Abstract
It is widely believed that race divides the world into biologically distinct kinds of people – an essentialist belief inconsistent with reality. Essentialist views of race have been described as early emerging, but the present study found that young children (n = 203, Mage = 5.45) hold only the more limited belief that the physical feature of skin color is inherited and stable. Overall, children rejected the causal essentialist view that behavioral and psychological characteristics are constrained by an inherited racial essence. Although average levels of children’s causal essentialist beliefs about race were low, variation in these beliefs was related to children’s own group membership, exposure to diversity, as well as children’s own social attitudes.
Keywords: Racial essentialism, diversity, prejudice
Evidence from multiple scientific disciplines, including genetics (Nei & Roychoudhury, 1982), evolutionary biology (Lewontin, 1972), and anthropology (Hirschfeld, 1996), confirms that race is a socially constructed category. Nevertheless, people often think about race as if it is deterministically rooted in biology (Haslam, Rothschild, & Ernst, 2000; Jayartne et al., 2006). The beliefs that racial categories reflect real distinctions found in nature, and that race is an inherently meaningful part of identity, are widespread (e.g., Markus, 2008). These beliefs reflect psychological essentialism – a set of cognitive biases that lead people to view members of a category as sharing a deep, underlying essence that causes them to be fundamentally similar to one another in both obvious and non-obvious ways (Gelman, 2003; Medin & Ortony, 1989).
People around the world hold essentialist beliefs about a range of social categories (e.g., gender, ethnicity, caste), and in the United States, where there is a historical precedent of categorizing people according to skin color, essentialist beliefs about race are especially common. Among adults, such beliefs have serious consequences for intergroup relations: they are associated with racial stereotyping (Bastian & Haslam, 2006; Keller, 2005), prejudice (Allport, 1954; Haslam, Rothschild, & Ernst, 2002; Mandalaywala, Amodio, & Rhodes, 2017; Yzerbyt, Corneille, & Estrada, 2001), and the decreased desire for cross-race interaction (Williams & Eberhardt, 2008). Given these implications and efforts by scientists and policy makers to reduce them, research on the developmental origins of racial essentialism is crucial to better understand how and when essentialist beliefs about race might have pernicious outcomes. However, relatively little is known about the degree to which children view race in essentialist terms, or about the experiences that might lead them to do so, and whether essentialist beliefs about race have similarly pernicious consequences in children as they do in adults. The present research therefore examines three main questions: (1) to what extent do young children hold essentialist views of race? (2) how do these beliefs develop? and (3) what are the implications of such essentialist beliefs for the early development of racial attitudes?
Measurement of essentialist beliefs in children
Essentialist beliefs in early childhood are often tested with “switched-at-birth” tasks – a task originally developed to test beliefs about animal species in young children (Gelman & Wellman, 1991). In the animal version of this task, for example, a child might be told that an animal born to parents from one category (e.g., pigs) has been raised by members of a different category (e.g., cows) and asked to predict what the baby animal would be like when it grows up. Test items include questions about what it will look like (i.e., will it possess the physical properties of pigs or cows?), what it will act like (i.e., will it possess the behavioral properties of pigs or cows?), and what kind of animal it will be (i.e., will it be a pig or cow?) (e.g., Atran et al., 2001; Sousa, Atran, & Medin, 2002; Waxman, Medin, & Ross, 2007). These tasks provide a strong test of essentialism, assessing the extent to which individuals believe that category members share an inherited and causally powerful essence that determines their physical and behavioral properties. These studies have shown that by age 4–5, children hold causal essentialist views for animal species (e.g., Waxman et al., 2007), as well as for human gender (e.g., Taylor, Rhodes, & Gelman, 2009).
In the first major developmental investigation of essentialist representations of race, Hirschfeld (1995) adapted the switched-at-birth task to examine children’s beliefs about the extent to which race is inherited or determined by the environment. This adapted task differed in one crucial way from the switched-at-birth tasks for animals described above, however, in that it only asked about physical properties (e.g., heritability and stability of skin color). In Hirschfeld’s (1995) task, children were told a story about a baby who is born to parents of one race (shown in an image to be Black), but directly after birth is adopted and subsequently raised by parents of a different race (shown in an image to be White, or vice versa). Children were then asked to think about this baby when it’s grown up, specifically, what it will look like (i.e., will it possess the skin color of the birth or adoptive mother?). By age four, children reliably chose the image with skin color that matched that of the birth parents, which has been broadly interpreted as indicating that young children have causal essentialist views of race. Further, the early emergence of racial essentialist beliefs – as revealed by this task – has been taken to support the broader theoretical claim that intuitive conceptual biases make the human mind particularly likely to essentialize race, and therefore that such beliefs take relatively limited cultural input to develop (Astuti, Solomon, & Carey, 2004; Atran, 1998; Gil-White, 2001; Hirschfeld, 1996). From this perspective, we might predict that essentialist beliefs about race emerge early in childhood and to a similar extent across diverse contexts.
However, because the test items in previous work asked only about skin color, this work indicates only that young children view skin color as heritable and stable – there were no measures of whether children viewed race in causally powerful terms (e.g., that members of a racial category share an inherited and causally powerful essence that also determines what a person will be like) or whether race represents coherent and meaningful categories of people. In this way, the type of belief about race examined previously in young children is much more limited in scope than the essentialist beliefs that children have been found to hold about animal categories (Gelman & Wellman, 1991; Waxman et al., 2007) or human gender categories (Taylor, 1996; Taylor et al., 2009). Moreover, the types of essentialist beliefs about race that have been linked to stereotyping and prejudice in adult populations are characterized as beliefs about the causality, naturalness, and inductive potential of race, not as beliefs only about the heritability of skin color (Jayartne et al., 2006; Mandalaywala et al., 2017; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008). Indeed, the belief that a child will possess the skin color of its birth parent might not reflect an essentialist view of racial categories at all, but rather a more general belief about inheritance (e.g., a belief that babies resemble their biological parents with respect to some physical properties; Springer, 1996). Indeed, Rhodes (2013) found that children reason about skin color on these scenarios in a manner very similar to how they reason about hair color, eye color, or other physical properties – that is, they expect these properties to be inherited and stable, but do not view them as informative regarding other properties of people and do not attribute particular social significance to them.
