Abstract
Nightly transitions into sleep are usually uneventful and transpire in the blink of an eye. But in the laboratory these transitions afford a unique view of how experience is transformed from the perceptually grounded consciousness of wakefulness to the hallucinatory simulations of dreaming. The present review considers imagery in the sleep-onset transition—“microdreams” in particular—as an alternative object of study to dreaming as traditionally studied in the sleep lab. A focus on microdream phenomenology has thus far proven fruitful in preliminary efforts to (i) develop a classification for dreaming’s core phenomenology (the “oneiragogic spectrum”), (ii) establish a structure for assessing dreaming’s multiple memory inputs (“multi-temporal memory sources”), (iii) further Silberer’s project for classifying sleep-onset images in relation to waking cognition by revealing two new imagery types (“autosensory imagery,” “exosensory imagery”), and (iv) embed a potential understanding of microdreaming processes in a larger explanatory framework (“multisensory integration approach”). Such efforts may help resolve outstanding questions about dream neurophysiology and dreaming’s role in memory consolidation during sleep but may also advance discovery in the neuroscience of consciousness more broadly.
Keywords: sleep and dreaming, mind wandering, hypnagogia, sleep onset, binding and multisensory integration, imagery
Limits of Traditional REM Sleep Dream Studies
The discovery that vivid dreaming accompanies recurrent bouts of rapid eye movement (REM) sleep (Aserinsky and Kleitman, 1953; Dement and Kleitman, 1957) was heralded as a major methodological breakthrough for the study of dream neurophysiology. The advantages were clear: investigators now possessed a method that gave immediate and predictable access to the vast reservoir of oneiric activity; activity that could be recorded in near real time with little distortion and under controlled conditions. Researchers were quick to exploit REM sleep to address fundamental questions about dreaming such as: “Is there a biological need for dreaming?” and “How does dreaming vary with sleep stage?” And although some progress was made using these laboratory methods, many fundamental questions remain unanswered. In particular, questions about the neurophysiological correlates of dreaming were not satisfactorily resolved, despite repeated attempts to assess both macro- and microphysiological sleep events. Evidence supporting psychophysiological isomorphism was so scant that Foulkes (1985, p. 4), a leader in the area, abandoned psychophysiological studies as moribund in favor of a more strictly cognitive framework.
Some insights were gleaned from neuropsychological assessments of brain-lesioned individuals (Solms, 1997), but the relationships uncovered remain imprecise and fall short of clarifying either the brain networks that sustain dreaming or the measures that reliably index it. Many studies did attempt to link dream recall or dream content attributes with specific neurophysiological indicators, most commonly with electroencephalograpy (EEG) measures, but such studies provide mixed results at best. For example, EEG correlates of remembering dreaming after REM sleep awakenings vary widely, from power reductions in alpha (Bertolo et al., 2003; Esposito et al., 2004; Chellappa and Cajochen, 2013), delta (Esposito et al., 2004), frontal beta (Chellappa et al., 2011), and 4- to 14-Hz activity (Lehmann et al., 1981), to power increases in 40-Hz (Llinas and Ribary, 1993), occipital beta (Chellappa et al., 2011), and theta (Marzano et al., 2011; Scarpelli et al., 2015). Studies attempting to uncover EEG signatures for specific dream qualities were quite uncommon (e.g. Nielsen and Chénier, 1999).
This discovery shortfall in dream neuroscience may have been due, paradoxically, to an overabundance of phenomenological and neurophysiological information. Researchers attempted to quantify, in parallel, extended multisensory sequences of dreaming on the one hand and multifactorial arrays of neurophysiological signals on the other. Yet, approaches that attempt to align such complex phenomena are largely unstandardized, with little agreement on what levels of description and types of measurement are appropriate to assess them. This is, ultimately, an unresolved problem of isomorphic mapping (Nielsen, 2000) or, more recently, of delineating the neural correlates of consciousness (Hohwy and Bayne, 2015).
The pitfalls of such a multicomponent undertaking are too numerous to detail here but they include factors such as reliance on subjects untrained in the introspective reporting of dreams, failure to control for inaccuracies in recalling and reporting long dream sequences, assessment of EEG signals in the frequency (not the time) domain, use of broad-band EEG definitions and use of a limited number of EEG leads, among others.
In this regard, some recent studies have shown progress by focusing on increasingly brief dream events and more precise neurophysiological signals (see review in Nir and Tononi, 2010). Notably, machine learning models have been applied to visual cortical functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) activity to extract patterns that accurately predict visual elements in sleep-onset dreams (Horikawa et al., 2013). Other promising approaches (Andrillon et al., 2015) demonstrate similarities in the intracranial, single-neuron activity of rapid eye movements and waking percept-driven eye movements. One approach that uses multiple, serial awakenings (Germain and Nielsen, 2001; Noreika et al., 2009, 2015; Stenstrom et al., 2012; Siclari et al., 2013; Nieminen et al., 2016) has shown particular promise for expediting the collection and assessment of sleep-onset imagery and could complement the microdreaming method espoused here. Serial awakening involves the collection of multiple reports following awakenings contingent upon either experimenter-determined “neuro-centric” criteria, e.g. following randomly presented tone stimuli (Siclari et al., 2013) or target EEG configurations (Foulkes and Vogel, 1965; Germain and Nielsen, 2001; Stenstrom et al., 2012), or “phenomeno-centric” criteria, i.e. subjects themselves signaling occurrences of imagery (Germain and Nielsen, 2001; Noreika et al., 2015). Nieminen et al. (2016) combined serial awakenings with transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) to show that TMS during non-REM (NREM) sleep evokes smaller negative deflections when there is recall of dreaming than when there is no recall; in fact, deflection amplitude correlates negatively with dream report length. These studies have brought several new neural activity measures into play, e.g. phase-locked oscillations (Nieminen et al., 2016) and dimension-of-activation (Noreika et al., 2015) but the elaboration of phenomenological features continues to lag behind. It is precisely here that the microdreaming approach, with its emphasis on detailed phenomenological description, may contribute most to the ongoing development of second-person approaches.
In sum, early laboratory methods of REM-period awakenings for sampling dreaming have not resulted in a substantially clearer portrait of dreaming’s neurophysiological underpinnings. The overabundance of information and an intractable isomorphic mapping problem failed to demonstrate reliable relationships between these two domains of measurement. Newer methodologies targeting more discrete events show promise in resolving this problem—although phenomenological advances are disproportionately needed.
An Alternative Approach: Microdynamic Neurophenomenology
Accordingly, discovery in dream science may benefit from neurophenomenological approaches such as those applied to uncovering the neural correlates of consciousness (Thompson and Varela, 2001; Lutz et al., 2002; Garrison et al., 2013). For example, one such approach (Petitmengin and Lachaux, 2013) employs a convergence of phenomenological and neural descriptions that are both aimed at brief cognitive events. The approach has been applied successfully to the study of waking-state visual imagery (Hamame et al., 2012) among other phenomena. The feasibility of applying microdynamic neural approaches to studies of dreaming is supported by advances in brain imaging, such as the delineation of EEG-defined microstates (Milz et al., 2015) and the development of real-time fMRI (Garrison et al., 2013) and high-density EEG (Mouthon and Huber, 2015) procedures, together with increasingly precise descriptions of sleep-onset EEG events.
A few studies support the feasibility of applying microdynamic approaches to dream neurophenomenology by simplifying neurophysiological measures and targeting specific features of dream content. In one early study (Gardner et al., 1975), subjects reported, in reverse order, only the last 15 s of dream content, and quantified their upper and lower dream limb movements; electromyography (EMG) tracings revealed correspondences between these and real limb activities that occurred within 5 s of waking up. At an even finer scale of measurement (Herman et al., 1984), subjects were trained to report only the last “few seconds” of dreamed content paying particular attention to reorientations of the eyes and head, while real pre-awakening eye movements were recorded. Again, correspondences between the directionality of dreamed and real eye movements were found.
Despite these preliminary successes, the approaches remain confounded by the very richness of the dream imagery upon which their analyses are based. First, it is problematic isolating experiential units from a large array of dream imagery and fixing these to a time scale that is reliably synchronized with neurophysiological signals. A second, related, problem is the “forward momentum” of vivid dreaming: experiential events activated at one time may remain active for an indeterminate duration and continue to shape and color events arising later. This is the phenomenological equivalent of how “upstream” neural correlates of a conscious state complicate identification of the current neural correlates of that state (Hohwy and Bayne, 2015). Third, the multisensory, multicomponent nature of rich dream imagery raises the difficulty of identifying discrete channels of information to match with neural events; different channels (e.g. visual, auditory, kinesthetic, etc.) are typically intertwined and may be wholly or partially associated with a given neural measure (e.g. EEG power). These confounds are only amplified as dream imagery becomes more vivid, extended, emotional, and multisensory—as is common for late night REM dreams. In contrast, images occurring at the very brink of sleep onset are easier to pinpoint temporally, are less influenced by forward momentum, and are simpler in structure—all features that facilitate identifying their neural correlates.
