Abstract
Purpose of review
Geographic variation in liver transplantation has been the subject of extensive scrutiny, reflecting concerns that location is unfairly determinative for people needing organ transplantation. Drawing upon a number of established ethical approaches, we examine whether geographic differences in access to livers are inherently unethical.
Recent findings
We posit that the ethical imperative for redistribution largely hinges upon the belief that access to organs is systematically disadvantages certain identifiable groups of patients over others. Yet, our data suggests that regions likely to be net-contributors may suffer from less access to transplantation and other health services, fewer social protections, and greater burden of liver disease. Drawing upon a number of ethical approaches, including: strict egalitarianism, utilitarianism, Maximin, Reciprocity, Sen’s Impartial Spectator, and a health equity framework, we demonstrate that the current proposal has significant weaknesses, and may not achieve its goals of improving equity and efficiency.
Summary
Formulating effective policies and programs to ameliorate health inequalities requires an understanding of the interrelated causes of mortality disparities and specific interventions to mitigate these causes. Although our analysis does not indicate how ethically distribute livers, but it suggests that this be done with consideration for population-based health measures.
Keywords: ethical analysis, geographic disparities, social capital, socioeconomic status, transplantation policy, liver transplant, liver allocation
INTRODUCTION
Although liver transplantation remains the only life-saving option for patients with end-stage liver disease (ESLD), the organ shortage has intensified, rendering this option unattainable for many. In 2015 12,001 patients were added to the national waiting list, while only 6,798 received a deceased-donor transplant.1,2 Access to liver transplantation varies significantly across the United States. Depending on where a patient is listed, the likelihood of receiving a liver transplant within 90-days varies from 18% to 86%.3 The 90-day likelihood of death on the waiting list varies from 14% to 82% for patients with MELD (Model for End-Stage Liver Disease) scores of 38-39 across all donor service areas (DSAs).
Geographic variation in liver transplantation has been the subject of extensive scrutiny, reflecting concerns that location is unfairly determinative for people needing organ transplantation. Consequently, in 2016, the Liver and Intestine Committee of the Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network (OPTN) put forth a redistricting proposal expanding geographic organ sharing to equalize median MELD scores at transplant.4 The proposal has been divisive, pitting centers likely to lose organs with those likely to gain organs. Opponents argue that sending livers from areas with greater relative supply and lower median MELD scores to areas with higher median MELD scores unfairly disadvantages local donors and will increase costs associated with organ transport. Proponents argue that local prioritization unjustly advantages some due to arbitrary circumstance, such as being born in or residing in a given state or DSA, and that persons living in areas with longer waiting times deserve redistribution.
The debate about geographic differences begs the question: Are geographic differences in access to livers inherently unethical? We posit that the ethical imperative for redistribution largely hinges upon the belief that access to organs is truly arbitrary, an “accident of geography”, systematically disadvantages certain identifiable groups of patients over others. We examine these beliefs, and drawing from a number of normative approaches, we analyze the moral imperative for broader geographic sharing of livers and implications for fair, equitable, and efficient organ allocation.
a. Differences versus disparities
A health equity framework posits that all people should have a fair opportunity to live a long and healthy life and to receive access to life-saving treatment irrespective of geography, race, ethnicity, sexual orientation, income, and other social conditions. Although numerous definitions for disparities exist, injustice is a key element of all definitions. As an example, the Whitehead-Dahlgren definition, employed by the World Health Organization, defines disparities as systematic “differences in health which are not only unnecessary and avoidable but, in addition, are considered unfair and unjust.”5 Differences, by contrast, reflect gaps that are not morally laden, such as differing treatment preferences for western versus eastern medicine or differences in hair color or blood type. Determining whether a health difference is considered unfair depends on the degree to which the situation is freely chosen, modifiable, and results in poor health. For example, poor populations may have little choice about living in unsafe and unhealthy environments, whereas differences in injury rates associated with participation in chosen leisure activities (e.g. skiing) are freely chosen and would not be considered unfair.