In contrast to the view that essentialist beliefs about race are widespread, several studies using other measures have revealed a more protracted and variable developmental trajectory of racial essentialism. For example, tasks assessing the belief that race marks an objectively meaningful way of categorizing people reveal that this type of belief emerges later in childhood, between 7 and 10 years of age, and more so in some cultural communities than in others (Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; see also Diesendruck & Haber, 2009; Diesendruck, Goldfein-Elbaz, Rhodes, Gelman, & Neumark, 2013). Further, preschool-age children have been found not to use race to make inductive inferences about what individuals will be like, unless race is highlighted within the experiment itself (e.g., with verbal category labels; Waxman, 2010; for related evidence that children make inferences based on ethnic categories when they are highlighted by labels, see Diesendruck & haLevi, 2006). Even on measures focusing on beliefs about the physical features associated with race, which test if children expect skin color to be stable over time, younger children (ages 5–6) appear less certain that skin color will remain constant when it is pitted against other individual characteristics, such as language (Kinzler & Dautel, 2012) or emotional expression (Roberts & Gelman, 2016). Also, when asked to explain judgments of why skin color would remain stable over time, younger children often do not express essentialist reasoning to support their judgments (Gaither, Schultz, Pauker, Sommers, Maddox, & Ambady, 2013; Pauker, Ambady, & Apfelbaum, 2010; Pauker, Xu, Williams, & Biddle, 2016).
The development of racial essentialism
The protracted developmental trajectory of children’s essentialist beliefs about race, and even the lengthy development of beliefs about racial stability, are consistent with the proposal that it takes rather extensive developmental experiences for children to apply their basic essentialist intuitions to particular ways of grouping people (Deeb, Segall, Birnbaum, Ben-Eliyahu, & Diesendruck, 2011; Diesendruck & Haber, 2009; Rhodes, Leslie, & Tworek, 2012; Rhodes, Leslie, Bianchi, & Chalik, 2017; Rhodes & Mandalaywala, 2017; Segall, Birnbaum, Deeb, & Diesendruck, 2015; Smyth, Feeney, Eidson, & Coley, 2017; Waxman, 2010). Also consistent with this proposal, the developmental trajectory of children’s beliefs about race show marked individual and cultural variability. For example, Black children often develop beliefs that race is a stable feature of identity at an earlier age than White children in the United States (e.g., Kinzler & Dautel, 2012; Roberts & Gelman, 2016), and children growing up in more racially homogenous cities exhibit stronger racial stability beliefs than their counterparts in more diverse cities (e.g., Pauker et al., 2016). The belief that race demarcates a meaningful way of categorizing people emerges in some cultural contexts (e.g., the United States), but not others (e.g., Israel; Diesendruck et al., 2013), and even within the United States, emerges more strongly in communities that are more racially and ethnically homogeneous (Rhodes & Gelman, 2009). This kind of variation has been found for other social categories as well; for example, children who are exposed to more social diversity because they attend purposefully integrated schools develop fewer essentialist beliefs about religious (Smyth et al., 2017) and ethnic (Deeb et al., 2011) groups in communities where those distinctions have particular cultural significance. Further, among individual children, essentialism about specific social categories varies in relation to parental beliefs and attitudes (Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Segall et al., 2015), and parental transmission of essentialist beliefs is thought to occur through subtle linguistic means (e.g., through verbal marking of category members: Gelman, Taylor, & Nguyen, 2004; Rhodes et al., 2012; Segall et al., 2015). Overall, these studies suggest that beliefs about specific social groupings – including race – develop in response to the local environment and after protracted experience.
However, whether beliefs about both the heritability of skin color as well as stronger causal essentialist beliefs about race require similar experiences to develop, and even whether they develop along similar timelines, is currently unknown. Despite the rich literature on the development of different types of beliefs about race, none of the previous studies have directly compared children’s beliefs about the heritability of skin color to the belief that race reflects an intrinsic, causally-powerful essence within the switched-at-birth paradigm (as has been done in studies of essentialist beliefs about biological and gender categories: e.g., Taylor et al., 2009; Waxman et al., 2007; but see Diesendruck & Haber, 2009 and Diesendruck & haLevi, 2006 for studies that have compared multiple aspects of essentialist thinking in other paradigms). Because of this, it is unclear whether both types of beliefs about race depend on similar cultural input to develop, as well as whether they develop along similar developmental trajectories.
The implications of racial essentialism for racial attitudes
Clarifying how experience shapes causal essentialist beliefs about race (beyond beliefs about the heritability of skin color) is particularly important because it is these causal essentialist beliefs – that race marks meaningful categories that are determined by intrinsic, causally powerful essences – that has been proposed to contribute to stereotyping and prejudice (Allport, 1954; Haslam et al., 2002; Yzerbyt et al., 2001). Indeed, the belief that race is an informative, coherent, and natural category relates to racial prejudice among both White (Jayaratne et al., 2006; Martin & Parker, 1995; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008) and Black (Mandalaywala et al., 2017) adults. Whether essentialism contributes to racial attitudes just as prejudice begins to emerge in early childhood (Clark & Clark, 1947; Raabe & Beelman, 2011), and how the implications of essentialism for racial attitudes might vary for children from racial minority or majority groups, have never been examined (but see Pauker et al., 2010, 2016; for evidence relating beliefs about racial stability to racial stereotyping). Thus, in the present research, we test whether beliefs about the heritability of skin color and the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence contribute to the early development of racial attitudes.