We demonstrated the feasibility of assessing microdreams in a laboratory protocol (Germain and Nielsen, 2001) in which subjects signaled precisely when brief sleep-onset images appeared in awareness. Specific relationships between image sensory modality, and EEG frequency and topography 9 s prior to the images were found; kinesthetic images possessed higher delta power in frontal regions (Fp1, Fp2, F3, Fz, F8) than did visual images, which were linked to higher delta power in mainly left central and temporal leads (F7, C3, Cz, T3, T5). Phenomenological precision in this study was relatively crude (subjective ratings of sensory imagery), but feasibility of the method was nonetheless validated. Similarly, this phenomeno-centric approach was validated in a study of a single highly trained subject who reported multiple-sleep-onset images (Noreika et al., 2015); purely linguistic images were accompanied by higher left alpha and gamma power and other perceptual images by higher right beta power.
In sum, rather than grappling with the overly large data sets of traditional research, dream science could benefit from focusing a microdynamic lens on the neurophysiological fluctuations that accompany the much briefer images of sleep onset. We developed a first-person self-observational approach to study sleep-onset imagery (Nielsen, 1995) and subsequently adapted it to a second-person approach for use with untrained laboratory subjects (Germain and Nielsen, 2001). This first-person method is used in the present work to highlight the phenomenological advantages of a focus on microdream imagery. Following a brief review of the spectrum of sleep-onset imagery, I demonstrate how microdream images in particular can be exploited to more efficiently identify the defining attributes of hallucinatory content, to uncover multiple memory sources, including previously unrecognized sensory sources, and to model imagery formation processes.
The Spectrum of Sleep-Onset Imagery
Multiple studies (see reviews in Oswald, 1962; Schacter, 1976; Mavromatis and Richardson, 1984; Vogel, 1991) attest to the presence of vivid dreams during the sleep-onset transition (Ogilvie, 2001); dreams that vary considerably in structure, specificity, length, clarity, and presence or absence of different sensory modalities (Fig. 1). Both anecdotal and empirical studies identify a spectrum of imagery ranging from elaborate and dreamlike to simple and near–subliminal. This spectrum includes images that appear to arise squarely out of the waking state. At one extreme are the complex elaborate dreams that accompany sleep-onset REM (SOREM) and partial SOREM episodes. SOREM episodes are far from rare; 13–23% of normal subjects exhibit at least one episode on the Multiple Sleep Latency Test (Bishop et al., 1996; Singh et al., 2006). Partial SOREM episodes, during which some (but not all) signs of REM sleep are visible, are also common; episodes of muscle atonia—a defining feature of REM sleep—are particularly likely to occur at sleep onset, a phenomenon referred to as “muscle atonia in NREM sleep” (Werth et al., 2002; Tinguely et al., 2006). Less complex and elaborate dream imagery occurs in NREM Stage 1 (N1) and Stage 2 (N2) sleep. Recall of any item of dream imagery is high at these times, 90–98%, for sleep-onset stages N1 and N2 (Foulkes and Vogel, 1965; Vogel, 1991); even higher than the average level (80%) for nocturnal REM sleep (Nielsen, 2000). However, more complex dreaming, defined as involving hallucinated dramatic episodes, is more scarce from N1 and N2 than from REM sleep: 31–76% (Vogel, 1991). Nonetheless, there are very few qualitative differences between N1/N2 and REM mentation (see review in Vogel, 1991). At the other extreme of this spectrum are the microdream images most suitable to a microdynamic analytic approach. These tend to occur during drowsiness and waking reverie and, although their brevity renders them less complex, less affectively charged, and less socially and narratively developed than images from elsewhere on the spectrum, they nonetheless share the core pseudohallucinatory qualities of such imagery and are particularly well suited for study of these qualities.
More detailed analysis of the physiological changes accompanying sleep-onset imagery (Tanaka et al., 1998a, 1998b; Hayashi et al., 1999) led to a subdivision of standard wake (W), N1, and N2 stages into a progression of nine, more precise, EEG-based sub-stages (Fig. 2, left panel). The likelihood of recalling dream mentation is present to some degree even at sub-stage 1 and increases progressively up to sub-stage 5 (Fig. 2, upper right). Assessment of sensory attributes (Fig. 2, lower right) reveals that visual quality is high for all sub-stages, but plateaus at sub-stage 5 when all other sensory attributes diminish. Together, the results suggest that dreamlike imagery is particularly apt to arise early in sleep onset when alpha drops out and theta appears (sub-stages 4/5). Our own study (Germain and Nielsen, 2001), which used a phenomeno- rather than a neuro-centric method for sampling spontaneously arising images, confirmed this: the vast majority of signaled images (93.4% or 112/120) arose from sub-stages 4/5.
Finally, dreamlike imagery is sometimes reported when objective and subjective measures indicate wakefulness; almost 25% of “waking” imagery reports in two studies were qualitatively similar to REM dreams—e.g. bearing hallucinatory imagery (19%), regressive content (25%), or a total loss of contact with external reality (15%)—and were distinct from waking mentation such as mindwandering or being lost in thought (Foulkes and Scott, 1973; Foulkes and Fleisher, 1975). As these studies remain unreplicated, it is unknown whether the observed images are distinct attributes of waking state imagery or, in fact, microdreams for which the sleep signs were too subtle to quantify with methods available at the time. They may have occurred during “microsleeps,” which are sleep intrusions as brief as a fraction of a second (Tirunahari et al., 2003). Microsleeps are associated with localized deactivations of the brain in some regions (thalamus, posterior cingulate, occipital cortex) and localized activations in others (frontal, posterior parietal, parahippocampal), and display the smallest brain changes when they are the briefest in duration (0.5–5 s) (Poudel et al., 2014). Subjects commonly—sometimes adamantly—deny having slept during microsleep episodes despite clear electrophysiological (e.g. EEG) and behavioral (e.g. response failure) evidence to the contrary (Oswald, 1962, pp. 63–65).
Conclusion: an oneiragogic spectrum
Windt (2010, 2015), better than any previous author, delineates a comprehensive framework for describing the variety of sleep-onset imagery, what she dubs the spectrum of “oneiragogic experience.” This new term refers to the progression of phenomenological events leading from drowsy wakeful perception to full-fledged dreaming (Table 1, items 1–5) or “the trajectory underlying the shift in self-location from a perceptual to a hallucinatory (or dreamlike) reference frame” (Windt, 2015, p. 536). In other words, one’s sense of immersion in space and time (“here” and “now”) shifts progressively from a veridical framework (the real world) to a hallucinatory framework (the dream world). Windt considers the oneiragogic spectrum analogous to, but distinct from, the hypnagogic state, which describes a progression of physiological changes from wake to sleep. The oneiragogic spectrum forms part of a broader conceptual framework for dream phenomenology, the immersive spatiotemporal hallucination (ISTH) model (see Windt, 2015, chapter 11). Five dimensions are proposed to constitute the oneiragogic spectrum; I suggest adding to these a sixth dimension, kinesis, to describe the experience’s movement quality (Table 1, item 6).
Table 1.
ISTH dimension | Description | Simple extreme (closer to waking) | Complex extreme (closer to dreaming) |
---|---|---|---|
1. Visuospatial scene | A sense of being located at a specific point in a larger spatial expanse (“here”) | Isolated, static | Dynamic, prolonged, immersive |
2. Phenomenal embodiment | A sense of bodily awareness that progresses from passive observation to active participation | Partial body awareness (e.g. sleepiness feelings) | Full-body awareness |
3. Temporal reference frame | A sense of being located in a specific moment within a succession of moments (“now”) | Brief, isolated instant | Prolonged, organized narrative |
4. Waking memory sources | Integration of recent with increasingly remote memory sources | Recent, episodic memories | Remote, abstract, but semantically related memories |
5. Autobiographical historicity | A sense that an image is part of one’s autobiographical experience/memory (“recallability”) | Barely graspable as own experience, difficult to recall | Integration in autobiographic memory, easily recalled |
6. Spatiotemporal kinesis (proposed) | A sense of dynamism, movement | Ultra-brief, incipient, or isometric movement | Complex movements |
Whereas the concept of microdreams has been used to describe all sleep-onset imagery (see review in Oswald, 1962), its use is clearly inappropriate for more complex imagery forms, such as those reported from REM and partial REM episodes. I use the term microdream in a more limited sense to refer to images falling on the simpler extreme of the oneiragogic spectrum. In sum, the oneiragogic spectrum improves upon the phenomenological triage of imagery types in facilitating identification of particularly brief images of interest to the microdynamic approach.
Microdreaming
Because existing studies have typically treated sleep-onset imagery as of a single type, only rarely are simpler images contrasted with more complex ones, despite the fact that differences in dream report length have remained a central methodological concern of researchers who compare REM and NREM dream reports (Hunt et al., 1993). The only systematic studies that attempt to identify the simplest forms of images are self-observational in nature. From a set of over 250 sleep-onset images recorded under either laboratory or naturalistic conditions, and for which a preliminary phenomenological description is presented elsewhere (Nielsen, 1992, 1995), a subgroup of images referred to as “fleeting images” was identified that I here consider a type of microdream. Some examples appear in a later section. I distinguished these brief images from “fully-formed” images in respect to their timing, duration, simplicity, ineffability, and association with sleepiness feelings. In short, fleeting images were previously found to:
occur in the very earliest stages of a self-observation trial, i.e. during mild drowsiness;
be so brief that they often require an established intent (if not introspective training) to observe;
possess primarily unimodal sensory content;
frequently fall outside of the normal range of experience, thus defying easy description;
be accompanied by subtle feelings of falling asleep.
