, however, that our analyses cannot provide precise estimates to all psychological results, as they cover only the most frequently used statistical methods (t, and F statistics) and, furthermore, they are subject to the errors in the original reports and to the limitations of text-mining. In particular, it is important to highlight that the analyzed results certainly contain a proportion of manipulation check, therefore, the present results are not exclusive descriptors of focal results. An additional distortion of the sample can originate from the fact that several questionable research practices affect the likelihood of finding evidence for false hypotheses [4]. Ad hoc exclusion of outliers [28], selective reporting of p-values [29], and motivated stopping rules for data collection [4] have all been diagnosed in the field as additional factors that increase the rate of false discovery. The preference in publication culture for significant results over nonsignificant results [3] also increases the prevalence of false positive reports and incentivizes researchers to produce significant results. Although the exact impact of these biases is unknown, recent analyses revealed a high level of distortion in published statistical results [5, 30].
Changes to statistical practices have been repeatedly proposed in recent decades [31–34]. Relying more on reported confidence intervals [35] or using lower decision thresholds for p-values (0.001 in 33, 0.005) [36] have been recommended to improve the use of NHST statistics. Despite the many reform attempts, NHST is still misinterpreted and misused, at an increasing rate in certain areas [37]. While, certainly, the use of Bayes factors can only be part of the solution, their proponents emphasize that besides being able to quantify evidence against, and even for, the null-hypothesis, its use is also less prone to potential biases of multiple comparisons or optional stopping rules [38]. In fact, within this approach, for any study with an insufficient level of evidence, the researchers may continue to collect data until the results allow decisions to be made about the hypotheses [39]. Nevertheless, even without Bayesian calculations great improvement in existing practices can be achieved, for example by simply reporting the largest possible ‘post-experimental rejection ratio’ calculated from the p-value of any standard statistical test [40]. As the new statistical methods become easily applicable [41], researchers and journal editors may become convinced to extend the statistical toolbox of psychological research when evaluating the relationship between theories and their empirical evidence.
This study aimed to highlight that disregarding all the intentional or unintentional biases in research practice, a sizable proportion of published results labeled as “statistically significant” provide, in themselves, very little or no convincing evidence for the presence of the effect. From this aspect, it is not that surprising that previous ‘evidential’ findings fail to replicate, rather it is a necessary consequence of the threshold of acceptance having been set too low for the purported effects [19, 36]. As failed replications in recent years motivated psychological research to increase the transparency of research and openness of science, the present results should carry a further message to the field that changes to the customary research and analysis practices are inevitable.
Supporting information
Acknowledgments
We thank Z. Dienes, C. H. Hargerink, Z. Kekecs, R. D. Morey, J. N. Rouder, A. Szollosi, E.-J. Wagenmakers, and M. Wood for providing valuable suggestions to an earlier version of the manuscript. The authors declare no financial conflict of interest with the reported research. The data analyzed in this paper are tabulated in the document ‘S1 Supplementary methods and results’ and archived at the following database: https://easy.dans.knaw.nl/ui/datasets/id/easy-dataset:65072. The project was not supported by any grant or financial funding. Bence Palfi is grateful to the Dr Mortimer and Theresa Sackler Foundation which supports the Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science.
Data Availability
The authors confirm that all data underlying the findings are fully available without restriction. All relevant data are within the Supporting Information files.
Funding Statement
The authors received no specific funding for this work.
References
- 1.Open Science Collaboration. Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. 2015;349(6251). [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Wagenmakers EJ, Beek T, Dijkhoff L, Gronau QF, Acosta A, Adams RB Jr, et al. Registered Replication Report: Strack, Martin, & Stepper (1988). Perspectives on Psychological Science. 2016;11(6):917–28. doi: 10.1177/1745691616674458 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 3.Franco A, Malhotra N, Simonovits G. Publication bias in the social sciences: Unlocking the file drawer. Science. 2014;345(6203):1502–5. doi: 10.1126/science.1255484 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.John LK, Loewenstein G, Prelec D. Measuring the prevalence of questionable research practices with incentives for truth telling. Psychol Sci. 2012;0956797611430953. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5.Nuijten MB, Hartgerink CH, Assen MA, Epskamp S, Wicherts JM. The prevalence of statistical reporting errors in psychology (1985–2013). Behav Res Methods. 2015;1–22. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Neyman J, Pearson ES. On the problem of the most efficient tests of statistical hypotheses. Philos. Philos Trans R Soc A. 1933;231(694–706):289–337. [Google Scholar]
- 7.Gigerenzer G. Mindless statistics. J Socio-Econ. 2004;33(5):587–606. [Google Scholar]
- 8.Goodman S. A dirty dozen: twelve p-value misconceptions. Semin Hematol. 2008;45(3):135–40. doi: 10.1053/j.seminhematol.2008.04.003 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Colquhoun D. An investigation of the false discovery rate and the misinterpretation of p-values. Open Sci. 2014;1(3):140216. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Rouder JN, Morey RD, Speckman PL, Province JM. Default Bayes factors for ANOVA designs. J Math Psychol. 2012;56(5):356–74. [Google Scholar]