The present research
The first goal of this research was to examine the extent to which young children hold essentialist views of race, focusing on the strong case of causal essentialism where people expect that skin color is tied to a causally powerful essence that determines what a person will be like, in comparison with children’s belief that skin color is heritable. Given that children’s own experiences as members of particular groups are important factors in the developmental trajectories of both types of beliefs (e.g., Diesendruck et al., 2013; Kinzler & Dautel, 2012; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Roberts & Gelman, 2016), we recruited a relatively large sample of both White and Black children. To test the extent to which the development of beliefs about the heritability of race and the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence vary as a function of experience, we also gathered data on parental essentialist beliefs (Deeb et al., 2011; Rhodes et al., 2012; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Segall et al., 2015) and on the demographic diversity of children’s neighborhoods (Pauker et al., 2016; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Roberts & Gelman, 2015). As children as young as 4-years-old reliably view skin color as heritable (Hirschfeld, 1995; Rhodes, 2013), whereas the view that race demarcates a meaningful way of grouping people develops later and with substantial cultural variation (Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Diesendruck et al., 2013), we predicted that children’s causal essentialist views of race might vary more than their skin color judgments in relation to neighborhood diversity and parental beliefs.
In order to compare children’s causal essentialist beliefs about race to their beliefs about the heritability and stability of skin color, we made two modifications to the switched-at-birth task used by Hirschfeld (1995). First, in addition to asking children to predict the skin color of the grown-up adopted child (i.e., what it would look like), we also asked them to make predictions about whether the child’s psychological and behavioral characteristics (i.e., what it would be like) would be determined by the birth parent or adoptive parent. Second, we compared responses to scenarios where the birth and adoptive mother were of different races to those where the birth and adoptive mothers were of the same race (for a similar approach used for gender, see Taylor, 1996). This allowed us to examine the extent to which responses to these questions about behavioral and psychological properties were due to the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence (when the races of the birth and adoptive mother were different), and when they were due to more general beliefs about the heritability of these characteristics (when the races of the birth and adoptive mother were the same).
The second goal of this research was to examine the implications of beliefs about both the heritability and causal essence of race for racial attitudes in early childhood, and particularly the extent to which such implications might vary depending on children’s own experiences as members of certain groups. To test these relations in early childhood, as negative racial attitudes begin to emerge (e.g., Clark & Clark, 1947; Raabe & Beelman, 2011; Shutts, 2015), children ages 5–6 years old were included in this study. We compare the responses of children in this age group to those of adults, for whom the effects of essentialism on prejudice have been previously examined (e.g., Jayaratne et al., 2006; Mandalaywala et al., 2017; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008). By focusing on young children, we can clarify precisely which types of beliefs contribute to the formation of racial attitudes. Although overall levels of the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence, and perhaps even beliefs about the heritability of skin color, might be quite low among children in this age range, we can test whether variation in these beliefs already explains variation in the development of children’s racial attitudes. This will allow us to determine whether these types of beliefs have implications for intergroup phenomena as soon as each emerges, or whether they begin to shape racial attitudes and interactions only later as children accumulate more experiences and stereotypes (in which case we might expect them to have implications for attitudes among adults, but not among young children who are just developing these beliefs). Moreover, by examining how racial attitudes relate to participants’ responses both when the race of the birth and adoptive mother were different (a measure of causal racial essentialism), as well as when the race of the mothers were the same (a measure of more general behavioral heritability), we can assess whether these two types of beliefs are differently affected by environmental input, as well as whether they differentially predict racial attitudes.
Method
Participants
Participants were Black (M = 5.49 years, SD = 0.50, 53% male, n = 81) and White (M = 5.41 years, SD = 0.49, 44% male, n = 122) children (age range = 5.00 – 6.99; n = 203), as well as Black (M = 33.6 years, SD = 12.0, 37% male, n = 137) and White (M = 39.6 years, SD = 13.4, 39% male, n = 293) adults (age range = 18 – 71; n = 430). Preliminary analyses revealed no effects of child age (in months) on essentialist beliefs about race across this sample; therefore, children were considered as a single age group for the main analyses. Child race was determined by parental report, and adult race was determined by self-report. Child participants were recruited from and tested at the Children’s Museum of Manhattan (CMOM) – a private, not-for-profit museum located in a large (pop. ~ 8.5 million) city – in a single research session (approximately 20 minutes long) conducted between January 2015 and March 2016. Written parental consent was obtained for all participants and children provided oral assent. Adult participants were recruited via Amazon’s Mechanical Turk (AMT); adult participants were required to live in the United States (based upon IP address) and provided written consent. For a subset of the child participants, data were collected from one parent as well (n = 66, 76% mothers). Data were collected from only a subset of all participants as parents sometimes had other responsibilities (e.g., watching other children) that precluded them from participating in the parent portion of the study. Data from parents were considered separately from those of the adult participant sample (i.e., they were not included in analyses designed to test effects of age). All study procedures were approved by the university’s Institutional Review Board.
Procedures for children
The full study protocol with scripts and images is available at Open Science Framework (OSF; DOI: https://osf.io/92pxv/).
Beliefs about heritability of properties
Participants were told two stories in which a baby was born to one mother (shown in an image) but adopted and raised by another (also shown in an image). In one story, the birth mother and adoptive mother were the same race (e.g., both White or both Black: same race scenario) and in the other they were of different races (e.g., one was White and the other was Black: different race scenario); the order of these stories was counter-balanced across participants, as was the race of the birth mother. Preliminary analyses revealed no effects of counter-balancing order, so this feature of the design was not considered further. Participants were then asked a series of questions about what the adopted child would both look like and what it would be like, as the child grew older. Because the use of category labels can lead children to use categories within experimental tasks when they would not otherwise do so (Dunham, Baron, & Carey, 2011; Roberts & Gelman, 2017; Waxman, 2010), children were not provided with racial labels at any point in the procedure. This approach permitted us to examine children’s spontaneous use of racial categories.