Fully formed images, in contrast, were found to:
occur later in the sleep-onset transition;
be longer and easier to recall;
possess a more complex, multimodal structure;
be easier to describe;
often mask accompanying sleepiness feelings.
Using the oneiragogic spectrum terminology, fleeting images may now be described more specifically to:
implicate an isolated spatiotemporal location (“here”);
include a sense of body awareness, however, ephemeral (e.g. sleepiness feelings);
occur in a discrete instant (“now”);
draw upon a few recent, episodic memories (e.g. ongoing sensory stimuli);
often be barely graspable and difficult to recall;
possess a subtle kinetic quality, i.e. sensed movement of self or setting.
Fully formed images, in contrast, more closely resemble REM dreams: they are spatiotemporally elaborate (multimodal), are more embodied and temporally extended, draw upon a wider swath of remote memory elements, are more fully integrated into one’s historical context (easily recalled), and are more obviously dynamic in character.
There is still no validated method for distinguishing fleeting microdreams from fully formed dream images, but the oneiragogic spectrum—possibly with the addition of the kinesis dimension—provides a thorough framework for drawing such distinctions clearly and reliably. With further development, it could serve as a standardized tool for classifying the phenomenological attributes of sleep-onset imagery. While extensive training in self-observation is not essential for collecting microdreams, accuracy can be improved by following an “upright napping” procedure (Nielsen, 1992, 1995). In two studies using upright napping, a maximum of 7 and 13 images/session, respectively, were recorded. In general, sitting upright prevents one from slipping into deep sleep thereby facilitating accurate recall. Immediate review and recording of imagery context, phenomenological details and memory sources is critical. Establishing an observational intent and applying structured rating scales to images is also valuable (Nielsen, 1995). Note that practice may well increase the likelihood of observing images, just as practice improves recall of morning dreams (Aspy, 2016), but it remains to be studied whether practice changes microdream content qualitatively.
Example microdream
An example microdream recorded in our sleep laboratory is shown in Fig. 3. The timing of this primarily kinesthetic image was signaled while falling asleep with a hand-held switch. The signal immediately follows the image, allowing its associated neurophysiological changes to be examined. Changes include occipital alpha decrease, REM atonia-like EMG decrease (Werth et al., 2002) and, possibly, a brief rapid eye movement.
The image was brief and unusual in that it consisted of apparent sensations of touch (“knocking”) and motion (“moving”) that seemed to occur inside the head. On the oneiragogic spectrum, it displays: (i) rudimentary spatiality (“inside”), including vague visuospatiality (“someone else’s head”), (ii) minimal embodiment (“head”), and (iii) minimal temporal extension (“[the knocking] is moving”). There was no report of (iv) memory sources, but (v) minimal historicity is suggested by the difficulty in recall (“vague visual impression”). Finally, the image possesses (vi) a clear spatially kinetic character in that the sensations changed dynamically over time (“knocking,” “moving”). Note that although the image memory sources were not reported or probed, the ready accessibility of these sources was previously demonstrated (Nielsen, 1995). Memory sources are considered in a later section.
Such simple oneiragogic experiences can be mined for evidence of features that define dreaming’s phenomenal core. These features are likely to be more easily discernible in simple images because these lack the common, albeit nonessential, features so typical of complex REM sleep imagery, e.g. emotion, visual/auditory details, or narrative structure. Windt (2015, pp. 517–520) argues that dreaming, including especially sleep-onset dreaming, may be purely spatial in nature, an argument bolstered by the observation that congenitally blind subjects report vivid dreaming despite their total absence of visual imagery in wakefulness (Kerr et al., 1982; Kerr and Domhoff, 2004). The next section argues that spatiotemporal kinesis may also be a defining feature of microdreaming.
Spatiotemporal kinesis
The kinetic attributes of a living organism are its capacity to move or react in its environment, usually in response to sources of stimulation. Analogously, an image’s kinetic qualities refer to its inherent dynamism, vitality, or moment-to-moment changeability within its hallucinatory context—and possibly also in response to its various memory sources of stimulation. Full-blown dreaming is clearly kinetic in this respect, rich with immersive self-movement, character actions and environmental flux that can all be linked to memory source elements. Microdreams, too, express this feature to some degree—even in their simplest, most ephemeral forms—and in this respect their phenomenal core is one with that of dreaming. Kinesis manifests most often as a realistic apparent movement of the self (or part of the self) or of another character, or of an apparent movement felt to take place inside the body. It also manifests as apparent movement of the environment in proximity to the self. But it may even occur in ways that are less obviously related to visuospatial modulation. For example, images containing vivid isometric tension or sensations of an imminent action or impending contact with some object or person may reflect a minimal form of spatial kinesis. In this respect, the present description of microdreams differs somewhat from that of Windt, who considers the simple extreme of microdreaming to be visuospatial stasis. Rather, kinesis may be as integral to the immersive nature of microdreams as it is to completely hallucinatory dream experiences. Whether all microdreams are kinetic, and how to quantify kinesis in its simplest forms are, therefore, fundamental empirical questions requiring further study.
Microdream memory sources
The study of microdreams offers unique possibilities for developing experimental methods to clarify how and why images are formed. These possibilities hinge on identifying an image’s memory associations, which are widely assumed to index the memory sources from which an image derives (Freud, 1900; Nielsen and Stenstrom, 2005). The following sections deal with three advantages of memory source analysis that microdreams confer, including how such work may contribute to the development of experimental methods for investigating image formation processes.
Access to multi-temporal memory associations
The memory sources of microdreams are few but readily accessible. Because microdream images are brief and occur in such close proximity to wakefulness, attention can be directed quickly and flexibly to identifying their source memories. Using a self-observational approach, we previously demonstrated both the feasibility of identifying memory sources and that these sources are relatively few in number (Stenstrom et al., 2012). Figure 4 shows all memories associated with 31 sleep-onset images collected from a single subject, classified by the memories’ times since occurrence. The number of memories for each image is clearly restrained: on average 2.6 ± 1.1 (range 1–5) per image (Contrast this with Freud’s memory source analysis of his “Irma’s Injection” dream: 332 words of dream and 4130 words of memory sources). For a majority of these images, memories were drawn simultaneously from both recent and remote time periods, a finding consistent with other research for dream imagery (Verdone, 1965). Further, systematic variations in the temporal distance of these memories from the target image suggests that their access may have been modulated by time of night and, possibly, day of week factors. For example, on both Nights 1 and 2 memories for elements that were encountered just prior to sleep (e.g. lab technician, EEG equipment) were clearly reported for the first four images of the night; yet, for Night 1 these very recent memories tended to diminish for later night images, while for Night 2 they persisted. Such variation may mean that circadian factors modulate access to memory sources (for review, see Nielsen, 2011) or that habituation to the laboratory and the self-observational method takes place before access to memory sources is stable. In either event, this case study illustrates the ease of both collecting memory sources at sleep onset and evaluating their temporal distances from a target image.
Sample memory source analysis
The following example describes a microdream's memory sources arising from multiple time periods and illustrates a hypothetical model that could explain formation of the image (for analysis, see Nielsen, 1995). The proposed multi-temporal classification of memory sources consists of four categories differentiated by their temporal distance from the target image:
Immediate memory: thoughts, perceptions, and sensations that are ongoing or occurred only moments before image onset. Might include sensations of pressure in the arms, legs, or neck that manifest as arm, leg, or head imagery.
Short-term memory: experiences that occurred minutes to hours prior to image onset. Relatively easy to identify, occurring only a short time before the observation session.
Medium-term memory: experiences that occurred one or more days prior to the image. Include memories from the previous day (day-residue effect; Freud, 1900; Nielsen and Powell, 1992) and from 6 to 8 days earlier (dream-lag effect; Nielsen et al., 2004; van Rijn et al., 2015). These sources may be difficult to retrieve but access can be facilitated by a systematic review of salient events from the previous week.
Long-term memory: experiences that occurred weeks, months, or years prior to the image. May be difficult to identify and have been investigated only minimally. Are often rooted in declarative memory and resemble “semantic knowledge” memory sources (Cicogna et al., 1991).
Figure 5 illustrates a 1-s microdream collected by the author in a naturalistic setting (seated with left elbow resting on table, knuckles supporting chin), immediately recorded in detail (right panel) and depicted with components listed in chronological order (left panel, X-axis, bottom row). Its associated memory elements were also recorded and classified according to the four-part temporal distance scheme (Y-axis). These sources are arranged in a hypothetical chronological sequence with causal influences indicated by arrows.
A qualitative comparison of the image elements and memory sources suggested that the image is a close, but not exact, reproduction of a distinctive episodic memory fragment, i.e. performing a quasi-reflexive arm movement during a volleyball game 6 days earlier. This fragment possesses a sequential structure that is mirrored in the microdream: the visual approach of the ball, the rapid motor response of the arm, and the cutaneous feedback from contact with the ball, which were all experienced a single time during a real volleyball exchange, are represented in slightly altered form but in the same chronological sequence. This primary memory fragment is modified by several secondary fragments such that the final image does not faithfully depict the episodic memory, e.g. the original arm movement became completely reflexive in the image; the ball’s trajectory was altered; the ball’s size and weight became appropriate to a larger, lighter beach ball, etc. Such transformations of episodic elements may reflect the piecemeal nature of episodic memory storage (e.g. Brady et al., 2013) or the influence of consolidation mechanisms that transform episodic into semantic memories (e.g. Stickgold, 2002).