Does variation in liver availability constitute a disparity, systematically disadvantaging socially underserved groups, or does it merely constitute a difference? Proponents of redistricting argue that higher median MELD scores of waitlisted patients and long waiting times in some regions reflect a disparity, with patients in these regions unjustly deprived access to life-saving treatments. Yet, others point to greater access to transplantation in these regions and superior survival on the waitlist.6
To determine whether geographic differences in liver availability reflect disparities, we must consider what the residual difference is, holding constant individual-level characteristics that are unrelated to social justice. To do so, we consider the counterfactual reality: meaning, we imagine how much would change if a person were to live in different region. We may consider a hypothetical patient with ESLD living in New York, California, or Massachusetts (regions with high-demand and low relative supply), and imagine that same patient’s circumstances as if she were a resident of South Carolina, Tennessee, or Kansas (areas with high-supply and relatively low demand). In this thought experiment, stipulate that individual-level characteristics (race, ethnicity, gender, age, disease severity) are held constant. However, other contextual factors, such as access to care, quality of care, exposure to environmental risks, likelihood of employment, insurance status, or median income level may differ significantly in the counterfactual life.
In considering this hypothetical, one may note that, in many respects, life in states with more severe liver shortages appears to be preferable from a health and well-being perspective to that of states with higher relative supply. For example, the largest contributors to mortality disparities in the United States are chronic diseases and injuries with established socially-patterned risk factors, including: alcohol and tobacco policies, availability of healthcare, levels of violent crime, rates of vehicular accidents, and obesity.7 These risk factors are disproportionately prevalent in regions with high organ supply.7 Stronger social protections and public safety laws, healthcare infrastructure, and public funding influence donor-eligible mortality rates and subsequent availability of donors.8 Data suggest that states with stronger safety nets may have lower risks of death from traumatic head injuries resulting from vehicular accidents or gunshot wounds, anoxic brain injuries from cardiac arrests, and cerebrovascular accidents.9–11,12 In addition, greater access to high-quality health care, especially to transplantation for a larger proportion of ESLD patients, appears to partially explain more people being waitlisted, and therefore higher relative demand for liver transplantation.6,13 Indeed, survival among waitlisted patients in areas of greater liver scarcity is higher compared to ESLD patients residing in regions with more limited access to transplantation, potentially reflecting better care.6 Higher median incomes, higher rates of health insurance, lower unemployment rates, access to superior Medicaid coverage, and greater access to high-quality care, especially to transplant centers, suggests that the relative liver shortage may be indicative of superior health and longevity. This account suggests that waitlist disparities described in the redistricting proposal may not constitute a disparity, but instead may be a difference. Consequently, policies calling for organ redistribution from high-supply to low-supply regions may exacerbate existing social and health disparities by redistributing the single benefit (greater organ availability) without redistributing the risks of the donating group (greater risk of violent death, scarcer access to transplantation).
While the tenets of public health and medicine necessitate concern with all determinants of morbidity and mortality, they assign a special moral imperative to rectify disparities over differences, as disparities have been partly caused by unjust social forces. This ethical approach is consistent with policy changes adopted by the UNOS that attempt to rectify disparities over differences, e.g. reducing the importance of HLA-matching to mitigate racial disparities in kidney allocation. Instead of broader sharing of organs, rectifying health disparities could require expanding access to health care, improving transportation, and strengthening financial supports especially to residents in underserved areas.
b. Maximin Principle
Another approach to prioritizing scarce resources is to consider the Maximin rule, which specifies that we select the alternative whose worst outcome leaves the population, specifically the most vulnerable, better off than the worst outcome of all other alternatives. Often cited as part of Rawls’ Theory of Justice., it too relies on a thought experiment: in this case the veil of ignorance.14 Rawls posits that, behind a “veil of ignorance” which blinds us to our particular place in society (class, race, ethnicity, income, etc.), the rational choice would be to protect ourselves from the worst-off scenario by ensuring that all people are provided an adequate share of primary goods guaranteeing equal basic liberties, fair equality of opportunity, and an adequate social minimum for all citizens. In this case, one must question whether redistributing organs would worsen the lot of the most vulnerable.