Behavioral properties
First, participants were told about four characteristics of the child (e.g., “This baby is now 6 years old. This baby is now very smart”), one at a time. Other test properties included the child now being very nice, good at music, and good at sports). Although these traits are sometimes associated with racial stereotypes, we did not find that the race of the birth mother systematically affected children’s or adult’s likelihood of viewing traits as heritable. Also, participants generally responded in a similar manner across the four types of properties, with one exception (described in the Supplemental Online Materials). For each property, participants were asked whether the trait was due to the birth mother (scored “1”) or adoptive mother (scored “0”; e.g., “Is that because of this mom (pointing to birth mother) or this mom (pointing to adoptive mother)?).
Skin color
After completing items regarding behavioral characteristics, participants were shown two images of children, one White and one Black, and asked to choose the image depicting how the baby looked like when it grew up. Although children were asked this question in both scenarios (i.e., same race and different race scenarios), only responses in the different race scenario were analyzed for this measure. Choosing the child that matched the birth mother in skin color was scored “1” and choosing the child that matched the adoptive mother was scored “0.”
Racial attitudes
Participants were shown images of six children, one at a time and in randomized order, each between the ages of 3 and 7 years old, displaying neutral expressions (3 White and 3 Black, taken from the CAFÉ dataset: LoBue, 2014; LoBue & Thrasher, 2015). Child stimuli were gender-matched to the participant. For each image, participants were asked, “Do you like this kid, or do you not like this kid?” followed by, “How much do you [like/not like] this kid? Do you sort of [like/not like] them, [like/not like] them, or really [like/not like] them?” (scored such that 1 = really dislike, 6 = really like). Each participant then received an average score for the warmth of their feelings toward all three White children and all three Black children separately. We examined feelings toward White and Black targets separately to determine whether racial essentialism was related to ingroup feelings or outgroup feelings for children from each group.
Additional measures
In addition to the tasks described here, children also completed an Implicit Association Test and a self-categorization test. For details of these procedures and a description of why they are not analyzed for this paper, see the Supplemental Online Materials.
Outgroup exposure
We measured the extent of outgroup exposure for White and Black child participants in each child’s current residential neighborhood. These analyses included a subset of the child participants (n = 97). Parents provided their child’s current residential zip code, from which we determined the number of inhabitants in each child’s total neighborhood population that identified as White or as Black/African-American, based upon publicly available census information (2010 census). In this way, we estimated outgroup exposure for each child (i.e., for a White child, the percentage of their total zip code population that identified as Black/African-American, and for a Black child, the percentage of their total zip code population that identified as White).
Procedures for adults
We collected data from parents of a subset of participating children (n = 66, 76% mothers), and from separate samples recruited and tested online via Amazon’s Mechanical Turk (n = 430, 62% female). Procedures for adults were very similar to procedures for children, but modified in some cases to be more appropriate to adult participants and for online administration. Although there are a variety of scale measures used to assess essentialist beliefs about race in adults (see Haslam et al., 2002; Mandalaywala et al., 2017; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008), we elected to administer the same switched-at-birth task to adults and children as essentialism is a multifaceted construct and different measures are likely to tap into different components of essentialist beliefs. By using the same essentialism measure across both age groups, we maximized our chances of assessing comparable components of essentialism in children and adults, and then examining how these particular components of essentialist beliefs relate to social phenomena, such as racial attitudes. We did not collect data from adults on their beliefs about the heritability of skin color, nor did we ask for their current residential zip code; therefore adult data are not included in those particular analyses. The adult protocol is available at OSF (DOI: https://osf.io/92pxv/).
Results
To examine children’s beliefs about whether properties were determined by the birth or adoptive mother we implemented quasibinomial generalized linear models in R, except where noted below. This approach was appropriate because children gave binary responses (0 adoptive mother; 1 birth mother) and were recruited from a convenience (not random) sample (Wilson & Lorenz, 2015). To compare responses to chance, we examined intercept-only models implemented in this manner. When analyses required examining a within-subjects factor, we instead implemented Generalized Estimating Equations with a binomial distribution. For all of these analyses, we report Odds Ratios (OR) as indicators of effect size. All of our data and analytic code are available at OSF (DOI: https://osf.io/92pxv/).
Beliefs about heritability of properties
Skin color
Overall, children predicted the character would share the skin color of the birth mother 62% of the time. The odds of giving a birth mother response on the skin color question were 1.60 (CI = 1.21, 2.14) times as high as expected by chance, p = 001. We next examined participant race and birth mother race (and their interaction) as possible predictors of children’s beliefs about the heritability of skin color. The model was only a marginal improvement over the null model, Likelihood Ratio Chi Square χ2(3) = 7.35, p = .06. Nevertheless, this model identified birth mother race as a significant predictor, β = 0.83, SE = 0.38, t = 2.15, p = .033; Wald χ2(1) = 7.32, p = .007. The odds of predicting that skin color was determined by birth were 2.29 (CI = 1.08, 4.93) times as high when children were shown White than Black birth mothers. There were no main or interactive effects of participant race in this model, and as shown in Figure 1 the patterns were very similar for Black and White children. To account for the effect of birth mother race, whenever heritability of skin color was included in subsequent models birth mother race was also included as a predictor.
In contrast to the overall findings for skin color, in the different race scenarios, children responded that the character would share behavioral properties with the birth mother only 31% of the time; the odds of children making birth mother responses for questions about behavioral properties was 0.44 (CI = 0.37, 0.53) times as high as expected by chance, p < .001. To directly compare responses to questions about skin color and behavioral properties, we next ran a Generalized Estimating Equations (GEE) binomial model predicting birth mother responses from question-type (skin color vs. behavioral), birth mother race, and the interaction. In this model, the odds of children giving birth mother responses were 2.85 (CI = 1.73, 4.70) times as high when they were asked about skin color than a behavioral property, β = 1.05, SE = 0.26, Wald χ2(1) = 16.96, p < .001. There were no main or interactive effects of birth mother race in this model, indicating that children distinguished between physical and behavioral properties, regardless of whether the birth mother was White or Black. Subsequent analyses confirmed that there was no effect of birth mother race on predictions about behavioral properties, therefore, this factor was not considered further in subsequent models focusing on those properties.