The memory sources identified by this simple descriptive analysis lend themselves to hypothetical causal models of image formation. One type, a real-time model illustrated by the connecting arrows in Fig. 5, might stipulate that memory sources are combined successively in the order shown. The notion of “transformative priming” is suggested as a basic mechanism of such real-time combination such that each memory source both triggers (primes) and merges with (transforms) a subsequent memory or imagery element. Alternatively, an off-line model might suggest that the image sequence emerges fully formed into awareness, without the need for real-time integration, i.e. memory elements are combined in the days, hours, minutes, or even seconds prior to the image but not in real time. A similar mechanism was postulated to account for some symbolic dream elements (Freud, 1900). Yet other models might be proposed that stipulate combinations of real-time and off-line influences. Figure 5 is but a starting point, intended to demonstrate that much of the evidence needed to explore such hypotheses is accessible from a thorough description of image and memory sources. And unlike previous efforts to analyze the memory sources of lengthy dream reports (Freud, 1900; Foulkes, 1978), microdreams offer a much simpler set of phenomenological observations and require a more limited number of hypothetical constructs to explain their formation.
Access to cognitive and somatic imagery sources: autosymbolic imagery
Microdreams are particularly useful for exploring the potential influences of recent memory sources to the extent that these reflect specific episodic experiences as opposed to general semantic knowledge. This is amply demonstrated by Silberer’s (1951) study of autosymbolic images, or images that automatically reflect ongoing waking states, thoughts, or feelings. He suggested three types:
Material images: These reflect the contents of pre-imagery thoughts, such as an abstract idea (e.g. thinking about the nature of transsubjectivity) being represented by a perceptual image (e.g. dreaming of a transparent sphere with peoples’ heads in it).
Functional (effort) images: These reflect attributes of the pre-imagery thinking process, such as a quality of cognitive activity (e.g. losing one’s train of thought) being reflected symbolically (e.g. image of a line of text with no ending).
Somatic images: These reflect the influence of sensations of any kind, such as somatic sensations (e.g. taking a deep breath) being reflected metaphorically (e.g. dream of lifting a table high in the air).
Silberer suggested—but did not empirically demonstrate—that autosymbolic images could be employed to examine dream production mechanisms experimentally. Experimental methods have, in fact, been used to influence the dreams of REM sleep (see review in Arkin and Antrobus, 1991), but Silberer’s examples did not employ such experimental controls. His posthoc observations of juxtapositions between images and memory elements do not guarantee that they are causally linked. Underlying factors that straddle sleep/wake state may produce both the memory source and the closely related image that follows it. Nonetheless, some self-observations reported below do support Silberer’s causality assumption. While anecdotal, these bolster the feasibility of developing more thorough experimental approaches to investigate microdreams and to model their formation mechanisms.
Silberer’s focus on immediate waking state precursors to microdream imagery suggests avenues of study that could overlap related methods for assessing consciousness dissolution during, e.g. meditation (Lehmann et al., 2001) or induced unconsciousness (Mashour, 2011). To illustrate, while there is evidence that sleep-like increases in delta power and neural network fragmentation accompany propofol anesthesia (Lewis et al., 2012; Purdon et al., 2013), such studies often address only the simplest phenomenological constituents of consciousness—e.g. its presence or absence. Microdream research, with its emphasis on phenomenological exactness, could contribute substantially to developments in this domain.
Access to causal factors in image formation
To facilitate causal analysis and modeling in microdream research, I suggest broadening Silberer’s three-part classification to include instances in which memory stimuli are more obviously linked causally to images. I suggest both adding a fourth type of autosymbolic imagery—“autosensory imagery”—to the list and expanding upon Silberer’s third type of imagery (somatic) to include “exosensory imagery.”
Autosensory imagery
An autosensory image is shaped by a self-generated stimulus that occurs immediately prior to the image’s appearance in awareness. The self-generated stimulus usually stems from a neuromuscular event like a muscle twitch, body jerk, or nodding of the head while falling asleep but may also include sounds like snoring, wheezing, or verbalization. Such events may even be triggered by one image only to merge with a subsequent one. Thus, a particularly kinetic microdream, such as poking an object with a dream finger, may produce an overt dream-enacting behavior (finger twitch) that stimulates a sensation of touch in a different body region (adjacent skin)—a sensation that feeds into and modifies a subsequent (autosensory) image. An autosensory image involving touch could be differentiated from others as “autosomatic” in that the image’s embodiment dimension is altered. Autosomatic images are the most common type I have observed although other types are possible: “autoacoustic” images for auditory stimuli (e.g. hearing one’s own voice or movements) or “autovestibular” and “autooptical” images for vestibular and visual stimuli, respectively. Because of the brevity of microdreams, a dream-enacting behavior that elicits an autosensory image may also provoke an awakening even as the new image takes hold in awareness.
An example of an autosomatic image is presented in detail (Table 2, Fig. 6) to highlight its clear causal implications in imagery formation.
Table 2.
Stage | Event | Comments |
---|---|---|
Context | Lying down on L side; L thumb, index and middle fingers were next to forehead while falling asleep. | Fingers were not put in this position intentionally; I was not aware of them there until the image occurred. |
Ongoing cognitive activity | I had been imagining using my L hand to execute a difficult (for me) guitar chord (Em add G#), unsure of its order in a song. | This chord requires a pinching action by the L thumb, index and middle fingers similar to the squeezing needed to remove a bottle cap. A difficult chord for me. |
1. Original image | I was using my L thumb, index and middle fingers to twist off the dark blue top of a blue plastic water bottle. I saw the cap between my fingers. | I typically perform this movement with my R hand. I cannot recall having done it with my L hand. |
2. Reflex/stimulus | While twisting the cap, I felt my actual L hand fingers twitch briefly and with the same direction of movement. I also felt a touch on my forehead. | The image → movement → touch sequence occurred very quickly. I realized almost immediately that the touch was self-produced. |
3. Autosensory image (somatic) | DZ was reaching her R arm in from my R side. It was gray and had very little form. I saw and felt her hand touch me at the same place my fingers were resting. | The visual details were relatively indistinct but the arm’s presence was very distinct. The image occurred as I woke up. |
4. Wake up | The entire image → movement → touch → image → wake up sequence took less than a second. | The sequence was recalled rapidly in reverse order. |
Imagery description appears in italics.
The example begins with a sub-example of a Silbererian type 1 (material) autosymbolic image for which a pre-sleep reverie about forming a difficult guitar chord with fingers of the left hand is followed by an image in which the same fingers unscrew a plastic bottle cap. The microdream action is further associated with twitch-like movements of the real fingers resting on, and triggering touch sensations in, the forehead. The latter sensations, in turn, evoke the autosensory image of someone abruptly appearing and touching precisely the same location on the forehead. The enactment and subsequent stimulation trigger an awakening immediately after the autosensory image enters awareness. The precise chronological order of events allows a causal connection to be inferred.
In light of this clear phenomenological sequence, the question arises as to how a self-induced cutaneous sensation produces a contextualized visual image of someone who appears to be the source of the sensation. In other words, how does a cutaneous stimulus so immediately produce its own context-appropriate visual precursor? This puzzle may be viewed as a special case of conflict in multisensory temporal ordering and will be addressed more fully once we have considered other instances in which external sensory stimuli causally influence microdreams, i.e. cases of exosensory imagery.
Exosensory imagery
I suggest exosensory imagery as a more inclusive category of Silberer’s third type of autosymbolic imagery (somatic imagery), i.e. imagery influenced causally by external stimuli (sounds, lights, imposed body movements, cutaneous contacts, etc.). At present, examples of exosensory microdreams are anecdotal and based on fortuitous observations made under the sleep-onset conditions detailed in Table 3. External stimulations occurred unpredictably in locations as varied as an airplane in turbulence, a noisy park, and a quiet office. Before discussing the exosensory nature of these images and their implications for image formation, some of their phenomenological, ISTH-like, characteristics are described.
Brevity (autobiographical historicity): The 18 images in Table 3 are all short-duration episodes—microdreams—despite their sometimes lengthy descriptions (Mwords = 28.8 ± 14.4; range 12–75). Most (N = 14) consist of a single part, usually a single dreamed movement of a limb, character, or object, accompanied by some visual details. The other four images (#1, #3, #9, #10) consist of at most two parts: two consecutive actions or movements with visual details. In all but one of these (#3), coherence between the two parts is discernible, but in image #3, the second part (“cat’s head emerges”) seems tangential to the first part (“hand puts file in box”).
Eruptive quality (temporal reference frame; spatiotemporal kinesis): Most of the images possess an eruptive character in two separate but interrelated ways. First, they seem to erupt into awareness, eliciting surprise and a quick return to consciousness. Second, the image content hinges on an abrupt emphatic movement that seems to have been caught in mid-expression. Thus, for image #2, the multi-colored clown is seen spinning with an energy and trajectory consistent with having just tripped violently or jumped off a trampoline. Similarly, in image #5 a young man vaults with such velocity that he seems to have just stumbled while running, and gives the image a “caricature-like” aspect. This eruptive quality is especially true for images affected by phasic stimuli, while for some images affected by tonic stimulation (e.g. #11–#13) an eruptive action is less apparent than its sudden appearance in awareness. For other tonic images (#15–#18) an eruptive action is, in fact, present.