- 11.Morey RD, Rouder JN. Bayes factor approaches for testing interval null hypotheses. Psychol Methods. 2011;16(4):406–19. doi: 10.1037/a0024377 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Verhagen J, Wagenmakers E-J. Bayesian tests to quantify the result of a replication attempt. J Exp Psychol Gen. 2014;143(4):1457–75. doi: 10.1037/a0036731 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Popper K. The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- 14.Rouder JN, Richard M, Wagenmakers E-J. The interplay between subjectivity, statistical practice, and psychological science. Collabra: Psychology 2016; 2, 1. [Google Scholar]
- 15.Rouder JN, Speckman PL, Sun D, Morey RD, Iverson G. Bayesian t tests for accepting and rejecting the null hypothesis. Psychon Bull Rev. 2009;16(2):225–37. doi: 10.3758/PBR.16.2.225 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Jeffreys H. Theory of probability Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1961. [Google Scholar]
- 17.Lee MD, Wagenmakers EJ. Bayesian cognitive modeling: A practical course. Cambridge University Press; 2014. April 3. [Google Scholar]
- 18.Schönbrodt FD, Wagenmakers EJ, Zehetleitner M, Perugini M. Sequential hypothesis testing with Bayes factors: Efficiently testing mean differences. Psychological Methods. 2017;22(2):322 doi: 10.1037/met0000061 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Etz A, Vandekerckhove J. A Bayesian perspective on the reproducibility project: Psychology. PLoS ONE. 2016;11(2):e0149794 doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0149794 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.Vovk VG. A logic of probability, with application to the foundations of statistics. J R Stat Soc Ser B Methodol. 1993;317–51. [Google Scholar]
- 21.Wetzels R, Matzke D, Lee MD, Rouder JN, Iverson GJ, Wagenmakers E-J. Statistical evidence in experimental psychology an empirical comparison using 855 t tests. Perspect Psychol Sci. 2011;6(3):291–8. doi: 10.1177/1745691611406923 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Hartgerink CH. 688,112 Statistical Results: Content Mining Psychology Articles for Statistical Test Results. Data. 2016;1(3):14. [Google Scholar]
- 23.Morey RD, Rouder JN, Jamil T. BayesFactor: Computation of Bayes factors for common designs. R Package Version 09. 2014;8. [Google Scholar]
- 24.Dienes Z. Bayesian versus orthodox statistics: Which side are you on? Perspect Psychol Sci. 2011;6(3):274–90. doi: 10.1177/1745691611406920 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 25.Szucs D, Ioannidis JP. Empirical assessment of published effect sizes and power in the recent cognitive neuroscience and psychology literature. bioRxiv. 2016;071530. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26.Sellke T, Bayarri MJ, Berger JO. Calibration of ρ values for testing precise null hypotheses. Am Stat. 2001;55(1):62–71. [Google Scholar]
- 27.Dienes Z, Mclatchie N. Four reasons to prefer Bayesian analyses over significance testing. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 2017. Mar 28:1–2. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28.Simmons JP, Nelson LD, Simonsohn U. False-Positive Psychology Undisclosed Flexibility in Data Collection and Analysis Allows Presenting Anything as Significant. Psychol Sci. 2011. October 1;0956797611417632. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29.Simonsohn U, Nelson LD, Simmons JP. P-curve: a key to the file-drawer. J Exp Psychol Gen. 2014;143(2):534–47. doi: 10.1037/a0033242 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30.Hartgerink CH, van Aert RC, Nuijten MB, Wicherts JM, van Assen MA. Distributions of p-values smaller than. 05 in psychology: what is going on? PeerJ. 2016;4:e1935 doi: 10.7717/peerj.1935 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31.Johnson VE, Payne RD, Wang T, Asher A, Mandal S. On the reproducibility of psychological science. J Am Stat Assoc. 2016; [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32.Pashler H, Wagenmakers E-J. Editors’ Introduction to the Special Section on Replicability in Psychological Science A Crisis of Confidence? Perspect Psychol Sci. 2012. November 1;7(6):528–30. doi: 10.1177/1745691612465253 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33.Berger JO, Sellke T. Testing a point null hypothesis: the irreconcilability of P values and evidence. J Am Stat Assoc. 1987;82(397):112–22. [Google Scholar]
- 34.Ioannidis JP. Why most published research findings are false. PLoS Med. 2005;2(8):e124 doi: 10.1371/journal.pmed.0020124 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35.Cumming G. The new statistics why and how. Psychol Sci. 2013;0956797613504966. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36.Johnson VE. Revised standards for statistical evidence. Proc Natl Acad Sci. 2013;110(48):19313–7. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1313476110 [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37.Pritschet L, Powell D, Horne Z. Marginally Significant Effects as Evidence for Hypotheses Changing Attitudes Over Four Decades. Psychol Sci. 2016;0956797616645672. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38.Dienes Z. How Bayes factors change scientific practice. J Math Psychol. 2016;72:78–89. [Google Scholar]
- 39.Rouder JN. Optional stopping: No problem for Bayesians. Psychon Bull Rev. 2014;21(2):301–8. doi: 10.3758/s13423-014-0595-4 [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 40.Bayarri MJ, Benjamin DJ, Berger JO, Sellke TM. Rejection odds and rejection ratios: A proposal for statistical practice in testing hypotheses. J Math Psychol. 2016;72:90–103. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 41.JASP Team. JASP (Version 0.8.0.0). 2016.
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.
Supplementary Materials
Data Availability Statement
The authors confirm that all data underlying the findings are fully available without restriction. All relevant data are within the Supporting Information files.