Behavioral properties
We next examined the effects of age and participant race on birth mother responses on questions about behavioral properties (collapsed across same and different race scenarios, to start). This model was a significant improvement over the null model, Wald χ2(3) = 72.60, p < .001. The odds of giving a birth mother response to questions about behavioral properties were 1.45 (CI = 1.13, 1.87) times as high for Black participants as for White participants, β= 0.37, SE = 0.13, t = 2.76, p = .006, Wald χ2(1) = 7.1, p = .03, and 1.82 (CI = 1.49, 2.23) as high for adults as for children, β = 0.60, SE = 0.10, t = 5.87, p < .001, Wald χ2 (1) = 62.20, p < .001. There was no interaction between participant race and age (see Figure 2).
We next ran a GEE model to examine the within-subjects effect of scenario-type (same-race vs. different-race mothers) on participants’ birth mother responses on behavioral questions (along with age, participant race, and also possible interactions). There was again a main effect of age as described above, β = 0.63, SE = 0.15, p < .001, Wald χ2 (1) = 17.49, p < .001 such that adults were more likely to view behavioral properties as heritable than children. There was no longer a significant main effect of race, p = .15. There were no main or interactive effects of scenario-type (all ps > .10), indicating that average levels of birth mother responses were similar regardless of whether the mothers in the stories were the same or different races.
Role of experience on the development of beliefs
Although children responded similarly to situations where the birth and adoptive mothers were of the same or different races (as described above), we considered that different processes could give rise to beliefs about the heritability of behavioral properties in these two scenarios, and also that beliefs about heritability in these two scenarios could have different implications for racial attitudes. Thus, we considered responses to the same race and different race scenarios separately for the remainder of analyses.
Outgroup exposure
We examined the effects of outgroup exposure on children’s birth mother responses to behavioral questions in the scenario where mothers were of different races (also including participant race in the model). Greater outgroup exposure was associated with reduced birth mother responses to behavioral questions, β = −1.05, SE = 0.53, t = −1.97, p = .051. Although on average Black children lived in neighborhoods with a higher proportion of outgroup members than White children did (Black participants: M = .46, CI = .38, .54; White participants: M = .21, CI = .15, .27), t(90)= 5.11, p < .001, D = 1.03), as shown in Figure 3, the relation of outgroup exposure to racial essentialism was very similar across participant race. In contrast to the findings shown in Figure 3, there were no main or interactive effects of outgroup exposure on participants’ responses to behavioral questions in scenarios where the birth and adoptive mothers were the same race (ps > .05), or on their beliefs about the heritability of skin color (ps > .05), suggesting that outgroup exposure only affected the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence (as detected by the different race scenario-type questions), not to more general beliefs about heritability.
Parental beliefs
There were no significant associations between children’s and parents’ beliefs about the heritability of behavioral properties in the different race scenario, p = .54 (n = 64). Further models confirmed that parent responses on these measures did not predict child responses on these measures, either on their own, p = .77, or via interactive effects with participant race, p = .99. There were also no main or interactive effects of parental beliefs on participants’ responses in the same race scenario, ps > .05. Thus, parent’s beliefs did not appear to relate to children’s belief that race is tied to a causal essence, nor to children’s belief about the heritability of behavioral properties more generally. Among adults, parents’ beliefs about the heritability of behavioral properties were significantly lower than the beliefs of adults on AMT across both scenario types (in the different race scenario, Parents: M = .32, CI = .27, .38; AMT: M = .40, CI = .38, .43, Wald χ2(1) = 5.91, p = .015; in the same race scenario, Parents: M = .33, CI = .27, .39; AMT: M = .41, CI = .39, .44, Wald χ2(1) = 6.86, p = .009), which could reflect either differences in sampling or in testing procedures (i.e., completing the study anonymously online, or in person at CMOM).
Racial attitudes
We tested the extent to which participant race, age, and birth parent responses to behavioral questions in the different race scenario were associated with participants’ feelings of warmth toward White and Black targets (z-scored values) in a linear regression model (child n = 83; adult n = 430). There were a number of main effects and interactions, which were all subsumed under a three-way interaction of participant race, birth mother responses to behavioral questions (in the different-race scenarios), and age, β = 0.46, SE = 0.21, t = 2.13, p = .03 (Fig. 4). Among adults, the relation of birth mother response to attitudes did not vary by race, p = .83; as illustrated in Figure 4, more birth parent responses to behavioral questions were associated with less warmth toward Black targets among adults, β = −0.10, SE = 0.05, t = −2.03, p = .04, and the pattern was very similar across Black and White participants. Among children, however, the relation of birth mother responses to prejudice varied by participant race, β = −0.47, SE = 0.20, t = −2.32, p = .03. As shown in Figure 4, this interaction arose because the relation of birth mother responses to feelings of warmth toward Black targets was negative among Black children, β = −0.28, SE = 0.14, t = −1.96 p = .057, as was found among White and Black adults, but positive among White children, β = 0.19, SE = 0.14, t =1.35, p = .18 (although it is important to note that the slope for White children did not differ from 0). In contrast to the findings in Figure 4, birth mother responses to behavioral questions in the scenarios where the birth and adoptive mothers were the same race did not predict feelings toward Blacks, ps > .05, suggesting that only the belief that race is tied to a causal essence is related to racial attitudes toward Blacks and illustrating the value of separating a more general belief in the heritability of behavioral properties from the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence.
We next examined feelings of warmth toward Whites in the same manner. This analysis revealed a significant interaction between birth mother responses for behavioral properties in the different race scenario and age, β = −0.30, SE = 0.14, t = −2.11, p = .04 (although the inclusion of this parameter did not significantly reduce the deviance associated with the model compared to null, F(2, 504) = 2.32, p = .13). This interaction arose because the direction of the relation between birth mother responses and feelings toward Whites was positive among children, β = 0.22, SE = 0.13, t = 1.63, p = .11 and negative among adults, β = −0.08, SE = 0.05, t = −1.68, p = .09, although neither slope differed from 0 (see Figure 5a).