Instability (visuospatial scene): Many of the images depict an instability theme: their primary constituent is a vigorous, even violent, movement in a downward or circular direction. These include an arm slapping down (#1); a clown somersaulting (#2); a door slamming (#4); a man tripping (#5); a girl falling (#7); a woman spilling a drink (#8); a bicycle collapsing and man falling on it (#9), a spinning ball sliding and falling (#10); and a page falling (#15). Image instability appears closely linked to the eruptive quality [Readers may be familiar with the common sleep-onset imagery of abruptly falling that can occur after a day of vigorous sport such as skiing (Wamsley et al., 2010). Such images both depict the self as falling and lead to an eruptive awakening, usually accompanied by an intense bodily jerk.].
Self vs. nonself focus (phenomenal embodiment): Focus of the microdreams is sometimes the movements and sensations of the self (N = 7) and sometimes those of other characters or objects (N = 11). Accordingly, the effects of external stimuli are detected in modifications to either self (somatic) or nonself (visual, auditory) imagery attributes. In rare cases (#17), an apparent overlap between self and nonself attributes occurs, e.g. the actions of another character are felt to be executed by the self.
Table 3.
Image (#parts, #words) | External stimulus | Stimulus modality | Stimulus type | Image focus | Clarifications | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
1. | A woman is holding her nose with her L hand, her R hand/arm sweep down in front of her face. Suddenly, a hand (and arm) comes out of nowhere and slaps down on the bare forearm of another arm with a loud “whop” (2, 43). | A “whop” sound coming from the tennis court near where I was lying in the grass woke me. | Auditory | Phasic | Other | The sound from the tennis shot matched precisely the timbre, timing and apparent direction of the sound in the image. |
2. | A bright, multi-colored clown/jester suddenly somersaults with a snapping, elastic motion. His black suit had patches of red, yellow, green, blue, and other colors (1, 24). | Dozing while sitting on a couch near an IKEA cash register, which abruptly sounds with a loud clatter and wakes me. | Auditory | Phasic | Other | The somersault coincided with the noise. I was surrounded by brightly colored sofas, pillows, and other furniture. |
3. | A hand puts a file into a white box; a black cat's head suddenly emerges from behind the edge of a table (2, 22). | A stapler suddenly sounds in the next office. | Auditory | Phasic | Other | The cat’s head emerges at the same time as the stapler sounds. The sound and the cat image seem strangely overlaid and incongruous. |
4. | A heavy door made of wood suddenly swings open to the R and slams against the corner of a counter top (1, 21). | The conference speaker had made a thudding sound by hitting the microphone. | Auditory | Phasic | Other | The thud sound corresponded exactly with the door slam in the image. A slide on the screen just pre-image depicted a closed, large, brown wooden door. |
5. | I see a young man’s legs and feet as he trips over something and falls to the right in my visual field. Almost a caricature of a fall (1,28). | A loud tearing sound, like Velcro ripping, from the seat behind me, woke me up. Airplane had been going through occasional turbulence. | Auditory/somatic | Phasic | Other | The fall coincided exactly with the ripping sound. Falling imagery is similar to other images observed during turbulence. |
6. | My upper body was in a seated, doubled over position, twisted toward the L and downward. I was in the act of pulling myself into an upright posture (1, 28). | Airplane dipped and rose quickly giving a feeling of “stomach rising” (like going over a hill in a car quickly). | Vestibular/somatic | Phasic | Self | The pulling up sensation coincided with the sudden dip/rise of the airplane. |
7. | A 5- to 6-year-old girl in an aisle—an airplane aisle perhaps—falls forward onto her hands and knees. She has dish-pan brown, shoulder length hair, and a hair band. The aisle is reddish (1, 33). | The airplane made an unexpected “dip” during final descent that woke me up. | Vestibular/somatic | Phasic | Other | The girl’s fall occurred at the instant the plane dipped. |
8. | A woman (face indistinct) seated across from me suddenly spills red liquid from a glass onto her lap. I saw dark stains on her beige dress (1, 26). | The airplane made an unexpected “dip” during final descent that woke me up. | Vestibular/somatic | Phasic | Other | The spill coincided with the sudden dip. The woman seated to my R had a glass of wine served to her earlier in the flight. |
9. | I felt some people pass very close by on my L, from back to front, as if on a sidewalk. Then a clear image of a bicycle collapsing in a pile on the ground, the driver falling to the L, face first on top of the bike (2, 47). | The airplane slowed abruptly, albeit very slightly, to begin final descent. | Vestibular/somatic | Phasic | Other | The bicycle collapse coincided with the sudden slowing of the airplane. Flight attendants passed close by on the L of my aisle seat (back to front) several times. |
10. | I flip a volleyball onto my R finger and spin it clockwise for a bit. It flattens, bulges at the center, then deviates forward, then downward. I progressively lose control of it. It is twice as wide now and very flat as I grab for it with both hands. I feel it on my R fingers, which seems incongruous because it cannot be spinning on that part of my hand—as if on the backside (2, 75). | Hands holding open a glossy reprint article songbook style on stomach (lodged against R thumb mainly). In waking I felt it slowly slipping forward along the crook of the thumb and coming to rest on the fingers underneath it. | Cutaneous | Phasic/tonic | Self | The gradual slipping forward of the reprint coincided with the gradual slipping forward of the spinning ball; the ball and reprint were both felt to slide at the same locations on the hand. |
11. | I am climbing a stairwell that has freshly fallen snow scattered over the stairs. My L hand is holding a thick metal railing (1, 23). | Sitting in office, left hand holding right in lap, window to my L is open and cold air is blowing in. | Thermal | Tonic | Self | There were no abrupt movements and nor phasic stimulus. |
12. | In the same stairwell, about half way up a flight of stairs. I have a cold feeling. I feel snow blowing up and enveloping me. The scene is largely dark (1, 30). | Sitting in office, left hand holding right in lap, window to my L is open and cold air is blowing in. | Thermal | Tonic | Self | There were no abrupt movements and nor phasic stimulus. |
13. | A man and boy are riding in a small motorcycle with a sidecar with bright red shiny fenders (1, 18). | Bright sunlight is coming in the windows of the office. | Visual | Tonic | Other | Sunlight may have shone red through my eyelids. |
14. | Seated in my chair I bend forward and place a medium-sized book on my desk, pressing against the book’s bottom edge with my fingertips (1, 24). | Holding a heavy book open in my lap with R fingers bookmarking several pages; pressure on middle and ring fingertips. | Cutaneous | Tonic | Self | Correspondence is in the localized sensations in fingertips. |
15. | A gray cardboard page resting on my L thumb and index finger suddenly falls forward (1, 15). | My right thumb is pressing down on my left thumb and index. | Cutaneous | Tonic | Self | Correspondence is in the localized sensations in fingers. |
16. | I suddenly and vigorously slap a door with my open R palm (1, 12). | Seated in chair, my left elbow is pressing on my R palm. | Cutaneous | Tonic | Self | Only correspondence is a general increase in sensation in the R palm. |
17. | Someone is spinning an animal quickly around in circles with his R hand. It just seems stuck to his hand and turning around it. I feel as though I were making the movements myself (1, 34). | Sitting upright with both hands between my thighs palms facing out. A bit of paresthesia in both, more in R. | Cutaneous | Tonic | Other | Only correspondence is a general increase in sensation in the R hand. |
18. | An obese person or creature on my L suddenly flails his R arm forward toward me and growls (1, 18). | Sitting with book in lap, arms on armrests. R arm is pained and slightly paralyzed. | Pain/cutaneous | Tonic | Other | Only correspondence is between the flailing arm and the arm in pain and paralyzed. |
Influence of external stimuli
Several important relationships between image elements and their immediately preceding external stimuli are illustrated in this collection.
Multiple sensory modalities : Images are affected by stimuli from many sensory modalities, including vestibular, auditory, visual, and various somatic stimuli (cutaneous, thermal, pain). Visual stimuli are the least prevalent. There is a fairly specific correspondence between stimulus modality and its influence on the image; in general, auditory stimuli affect sounds, vestibular stimuli affect balance, cutaneous stimuli affect touch, thermal stimuli affect perceived temperature, and so forth. Some exceptions to this general rule (e.g. #3, #18) point to nonspecific influences. For example, in image #18 pain and cutaneous sensations in a limb were associated with a visual image of an arm abruptly flailing. Additionally, cross-modality influences, especially an auditory stimulus effecting a visual change, are common.
Phasic vs. tonic stimuli : Abrupt, short-lasting (phasic) stimuli and ongoing, longer-lasting (tonic) stimuli appear to affect images in different ways. For images #1–#9, phasic influences such as sudden sounds or airplane movements, result in equally abrupt changes in image content, most notably, in people or objects falling, appearing quickly, or being hit brusquely. Some changes suggest a direct integration of the stimulus into the image’s core, e.g. in image #1, the dreamed sound of an arm being slapped directly reflects the real sound of a tennis ball being hit; in image #4, the dreamed sound of a door slamming reflects the real sound of a microphone being struck; and in image #6, a dreamed sense of pulling the bent-over self into an upright posture reflects the real feeling of rising as an airplane is buffeted abruptly by turbulence.