All things equal, patients awaiting livers in any region are vulnerable and will die without access to transplantation. However, data suggest that waitlisted patients in regions with a more severe shortage experience superior waitlist survival comparatively, and as such, may be considered somewhat better-off.6 Moreover, redistributing organs based solely on characteristics of the waiting list may violate liberal egalitarian conceptions of justice. Although Rawls does not explicitly consider health due to a simplifying assumption, the Maximin Principle prioritizes concern for the worst-off and most vulnerable who, due to socially determined causes, may never reach the waiting list.6 By numerous standards (described above), the plight of residents from states that would be net organ contributors may unparalleled. If availability of organs reflects a higher likelihood of dying prematurely and less access to life-saving treatments, redistributing organs from these underserved populations may compound their disadvantage. If social determinants result in limited access to preventative care, disproportionate ESLD burden, high levels of poverty and unemployment, inadequate subsidies for health insurance, and less access to health care services, including transplantation, there may be grounds to be concerned with redistributing these organs.
c. Reciprocity
A reciprocity argument, although weaker, but may also apply. It suggests that local claims to local organs are supported by two arguments: First, local claimants endure exposures that place them at a uniquely high risk of becoming organ donors, and this disproportionate risk justifies proportional benefit. Second, focusing on the waitlist considers only single factor in determining who is worst-off, yet, organ availability should not be considered in isolation because it is a function of many factors, including social determinants of health and divergent health and social policies. Finally, some have noted that prioritizing localities encourages donation and strengthens social norms related to organ donation.15,16
d. Utility (efficiency)
Another consequentialist approach, utilitarianism, suggests that it is best to select the option that will improve efficiency by saving more lives and reducing organ waste. Proponents of the proposal also suggest that ethnic disparities may decrease, although the number of liver transplants for blacks would remain unchanged. Proponents suggest that redistricting would save upwards of 676 lives over 5 years, in addition to saving an estimated $161 million dollars on Medicare payments for clinical care before, during, and after transplant in the new 8 district model.17
Yet, controversy of these estimates remains. Ladner and Mehrota raise methodological concerns with the proposal, including uncertainty inherent to the models.18 Estimates suggest that the proposal may increase costs and risks associated with transporting organs and surgical teams across long distances, and may favor population-dense urban regions over rural impoverished regions.19–21 Skeptics cite broader geographic sharing implemented in Region 8 from 2010-2012 which did not significantly reduce mortality but raised costs significantly. Patients served by smaller transplant centers may experience disproportionate cost increases and worse outcomes associated with low volume.19
Although the utilitarian approach is appealing due to its simplicity (weighing costs against benefits), its application relies upon accurate estimates. Without greater consensus about the costs and benefits, both financial and lives-saved, it is unclear whether a utilitarian would support redistricting.
e. Strict Egalitarianism
A strict egalitarian approach may provide support for a single national list, and thus, for reducing the gap between areas with greater and lesser liver supply. With the argument that all members of society deserve equal access, a strict egalitarian may move to abolish regions entirely and use urgency (MELD) or other criteria to determine priority. While perhaps intuitively appealing, the limitations to this approach are numerous, including feasibility objections. This approach may also result in widening disparities if areas more saturated with transplant centers list more patients (thereby offering preferential treatment due to proximity to a transplant center).
f. Impartial Spectator
Amartya Sen conveys the inherent challenge of distributive justice problems and determining how to proceed justly when there are a plurality of “right” answers and deserving parties.22 Sen observes that many inequalities which cannot be justified, such as differences in health, education, and well-being, favor the wealthier and more powerful. He argues that when attempting fair redistribution, we must consider the imbalance of privilege as a guiding principle. The privileged have a special obligation to adopt the viewpoint of an “impartial spectator”, assuming the perspective of those whose life chances are severely restricted compared to their own. Those with resources must recognize and respect the interests of the poor and powerless, and with that, the interdependence of people across the country.