There was also a significant interaction between birth mother responses to behavioral questions and age on feelings toward Whites in scenarios where the birth and adoptive mothers were the same race, β = −0.38, SE = 0.15, t = −2.61, p = .009, F(1, 503) = 4.64, p = .03. Birth mother responses for behavioral properties related to more positive attitudes among children, β = 0.36, SE = 0.13, t = 2.72, p = .008, F(1, 77) = 4.49, p = .04, but did not relate among adults (see Figure 5b). In other words, children’s, but not adults’, attitudes toward Whites were predicted by more general beliefs in the heritability of behavioral properties.
Finally, we tested whether children’s feelings of warmth toward Whites and Blacks was predicted by their beliefs about the heritability of skin color and participant race (adjusting for the race of the birth mother in the story, as noted above). For feelings toward Blacks, birth mother responses on the skin color question were associated with more warmth, β = 0.77, SE = 0.32, t = 2.41, p = .02. There was no interaction with participant race, p = .15, but as shown in Figure 6, White participants drove this effect. Among White children, birth mother responses were associated with more warmth toward Blacks, β = 0.75, SE = 0.32, t = 2.35, p = .02, whereas among Black children, there was no relation, β = 0.11, SE = 0.34, t = 0.31, p = .76.
Discussion
The present research investigated the extent to which young children hold essentialist views of race and the implications of these beliefs for the early development of social attitudes. Our findings, based on a large sample of Black and White children in the United States, suggest that while young children view skin color as inherited, they do not hold strongly causal essentialist representations of race. On average, children expected what a person would be like (in terms of behavioral and psychological properties) to be determined by the environment of upbringing, not by inherited race. Thus, when strong causal essentialist beliefs about race do emerge (which seems to occur in some populations, e.g., Diesendruck et al., 2013; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009), these beliefs are the product of protracted developmental processes and require ample cultural input. The present data suggest that, by focusing on beliefs about heritability of skin color, previous studies (e.g., Hirschfeld, 1995) overestimated the extent to which young children hold essentialist views of race. In the present samples, adults also did not have strongly essentialist representations of race, although they generally viewed behavioral properties as more heritable than children did. Moreover, although low, the average levels of racial essentialism among adults in this sample were comparable to average levels found in previous work using other measures (e.g., Haslam et al., 2002; Mandalaywala et al., 2017; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008).
These findings suggest that the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence, an important component of racial essentialism, takes considerably longer to develop (when it does) than comparable beliefs about animal species (Waxman et al., 2007) or for human gender (Taylor et al., 2009) which emerge by ages 4–5 years old. The lengthy (relative to other categories) and culturally variable developmental trajectory of essentialist beliefs about race (e.g., as found in Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; see also Kinzler & Dautel, 2012; Pauker et al., 2016) is consistent with the proposal that children require a fair amount of developmental and cultural experiences to apply their general essentialist intuitions to particular ways of grouping people (Deeb et al., 2011; Diesendruck & Haber, 2009; Rhodes et al., 2012; Rhodes, Leslie, Saunders, Dunham, & Cimpian, 2017; Segall et al., 2015; Smyth et al., 2017).
We also found that the essentialist belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence varied by children’s own experiences as members of particular groups (i.e., average levels were higher in Black children than White children) and neighborhood demographics. That is, increased outgroup exposure was associated with decreased likelihood of viewing race as tied to a causally powerful essence in children, regardless of their race (for similar findings see Deeb et al., 2011; Pauker et al., 2016; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009: Smyth et al., 2017). Notably, outgroup exposure predicted birth parent responses for the behavioral characteristics only in the scenario where the birth and adoptive mothers were of different races (the strongest and clearest indicator of racial essentialism). Outgroup exposure did not predict responses in the scenario when the mothers were of the same race (a measure of more general beliefs about heritability), or for responses regarding heritability of skin color.
This pattern suggests that outgroup exposure has implications particularly for the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence, but the potential mechanisms underlying this effect remain unclear. There are a number of possible explanations for why outgroup exposure is related to the strength of racial essentialism in children. Research on intergroup contact suggests that greater racial outgroup exposure could be a proxy for higher quality of cross-race relations (e.g., Tropp & Pettigrew, 2005; MacInnis & Page-Gould, 2015), which could facilitate more nuanced and individual – instead of group – oriented beliefs about people. It is important to note that although increased outgroup exposure related to lower levels of essentialist beliefs in both Black and White children, it is possible that neighborhood demographics co-vary with other important demographic factors, such as socioeconomic status, in ways that differ for Black and White children (e.g., higher outgroup exposure for Black participants might signal proximity to gentrification and increasing SES). Thus, our findings here do not indicate whether the neighborhood feature that we measured relates to variation in essentialist beliefs via the same or different mechanisms for children from different backgrounds. For instance, as suggested in Pauker et al. (2016), it is possible that when diversity is experienced in the context of intergroup conflict – something that might not be experienced similarly by White and Black children – exposure to diversity might actually lead to greater essentialist beliefs. Future studies on the development of racial essentialism would benefit from collecting more nuanced and detailed data on the types and quality of social interaction children have, as well as more detailed data on children’s environments themselves.