However, in several other images a phasic stimulus appears to have only indirectly modified an image. In image #2, an abrupt vestibular stimulus is not incorporated directly as a self-feeling of falling or moving, but as a clown character abruptly somersaulting. Similarly, in images #7 and #9 vestibular stimuli lead not to self-feelings of falling, but to other characters falling; in images #8 and #9, such stimuli lead to objects falling. Such indirect, “projected” incorporations have also been observed in REM sleep dream imagery after somatosensory stimulation (Dement and Wolpert, 1958; Koulack, 1969; Nielsen, 1993).
Tonic stimuli also sometimes lead to abrupt changes. Images #15, #16, and #18 demonstrate the eruptive quality familiar from phasic stimuli even though in all three cases there was no sudden stimulus. Thus, although there is a general correspondence between both the modality and the phasic or tonic nature of source stimulations, exceptions behoove us to seek explanations beyond a simple mechanism of “direct incorporation” or even “projected incorporation” (see later).
The orderliness of imagery disruption : When disruptions of image formation are induced, the end-content maintains a certain degree of orderliness. The integrity of objects and characters is preserved to varying degrees and the image contents almost inevitably adhere to the physical laws of classical mechanics. For example, images for which stimulation triggered a “falling” theme (#5, #7, #8, #9, #10, #15) all depict objects or characters that fall in a relatively orderly manner, i.e. downwards in accordance with the influence of gravity, not up or sideways as might be expected if no sense of gravity was in play. Further, although some objects in these images do appear to lose their stability within the scene, they do not completely lose their structural integrity. For example, for the spinning ball in image #10 there is a progressive loss of balance control and round shape, yet the ball changes in a plausible manner (“flattening”) rather than bursting or falling apart entirely. Even so, there are again exceptions; in image #9, a bicycle collapses into a pile, losing most of its structure. Overall, however, the maintenance of an image’s stability, even in the face of disruption, points to degrees of resilience of a basic reality simulation process and, more precisely, to relative preservation of the multisensory integration (MSI) of multimodal and self/nonself elements. Even as an image is disrupted there is improvisation of a solution that obeys rules of classical mechanics for the real world. Further, the integration of real perceptual events into imagined ones in this manner suggests that sensory systems may normally be implicated in imagery formation in various ways, a notion that has been proposed both for waking imagery (Finke, 1980; Kosslyn et al., 1995; McNorgan, 2012) and dreaming (Windt, 2015).
Interpretation of causal factors: MSI
The preceding observations illustrate that sometimes an external stimulus is not only incorporated directly into an image, but it elicits details in other modalities that contextualize this incorporation. This takes place very quickly, possibly within a few hundred milliseconds to, at most, a second or two, and before a full return to consciousness. This rapid elicitation of both direct incorporation and apparent context poses a logical conundrum for an on-line theory of microdream formation, but a conundrum whose resolution might help resolve how more complex dream imagery is so seamlessly improvised. The conundrum hinges on the observation that an external stimulus so quickly elicits a set of image features, some of which seem to temporally precede the stimulus. It is particularly clear in two images from Table 3 that are affected by phasic sounds. For image #1, the sound of a tennis racquet striking a ball is not only incorporated directly as a hand slap sound, but visual details preceding the slap are also represented, i.e. the hand falling prior to it slapping. For image #4, the sound of a microphone being bumped is incorporated directly into the image as the sound of a door slamming, yet it also elicits the visual image of a swinging door that seems to precede the sound. The stimuli in both cases presumably elicit—through some associative mechanism—visual details that are appropriate to, and thus help contextualize, the sound stimuli, but that also seem to occur just before the sounds themselves.
One explanation for this type of experiential component reordering is that the external stimulus, an abrupt sound in both examples, is incorporated as a dreamed sound only after a contextualizing visual image has been triggered associatively. There is a precedent for hypothesizing such a selective delay; conscious awareness of a sensory event may not occur until up to 500 ms after an initial response in sensory cortex; delays are shorter for supra-liminal sensations but longer for near-threshold events (Libet et al., 1991). Further, individuals are not aware of these delays (Libet et al., 1979). According to Libet (2006): “It is as if this delayed awareness is subjectively referred backwards in time to the time of the primary evoked response of the sensory cortex” (p. 324). According to this view, then, the stimulus sounds in examples #1 and #4 may immediately evoke associated visual images, but the sounds and visual images are differentially delayed within the 500-ms window. The sounds may be delayed longer than the visual images or the visual images may be referred backwards in time to a greater extent than are the sounds. In either case, the visual images seem subjectively to occur before the sounds that triggered them.
While the merits of Libet’s findings—and especially the limitations of his phenomenological measures—continue to be debated (Lau et al., 2006; Wolpe and Rowe, 2014), their application here is clearly speculative. However, a second, related, approach to dealing with this conundrum and several other features of exosensory images is to consider these images as a special case of MSI (see reviews in De Gelder and Bertelson, 2003; Talsma, 2015). Specifically, exosensory microdreams could be assessed as instances of MSI in which the sensory modalities of an external stimulus and the features of an endogenous image are in conflict (e.g. auditory stimulus vs. visual image). A similar perspective has been supported for interactions between MSI and intentionally generated, waking state, auditory and visual images (Berger and Ehrsson, 2013; Berger and Ehrsson, 2014; Vetter et al., 2014). Microdreams could potentially be studied experimentally with similar methods, e.g. by presenting external stimuli while subjects are falling asleep. These findings for imagery justify us considering how a number of findings from MSI studies may parallel observations of microdreams from the present inquiry. These include findings about: (i) the timing of percepts (For the present discussion, the term “percept” is used to refer to both real sensory information and the representation of such information in either waking or dreaming imagery.) in different sensory modalities, (ii) the perceived localization of these percepts, (iii) the perceived intensity of percepts, and (iv) the qualitative alteration of visual percepts by auditory and somatic stimuli.
Percept timing
During wakefulness, information in different modalities reaches sense receptors at different speeds (e.g. light travels faster than sound) and is processed in sensory systems at different rates. Thus, MSI mechanisms compensate for discrepancies in the timing, localization, and other multisensory features of objects. These mechanisms are thought to overcome intersensory conflicts to preserve the perception of unified objects and, ultimately, a unified stream of consciousness.
In the case of percept timing, evidence indicates that the perceived onset of visual events can be temporally shifted by stimuli in other modalities—but especially by auditory stimuli. Thus, when brief visual and auditory stimuli are presented consecutively, regardless of order, the perceived onset of the visual stimulus shifts toward that of the sound (Fendrich and Corballis, 2001; Bertelson and Aschersleben, 2003; De Gelder and Bertelson, 2003; Morein-Zamir et al., 2003; Jaekl and Harris, 2007). Cutaneous stimulation can also force a time shift of visual events.
If the visual content of microdream imagery behaves like that of visual perception, then visual imagery, too, may be shifted temporally to appear closer in time to an external auditory stimulus. This one mechanism alone may account for how a visual image comes to be perceived prior to the auditory stimulus that triggered it.
Percept localization
Unlike percept timing, percept localization is more strongly influenced by visual stimuli and may help explain how external stimuli are seamlessly relocalized into microdreams. A sound’s apparent location is likely to shift toward that of a visual event if the two occur close enough in time. The visual event is said to “capture” the sound’s location as in the “ventriloquist effect” (Howard and Templeton, 1966) in which a visual stimulus (the dummy’s mouth) captures the verbal stimulus (the ventriloquist’s voice) forcing a multisensory illusion of integration. Such an effect might underlie the production of exosensory imagery once a visual component has been elicited (e.g. images #2, #4); the eliciting sound may be captured by the visual image and seem to arise from it rather than from the real world. This is analogous to experiments in which the classic ventriloquist effect occurs when subjects only imagine the visual component of the illusion; an auditory stimulus is drawn toward the visual image’s location just as it is for a real visual stimulus (Berger and Ehrsson, 2013). These authors conclude that “mental imagery is capable of integrating with perceptual stimuli of a different sensory modality” (p. 1369). A similar integrative mechanism could explain why incorporation of a sound stimulus into visual microdream imagery usually does not preserve the original location of the stimulus. However, it is noteworthy that such a mechanism may also fail entirely as suggested by image #1 (Table 3) in which the incorporated sound was perceived to originate exactly from its location in the real world.
Percept intensity
Sound stimuli may modify the apparent intensity of visual percepts (Stein et al., 1996). For example, if an LED light is presented together with a brief, broad-band auditory stimulus, the light will be rated as more intense than if it is presented alone—especially when the light is at a low visual intensity. Such auditory stimuli appear to facilitate early stage sensory processing of visual stimuli as suggested by when they e.g. reduce reaction times in visual identification (Doyle and Snowden, 2001) or improve detection of changes in visual motion (Staufenbiel et al., 2011). A similar facilitative mechanism may be implicated in the rapid production of visual imagery at sleep onset when a phasic noise elicits an abrupt facilitation of visual imagery, leading possibly to the “eruptive” quality of elicited images.