Although Sen’s The Idea of Justice objects to some of Rawls’ assumptions, he argues in a similar vein (albeit for different reasons) that we ought to be concerned with the most vulnerable. Through this lens, Sen’s approach offers a reasoned justification for questioning the broader geographic sharing as currently proposed because of unintended effects on those already disadvantaged. Those living in regions with fewer social protections may be at higher risk for dying prematurely and as a result, residents of these regions may have access to a greater supply of organs. Consequently, shorter waits for organs may be the only direct benefit of noninterventionist social policies, including: riskier traffic safety laws, higher crime rates, and less access to healthcare. As such, people residing in areas with poor social protections collectively assume disproportionately higher risks than those living in areas with more generous social policies, which may entitle them to greater priority for organs obtained locally. Proposed redistricting based on reducing MELD disparities fails to account for underlying social determinants.19 Sen cautions us not to equalize access to organs at the expense of a donor class, and not to view those with greater access to organs but less access to transplant centers as less deserving. Instead, he prompts us to consider redistributing health resources, and not organs, as a more fair solution.
CONCLUSION
Fairly balancing considerations for equity and efficiency is a perpetual challenge for the transplant community, and consequently, priorities for organ allocation are ever-evolving based on new data. Drawing upon a number of ethical approaches underscores concerns that redistricting may amplify disparities, not alleviate them. Formulating effective policies and programs to ameliorate health inequalities requires an understanding of the interrelated causes of mortality disparities and specific interventions to mitigate these causes. Although our analysis does not indicate how ethically distribute livers, but it suggests that this be done with consideration for population-based health measures.
Key points.
Drawing upon a number of ethical approaches underscores concerns that redistricting may amplify disparities, not alleviate them.
Formulating effective policies and programs to ameliorate health inequalities requires an understanding of the interrelated causes of mortality disparities and specific interventions to mitigate these causes.
To ethically distribute livers, attention must be paid to population-based health measures
Acknowledgments
none
Financial support and sponsorship
Dr. Ladin gratefully acknowledges financial support from the National Center for Advancing Translational Sciences, National Institutes of Health, Award Number KL2TR001063 and the Greenwall Foundation’s “Making a Difference” grant.
Footnotes
Conflicts of interest
The authors have no conflicts of interests and no additional financial disclosures to report. The content is solely the responsibility of the authors and does not necessarily represent the official views of the NIH or the Greenwall Foundation.
References
- 1.Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, editor. Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network. Waiting List Additions Age by Listing Year, Liver. Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network; 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 2.Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network, editor. Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network. Removal Reasons by Year, Liver. Organ Procurement and Transplantation Network; 2016. [Google Scholar]
- 3.Massie AB, Caffo B, Gentry SE, et al. MELD Exceptions and Rates of Waiting List Outcomes. American Journal of Transplantation. 2011;11:2362–71. doi: 10.1111/j.1600-6143.2011.03735.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Liver and Intestinal Organ Transplantation Committee. Redesigning Liver Distribution: Organ Procurement Transplantation Network. 2015 [Google Scholar]
- 5.Dahlgren G, Whitehead M. Policies and Strategies to Promote Social Equity in Health. Stockholm: Institute for Future Studies; 1991. [Google Scholar]
- 6**.Goldberg D, French B, Shahota G, Wallace A, Lewis J, Halpern S. Use of population-based data to demonstrate how waitlist-based metrics overestimate geographic disparities in access to liver transplant care. American Journal of Transplantation. 2016 doi: 10.1111/ajt.13820. Epub ahead of print. Liver allocation policies are evaluated by how they impact waitlisted patients, without considering broader outcomes for all patients with end-stage liver disease (ESLD) not on the waitlist. Compared to population-based metrics, waitlist-based metrics overestimate geographic disparities in access to liver transplantation. This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7.García MC, Bastian B, Rossen LM, et al. Potentially Preventable Deaths Among the Five Leading Causes of Death—United States 2010 and 2014. MMWR Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report. 2016;65 doi: 10.15585/mmwr.mm6545a1. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Reported Eligible Deaths and Recovered Deceased Donors 2008 to 2016. Accessed Accessed December 1, 2016., at http://www.aopo.org/related-links-data-on-donation-and-transplantation/
- 9.Crime in the United States by State. 2013 Accessed December 18, 2016, at https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/cjis/ucr/crime-in-the-u.s/2013/crime-in-the-u.s.-2013/tables/5tabledatadecpdf/table_5_crime_in_the_united_states_by_state_2013.xls.