We found no relation between parents’ and children’s essentialist beliefs among either Black or White children, in contrast to Segall et al. (2015; on ethnic categories in Israel) and Gelman et al. (2004; on gender categories). There are several possible reasons why we did not find a relation here. In previous work, children’s essentialist (or non-essentialist) beliefs about race begin to mirror those of adults in their communities only later in childhood (e.g., between ages 7–10, Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; for similar age-related changes in older childhood for other categories see Astuti et al., 2004; Diesendruck et al., 2013; Smyth et al., 2017). Thus, it is possible that relations between parent and child essentialist beliefs for race emerge at older ages than we studied here. Consistent with the possibility that older children are sensitive to their parents’ beliefs about race, children ages 9–12 are less likely even to mention race when they perceive their parents or teachers to be generally uncomfortable talking openly about race (Pauker, Apfelbaum, & Spitzer, 2015). Language that parents use to talk about or refer to race provides one possible mechanism by which parents could pass on their beliefs to children (see for example, Gelman et al., 2004; Gelman, Ware, & Kleinberg, 2010; Rhodes et al., 2012; Segall et al., 2015). Language used to discuss race, and the effects of language on children’s beliefs, might both vary across racial majority and minority families. For example, explicit discussions of race increase with age among racial minority families in the United States (Hughes & Chen, 1997; Hughes et al., 2006), but remain rare in racial majority families (Vittrup, 2016). In future work, it would be useful to examine the relation between parent and child essentialism in older children, with a particular emphasis on mechanisms of transmission within families and how these might vary across families from different backgrounds.
It is also possible, however, that limitations in our sample size for our analysis of parental beliefs, or the limited measures we had available from parents, made it difficult to detect a relation between parents’ and children’s essentialist beliefs among children in this sample. Here, the only measure of essentialist beliefs that we had from parents was their responses to the switched-at-birth task. Although responses were not at floor – indicating that parents were willing to express some essentialist beliefs about race – it is possible that the task was somewhat transparent for adults and therefore was not a very sensitive measure of their beliefs. Indeed, among adults in this sample, levels of essentialist beliefs about race were relatively low for both parents and adults tested on AMT. Importantly though, it should be noted that levels of racial essentialism are often quite low in adults, even when assessed using measures designed for adults (e.g., Haslam et al., 2002; Mandalaywala et al., 2017; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008). Even if the present task (designed for children) underestimated adults’ levels of essentialist beliefs about race to some extent, it is important to note that variation in adults’ responses still correlated with their racial attitudes. This is consistent with other studies that have found that even if switched-at-birth tasks underestimate mean levels of adults’ essentialist beliefs, variation in adults’ responses to these tasks track variation in adults’ underlying beliefs (see Chalik, Leslie, & Rhodes, 2017, or Segall et al., 2015 for related evidence on this point, and Mandalaywala et al., 2017 for evidence on the relation between essentialism and racial attitudes in adults using additional measures).
Consistent with previous work showing that stability beliefs regarding race develop earlier in Black children than in White children (Kinzler & Dautel, 2012; Roberts & Gelman, 2016), we found that, on average, Black children in this study gave more birth parent responses for behavioral properties compared with White children (although the magnitude of this difference was small and responses were highly variable among children from both groups, as shown in Figure 2). Interestingly, they did so regardless of whether or not the adoptive mother was the same race as the birth mother, suggesting that average levels of beliefs about the heritability of traits in general may be slightly higher among young Black children. Neither of the two aspects of experience that we measured here can account for why Black children in our sample were more likely to view behavioral traits as heritable: parental beliefs did not correlate with child beliefs among either White or Black families in this sample. Moreover, although outgroup exposure related to decreased belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence among both White and Black children, Black children in this sample on average experienced more outgroup exposure – a pattern that cannot account for the observed differences in essentialist beliefs. It is possible that children’s experiences growing up as members of minority groups makes race category boundaries more salient to them, which might reinforce general essentialist views of social structure (beyond those particular to race).
Even though levels of racial essentialism were fairly low among both children and adults, variation in these beliefs reliably predicted racial attitudes. Among adults, we found the same pattern as in previous work (Mandalaywala et al., 2017): more essentialist beliefs related to more negative feelings toward Blacks, among both Black and White adults, illustrating the validity of measuring essentialist beliefs using switched-at-birth tasks in adults. We found this same pattern in this sample of Black children. In contrast, viewing skin color as heritable was unrelated to feelings toward Blacks among Black children, and related positively among White children. In other words, in the present study, causal essentialism specifically was associated with more negative ingroup feelings among Black children and adults (but more negative outgroup feelings among White adults). At first glance, these findings might appear inconsistent with previous work on essentialism and intergroup attitudes in early childhood, which has found that essentialism contributes to more negative outgroup attitudes. For instance, Diesendruck and Menaham (2015) found that increasing the salience of religious-ethnic essentialism regarding Jews and Arabs led 6-year-old Jewish Israeli children to draw members of these two groups farther apart and to draw ingroup members with more positive affect than outgroup members.
One possible explanation for the present findings, in light of this previous work, is that the effect of essentialism on racial prejudice depends less on one’s own group membership and more on the status and stigma associated with a group in society. From this perspective, developing essentialist beliefs about a category that is stigmatized within society could lead people to view negative stereotypes as fixed and inherent features of the category, and therefore to feel more negatively toward group members, even if one is a member of that group. On this account, one possible reason why essentialism did not relate negatively to feelings toward Blacks among White children in our sample (and in fact, in some cases related to warmer feelings) is that White children at the ages we tested were not yet aware of negative societal stereotypes of Black Americans. This explanation is consistent with Rhodes et al. (2017), which found that inducing essentialist beliefs about a novel category (which was not associated with any negative stereotypes) did not lead children to feel more negatively toward members of this group. Also consistent with the possibility that essentialism interacts with information about social status or stereotypes to influence racial attitudes is that, in the present sample, more birth mother responses sometimes related to warmer feelings toward Whites, regardless of participant race. Moreover, this relation varied across development, suggesting again that the incorporation of socially relevant information can alter the effects of essentialism on racial attitudes. Together, the present findings build on prior work to suggest that essentialism alone is insufficient to engender negative social attitudes. Rather, essentialism is more likely to shape racial attitudes only once it interacts with other features of children’s knowledge and experiences, and thus essentialist beliefs can have very different implications for different children.