Qualitative changes in visual events
Auditory stimuli can alter visual percepts in several qualitative respects that have implications for image formation processes, including (i) apparent motion and (ii) image segmentation. First, in the “bounce illusion,” two small target discs moving in a straight line toward each other, coinciding, then continuing on can be made to seem to “bounce off” each other if a phasic sound burst is presented near the point of coincidence. Even a subliminal sound can induce this effect (Dufour et al., 2008) and the window of coincidence is widened by positive emotion (Kitamura et al., 2015). The pertinence for microdream imagery is demonstrated by the fact that the bounce illusion is induced even when subjects only imagine the phasic sound (Berger and Ehrsson, 2013).
Second, brief sound stimuli can fragment a unitary visual percept into two or more parts. With the sound-induced flash illusion, one phasic light flash accompanied by two rapid beeps will be perceived as two flashes of light; multiple beeps will elicit multiple light flashes (Shams et al., 2002). Multiple tactile stimuli can also elicit this illusion (Violentyev et al., 2005).
These two sets of findings suggest further ways in which exosensory sleep-onset images might be affected by external phasic stimuli. On the one hand, external sounds or tactile sensations may induce “bounce”-like changes in visual imagery such that the latter are induced to change velocity, trajectory, or some other ongoing kinetic feature. On the other hand, phasic sounds might affect the structural integrity of images such that stimulation leads to a fragmentation of imagery in a manner contingent upon stimulus timbre or temporal structure.
MSI approach: synthesis
These four types of MSI findings applied to exosensory microdream imagery suggest several novel possibilities for explaining basic mechanisms of imagery formation. Findings illustrating MSI changes in percept timing, localization, intensity, and qualitative features such as movement and structural integrity all find ready parallels in the exosensory phenomena identified in microdreams. While there is evidence that MSI principles can be applied to waking imagery formation processes, the present analysis demonstrates at least the proof of concept that their application to microdream imagery is feasible and a potentially fertile avenue for future research and theory building.
References
- Andrillon T, Nir Y, Cirelli C. et al. Single-neuron activity and eye movements during human REM sleep and awake vision. Nat Commun 2015;6:1–10. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Arkin AM, Antrobus JS.. The effects of external stimuli applied prior to and during sleep on sleep experience In: Ellman SJ, Antrobus JS (eds), The Mind in Sleep, 2 edn.New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc, 1991, 265–307. [Google Scholar]
- Aserinsky E, Kleitman N.. Regularly occurring periods of eye motility, and concomitant phenomena during sleep. Science 1953;118:273–74. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Aspy DJ. Is dream recall underestimated by retrospective measures and enhanced by keeping a logbook? An empirical investigation. Conscious Cogn 2016;42:181–203. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Berger CC, Ehrsson HH.. Mental imagery changes multisensory perception. Curr Biol 2013;23:1367–72. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Berger CC, Ehrsson HH.. The fusion of mental imagery and sensation in the temporal association cortex. J Neurosci 2014;34:13684–92. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bertelson P, Aschersleben G.. Temporal ventriloquism: crossmodal interaction on the time dimension. 1. Evidence from auditory-visual temporal order judgment. Int J Psychophysiol 2003;50:147–55. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bertolo H, Paiva T, Pessoa L. et al. Visual dream content, graphical representation and EEG alpha activity in congenitally blind subjects. Brain Res Cogn Brain Res 2003;15:277–84. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Bishop C, Rosenthal L, Helmus T. et al. The frequency of multiple sleep onset REM periods among subjects with no excessive daytime sleepiness. Sleep 1996;19:727–30. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Brady TF, Konkle T, Alvarez GA. et al. Real-world objects are not represented as bound units: independent forgetting of different object details from visual memory. J Exp Psychol Gen 2013;142:791–808. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Chellappa SL, Cajochen C.. Ultradian and circadian modulation of dream recall: EEG correlates and age effects. Int J Psychophysiol 2013;89:165–70. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Chellappa SL, Frey S, Knoblauch V. et al. Cortical activation patterns herald successful dream recall after NREM and REM sleep. Biol Psychol 2011;87:251–56. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Cicogna P, Cavallero C, Bosinelli M.. Cognitive aspects of mental activity during sleep. Am J Psychol 1991;104:413–25. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- De Gelder B, Bertelson P.. Multisensory integration, perception and ecological validity. Trends Cogn Sci 2003;7:460–67. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dement W, Kleitman N.. Cyclic variations in EEG during sleep and their relation to eye movements, body motility, and dreaming. Electroencephalogr Clin Neurophysiol 1957;9:673–90. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dement W, Wolpert E.. The relationship of eye movements, body motility, and external stimuli to dream content. J Exp Psychol 1958;55:543–53. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Doyle MC, Snowden RJ.. Identification of visual stimuli is improved by accompanying auditory stimuli: the role of eye movements and sound location. Perception 2001;30:795–810. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dufour A, Touzalin P, Moessinger M. et al. Visual motion disambiguation by a subliminal sound. Conscious Cogn 2008;17:790–97. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Esposito MJ, Nielsen TA, Paquette T.. Reduced alpha power associated with the recall of mentation from Stage 2 and Stage REM sleep. Psychophysiology 2004;41:288–97. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Fendrich R, Corballis PM.. The temporal cross-capture of audition and vision. Percept Psychophys 2001;63:719–25. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Finke RA. Levels of equivalence in imagery and perception. Psychol Rev 1980;87:113–32. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Foulkes D, A Grammar of Dreams. New York: Basic Books, Inc, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Foulkes D, Dreaming: A Cognitive-Psychological Analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1985. [Google Scholar]
- Foulkes D, Fleisher S.. Mental activity in relaxed wakefulness. J Abnorm Psychol 1975;84:66–75. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Foulkes D, Scott E.. An above-zero baseline for the incidence of momentary hallucinatory mentation. Sleep Res 1973;2:108. [Google Scholar]
- Foulkes D, Vogel G.. Mental activity at sleep onset. J Abnorm Psychol 1965;70:231–43. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Freud S, The Interpretation of Dreams. New York: Basic Books, 1900. [Google Scholar]
- Gardner R Jr, Grossman WI, Roffwarg HP. et al. The relationship of small limb movements during REM sleep to dreamed limb action. Psychosom Med 1975;37:147–59. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Garrison KA, Scheinost D, Worhunsky PD. et al. Real-time fMRI links subjective experience with brain activity during focused attention. Neuroimage 2013;81:110–18. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Germain A, Nielsen TA.. EEG power associated with early sleep onset images differing in sensory content. Sleep Res Online 2001;4:83–90. [Google Scholar]
- Hamame CM, Vidal JR, Ossandon T. et al. Reading the mind's eye: online detection of visuo-spatial working memory and visual imagery in the inferior temporal lobe. Neuroimage 2012;59:872–79. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hayashi M, Katoh K, Hori T.. Hypnagogic imagery and EEG activity. Percept Mot Skills 1999;88:676–78. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Herman JH, Erman M, Boys R. et al. Evidence for a directional correspondence between eye movements and dream imagery in REM sleep. Sleep 1984;7:52–63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hohwy J, Bayne T.. The neural correlates of consciousness In: Miller SM. (ed.), The Constitution of Phenomenal Consciousness. Toward a Science and Theory. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2015, 155–76. [Google Scholar]
- Hori T, Hayashi M, Morikawa T.. Topographical EEG changes and the hypnagogic experience In: Ogilvie R, Harsh JR, eds. Sleep onset: Normal and abnormal processes. Washington, D.C: American Psychological Association, 1994:237–53. [Google Scholar]
- Horikawa T, Tamaki M, Miyawaki Y. et al. Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep. Science 2013;340:639–42. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Howard IP, Templeton WB.. Human Spatial Orientation. London: John Wiley & Sons, 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Hunt H, Ruzycki-Hunt K, Pariak D. et al. The relationship between dream bizarreness and imagination: Artifact or essence? Dreaming 1993;3:179–99. [Google Scholar]
- Jaekl PM, Harris LR.. Auditory-visual temporal integration measured by shifts in perceived temporal location. Neurosci Lett 2007;417:219–24. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kerr NH, Domhoff GW.. Do the blind literally “see” in their dreams? A critique of a recent claim that they do. Dreaming 2004;14:230–33. [Google Scholar]
- Kerr NH, Foulkes D, Schmidt M.. The structure of laboratory dream reports in blind and sighted subjects. J Nerv Ment Dis 1982;170:286–94. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kitamura MS, Watanabe K, Kitagawa N.. Positive emotion facilitates audiovisual binding. Front Integr Neurosci 2015;9:1–9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kosslyn SM, Behrmann M, Jeannerod M.. The cognitive neuroscience of mental imagery. Neuropsychologia 1995;33:1335–44. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Koulack D. Effects of somatosensory stimulation on dream content. Arch Gen Psychiatry 1969;20:718–25. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lau HC, Rogers RD, Passingham RE.. On measuring the perceived onsets of spontaneous actions. J Neurosci 2006;26:7265–71. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lehmann D, Dumermuth G, Lange B. et al. Dream recall related to EEG spectral power during REM periods. Sleep Res 1981;10:151. [Google Scholar]