- 10.Dickert-Conlin S, Elder T, Moore B. Donorcycles: Motorcycle Helmet Laws and the Supply of Organ Donors Journal of Law and Economics Forthcoming [Google Scholar]
- 11.Adler JT, Yeh H. Social Determinants in Liver Transplantation. Clinical Liver Disease. 2016;7:15–7. doi: 10.1002/cld.525. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Rana A, Kaplan B, Riaz IB, et al. Geographic Inequities in Liver Allograft Supply and Demand: Does it Affect Patient Outcomes? Transplantation. 2015;99:515–20. doi: 10.1097/TP.0000000000000372. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Garwe T, Cowan LD, Neas BR, Sacra JC, Albrecht RM. Directness of transport of major trauma patients to a level I trauma center: a propensity-adjusted survival analysis of the impact on short-term mortality. Journal of Trauma and Acute Care Surgery. 2011;70:1118–27. doi: 10.1097/TA.0b013e3181e243b8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 14.Rawls JA. Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press; 1971. [Google Scholar]
- 15*.Ladin K, Wang R, Fleishman A, Boger M, Rodrigue JR. Does Social Capital Explain Community-Level Differences in Organ Donor Designation? The Milbank quarterly. 2015;93:609–41. doi: 10.1111/1468-0009.12139. Because community-level factors, including social capital, predict more than half the variation in donor designation, interventions to reduce geographic variation in organ availability should tailor strategies to specific communities as the unit of intervention. Understanding the contextual determinants of organ donor designation, including social capital, may enhance efforts to increase organ donation by raising the probability of collective action and fostering norms of cooperation and altruism associated with organ donation. Local priority may also help encourage social capital related to organ donation. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16.Ladin K. Organ Donation as a Collective Action Problem: Ethical Considerations and Implications for Practice. AMA journal of ethics. 2016;18:156–62. doi: 10.1001/journalofethics.2016.18.2.msoc1-1602. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 17.Gentry S, Chow E, Dzebisashvili N, et al. The impact of redistricting proposals on health care expenditures for liver transplant candidates and recipients. American Journal of Transplantation. 2015 doi: 10.1111/ajt.13569. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18**.Ladner DP, Mehrotra S. Methodological Challenges in Solving Geographic Disparity in Liver Allocation. JAMA surgery. 2015:1–2. doi: 10.1001/jamasurg.2015.3937. The authors point to methodological weakness in the current liver redistricting proposal and advocate for a rigorous independent external peer review of both data inputs and the modeling methods, transparency, and a fair process for a critique. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19.Reed A, Chapman WC, Knechtle S, Chavin K, Gilroy R, Klintmalm GB. Equalizing MELD scores over broad geographies is not the most efficacious way to allocate a scarce resource in a value-based environment. Annals of Surgery. 2015;262:220–3. doi: 10.1097/SLA.0000000000001331. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 20.DuBay D, MacLennan P, Reed R, et al. The impact of proposed changes in liver allocation policy on cold ischemia times and organ transportation costs. American Journal of Transplantation. 2015;15:541–6. doi: 10.1111/ajt.12981. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 21.Kappel D, Chapman W, Conrad S, et al. Organ procurement organization liver acquisition costs could more than double with proposed redistricts. American Journal of Transplantation. 2015;15:2269–70. doi: 10.1111/ajt.13346. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 22.Sen A. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press: Harvard University Press; 2009. [Google Scholar]