- Lehmann D, Faber PL, Achermann P. et al. Brain sources of EEG gamma frequency during volitionally meditation-induced, altered states of consciousness, and experience of the self. Psychiatry Res 2001;108:111–21. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lewis LD, Weiner VS, Mukamel EA. et al. Rapid fragmentation of neuronal networks at the onset of propofol-induced unconsciousness. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2012;109:E3377–86. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Libet B. Reflections on the interaction of the mind and brain. Prog Neurobiol 2006;78:322–26. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Libet B, Pearl DK, Morledge DE. et al. Control of the transition from sensory detection to sensory awareness in man by the duration of a thalamic stimulus. Brain 1991;114:1731–57. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Libet B, Wright EW Jr, Feinstein B. et al. Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory experience - a functional role for the somatosensory specific projection system in man. Brain 1979;102:193–224. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Llinas R, Ribary U.. Coherent 40-Hz oscillation characterizes dream state in humans. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 1993;90:2078–81. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lutz A, Lachaux JP, Martinerie J. et al. Guiding the study of brain dynamics by using first-person data: synchrony patterns correlate with ongoing conscious states during a simple visual task. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2002;99:1586–91. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Marzano C, Ferrara M, Mauro F. et al. Recalling and forgetting dreams: theta and alpha oscillations during sleep predict subsequent dream recall. J Neurosci 2011;31:6674–83. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mashour GA. Sleep, anesthesia, and consciousness. Sleep 2011;34:247–48. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mavromatis A, Richardson JTE.. Hypnagogic imagery In: Sheikh AA. (ed.), International Review of Mental Imagery, Vol. 1 New York: Human Sciences Press, 1984, 159–89. [Google Scholar]
- McNorgan C. A meta-analytic review of multisensory imagery identifies the neural correlates of modality-specific and modality-general imagery. Front Hum Neurosci 2012;6:1–14. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Milz P, Faber PL, Lehmann D. et al. The functional significance of EEG microstates-Associations with modalities of thinking. Neuroimage 2016;125:643–56. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Morein-Zamir S, Soto-Faraco S, Kingstone A.. Auditory capture of vision: examining temporal ventriloquism. Brain Res Cogn Brain Res 2003;17:154–63. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mouthon AL, Huber R.. Methods in pediatric sleep research and sleep medicine. Neuropediatrics 2015;46:159–70. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen T. Ultradian, circadian, and sleep-dependent features of dreaming In: Kryger M, Roth T, Dement WC (eds), Principles and Practice of Sleep Medicine, 5th edn.New York: Elsevier, 2011, 576–84. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA. A self-observational study of spontaneous hypnagogic imagery using the upright napping procedure. Imagin Cogn Pers 1992;11:353–66. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA. Changes in the kinesthetic content of dreams following somatosensory stimulation of leg muscles during REM sleep. Dreaming 1993;3:99–113. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA. Describing and modeling hypnagogic imagery using a systematic self-observation procedure. Dreaming 1995;5:75–94. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA. A review of mentation in REM and NREM sleep: ‘covert’ REM sleep as a possible reconciliation of two opposing models. Behav Brain Sci 2000;23:851–66. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA, Chénier V.. Variations in EEG coherence as an index of the affective content of dreams from REM sleep: relationships with face imagery. Brain Cogn 1999;41:200–12. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA, Kuiken D, Alain G. et al. Immediate and delayed incorporations of events into dreams: further replication and implications for dream function. J Sleep Res 2004;13:327–36. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA, Powell RA.. The day-residue and dream-lag effects: A literature review and limited replication of two temporal effects in dream formation. Dreaming 1992;2:67–77. [Google Scholar]
- Nielsen TA, Stenstrom P.. What are the memory sources of dreaming? Nature 2005;437:34–38. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nieminen JO, Gosseries O, Massimini M. et al. Consciousness and cortical responsiveness: a within-state study during non-rapid eye movement sleep. Sci Rep 2016;6:1–10. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Nir Y, Tononi G.. Dreaming and the brain: from phenomenology to neurophysiology. Trends Cogn Sci 2010;14:88–100. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Noreika V, Canales-Johnson A, Koh J. et al. Intrusions of a drowsy mind: neural markers of phenomenological unpredictability. Front Psychol 2015;6:1–10. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Noreika V, Valli K, Lahtela H. et al. Early-night serial awakenings as a new paradigm for studies on NREM dreaming. Int J Psychophysiol 2009;74:14–18. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Ogilvie RD. The process of falling asleep. Sleep Med Rev 2001;5:247–70. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Oswald I. Sleeping and waking Physiology and Psychology. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1962. [Google Scholar]
- Petitmengin C, Lachaux JP.. Microcognitive science: bridging experiential and neuronal microdynamics. Front Hum Neurosci 2013;7:1–6. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Poudel GR, Innes CR, Bones PJ. et al. Losing the struggle to stay awake: divergent thalamic and cortical activity during microsleeps. Hum Brain Mapp 2014;35:257–69. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Purdon PL, Pierce ET, Mukamel EA. et al. Electroencephalogram signatures of loss and recovery of consciousness from propofol. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 2013;110:E1142–51. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Scarpelli S, D'atri A, Gorgoni M. et al. EEG oscillations during sleep and dream recall: state- or trait-like individual differences? Front Psychol 2015;6:1–10. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Schacter DL. The hypnagogic state: a critical review of the literature. Psychol Bull 1976;83:452–81. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Shams L, Kamitani Y, Shimojo S.. Visual illusion induced by sound. Brain Res Cogn Brain Res 2002;14:147–52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Siclari F, Larocque JJ, Postle BR. et al. Assessing sleep consciousness within subjects using a serial awakening paradigm. Front Psychol 2013;4:1–9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Silberer H. Report on a method of eliciting and observing certain symbolic hallucination-phenomena In: Rapaport D. (ed.), Organization and Pathology of Thought. New York: Columbia University Press, 1951, 195–207. [Google Scholar]
- Singh M, Drake CL, Roth T.. The prevalence of multiple sleep-onset REM periods in a population-based sample. Sleep 2006;29:890–95. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Solms M. The Neuropsychology of Dreams. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Staufenbiel SM, van der Lubbe RH, Talsma D.. Spatially uninformative sounds increase sensitivity for visual motion change. Exp Brain Res 2011;213:457–64. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stein BE, London N, Wilkinson LK. et al. Enhancement of perceived visual intensity by auditory stimuli: a psychophysical analysis. J Cogn Neurosci 1996;8:497–506. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Stenstrom P, Fox K, Solomonova E. et al. Mentation during sleep onset theta bursts in a trained participant: a role for NREM stage 1 sleep in memory processing? Int J Dream Res 2012;5:37–46. [Google Scholar]
- Stickgold R. EMDR: a putative neurobiological mechanism of action. J Clin Psychol 2002;58:61–75. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Talsma D. Predictive coding and multisensory integration: an attentional account of the multisensory mind. Front Integr Neurosci 2015;9:19. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tanaka H, Hayashi M, Hori T, Coherence analysis of topographical characteristics of the hypnagogic EEG In: Koga Y, Nagata K, Kirata K (eds), Brain Topography Today. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 1998a, 309–12. [Google Scholar]
- Tanaka H, Hayashi M, Hori T.. Topographic mapping of electroencephalography coherence in hypnagogic state. Psychiatry Clin Neurosci 1998b;52:147–8. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Thompson E, Varela FJ.. Radical embodiment: neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends Cogn Sci 2001;5:418–25. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tinguely G, Huber R, Borbely AA. et al. Non-rapid eye movement sleep with low muscle tone as a marker of rapid eye movement sleep regulation. BMC Neurosci 2006;7:1–9. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tirunahari VL, Zaidi SA, Sharma R. et al. Microsleep and sleepiness: a comparison of multiple sleep latency test and scoring of microsleep as a diagnostic test for excessive daytime sleepiness. Sleep Med 2003;4:63–67. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- van Rijn E, Eichenlaub JB, Lewis PA. et al. The dream-lag effect: selective processing of personally significant events during Rapid Eye Movement sleep, but not during Slow Wave Sleep. Neurobiol Learn Mem 2015;122:98–109. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Verdone P. Temporal reference of manifest dream content. Percept Mot Skills 1965;20:1253–68. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Vetter P, Smith FW, Muckli L.. Decoding sound and imagery content in early visual cortex. Curr Biol 2014;24:1256–62. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Violentyev A, Shimojo S, Shams L.. Touch-induced visual illusion. Neuroreport 2005;16:1107–10. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Vogel GW. Sleep-onset mentation In: Ellman SJ, Antrobus JS (eds), The Mind in Sleep: Psychology and Psychophysiology, 2nd edn New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons, 1991, 125–42. [Google Scholar]
- Wamsley EJ, Perry K, Djonlagic I. et al. Cognitive replay of visuomotor learning at sleep onset: temporal dynamics and relationship to task performance. Sleep 2010;33:59–68. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Werth E, Achermann P, Borbely AA.. Selective REM sleep deprivation during daytime. II. Muscle atonia in non-REM sleep. Am J Physiol Regul Integr Comp Physiol 2002;283: R527–32. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Windt JM. The immersive spatiotemporal hallucination model of dreaming. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 2010;9:295–316. [Google Scholar]
- Windt JM, Dreaming: A Conceptual Framework for Philosophy of Mind and Empirical Research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Wolpe N, Rowe JB.. Beyond the "urge to move": objective measures for the study of agency in the post-Libet era. Front Hum Neurosci 2014;8:1–13. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]