Although we found that viewing race as tied to a causally powerful essence was related to more negative attitudes toward ingroup members in Black children, this troubling outcome may represent the consequences of one specific component of essentialist beliefs. Racial essentialism is a multifaceted construct, and it is plausible that other components of essentialist beliefs have beneficial effects, perhaps particularly for members of minority groups. For example, by emphasizing category stability and within group commonalities, racial essentialism might increase ingroup identity and pride, which has been associated with positive outcomes in racial minority children (Spencer & Markstrom-Adams, 1990; Rivas-Drake et al., 2014), as well as in older children and adults (Altschul, Oyserman, & Bybee, 2006; Ratner, Halim, & Amodio, 2013; Sellers, Copeland-Linder, Martin, & Lewis, 2006). More developmental research on how various components of essentialist beliefs relate to intergroup phenomena, as well how they relate to children’s self- and group-identity beliefs, could clarify when and how essentialism has more positive or more negative outcomes (for detailed explanation, see Rhodes & Mandalaywala, 2017). Even with the myriad ways essentialist beliefs might shape racial attitudes, it is important to note that the only measure in our study that predicted prejudice toward a vulnerable social group was children’s belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence; negative attitudes toward Blacks were not predicted by their general beliefs about heritability of behavioral properties, or their beliefs about the heritability and stability of skin color. This further illustrates the importance of directly measuring specific features of essentialism in efforts to understand how essentialism shapes intergroup phenomena across development.
The present study found that the belief that race is tied to a causally powerful essence is endorsed at relatively low levels in early childhood and varies in relation to children’s experiences and environment. These findings do not preclude the possibility that children might develop essentialist beliefs about race at an earlier age in communities that differ from those tested here (e.g., in communities where race and racial stereotypes are more salient) or even that children in the present context might have stronger essentialist beliefs about properties other than those that we asked about here (e.g., if there are properties that they associate more strongly with racial stereotypes). Given the sheer number of ways in which people can be classified, however, as well as abundant cultural and historical variability in racial and ethnic classification systems, it is reasonable that children would require ample time and cultural input to develop essentialist beliefs about the particular groups in their community. Moreover, we found that the development and consequences of this component of racial essentialism is variable, illustrating the value of exploring these relations in a more diverse sample of children and adults than have traditionally been included.
Future research should continue to explore the mechanisms by which racial essentialism relates to racial attitudes, both positive and negative, and whether the particular mechanisms in play vary by people’s own experiences in particular groups. By better understanding both the factors that contribute to the development of essentialist beliefs about race, as well as the mechanisms by which they exert their downstream effects, we can develop ways of maximizing positive impacts while minimizing negative ones to improve outcomes for everyone.
Supplementary Material
Acknowledgments
Funding was provided by the NIH Grant R01-HD087672 to M. Rhodes.
We thank the Children’s Museum of Manhattan and the families that participated in this research, as well as the three anonymous reviewers that provided helpful feedback on previous versions of this manuscript.
References
- Allport G. The Nature of Prejudice. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley; 1954. [Google Scholar]
- Altschul I, Oyserman D, Bybee D. Racial-ethnic identity in mid-adolescence: Content and change as predictors of academic achievement. Child Development. 2006;77:1155–1169. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2006.00926.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Astuti R, Solomon GEA, Carey S. Constraints on conceptual development. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development. 2004;69:vii–135. doi: 10.1111/j.0038-976X.2004.00296.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Atran S. Folk biology and the anthropology of science: Cognitive universals and cultural particulars. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1998;21:547–569. doi: 10.1017/S0140525X98001277. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Atran S, Medin D, Lynch E, Vapnarsky V, Ek EU, Sousa P. Folkbiology doesn’t come from folkpsychology: Evidence from Yukatek Maya in cross-cultural perspective. Journal of Cognition and Culture. 2001;1:3–42. doi: 10.1163/156853701300063561. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Bastian B, Haslam N. Psychological essentialism and stereotype endorsement. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology. 2006;42:228–235. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp.2005.03.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Chalik L, Leslie SJ, Rhodes M. Cultural context shapes essentialist beliefs about religion. Developmental Psychology. 2017;53:1178–1187. doi: 10.1037/dev0000301. doi:10/1037dev0000301. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Clark KB, Clark MP. Racial identification and preference among negro children. In: Hartley EL, editor. Readings in Social Psychology. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston; 1947. [Google Scholar]
- Deeb I, Segall G, Birnbaum D, Ben-Eliyahu A, Diesendruck G. Seeing isn’t believing: The effect of intergroup exposure on children’s essentialist beliefs about ethnic categories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2011;101:1139–1156. doi: 10.1037/a0026107. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Diesendruck G, Goldfein-Elbaz R, Rhodes M, Gelman SA, Neumark N. Cross-cultural differences in children’s beliefs about the objectivity of social categories. Child Development. 2013;84:1906–1917. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12108. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Diesendruck G, Haber L. God’s categories: The effect of religiosity on children’s teleological and essentialist beliefs about categories. Cognition. 2009;110:100–114. doi: 10.1016/j.cognition.2008.11.001. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Diesendruck G, haLevi H. The role of language, appearance, and culture in children’s social category-based induction. Child Development. 2006;77:539–553. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2006.00889.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Diesendruck G, Menahem R. Essentialism promotes children’s inter-ethnic bias. Frontiers in Psychology. 2015;6:1180. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01180. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Dunham Y, Baron AS, Carey S. Consequences of “minimal” group affiliations in children. Child Development. 2011;82:793–811. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2011.01577.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gaither SE, Schultz JR, Pauker K, Sommers SR, Maddox KB, Ambady N. Essentialist thinking predicts decrements in children’s memory for racially ambiguous faces. Developmental Psychology. 2013;50:484–488. doi: 10.1037/a0033493. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gelman SA. The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought. New York: Oxford University Press; 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Gelman SA, Taylor MG, Nguyen SP. Mother-child conversations about gender: Understanding the acquisition of essentialist beliefs. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development. 2004;69:1–142. [Google Scholar]
- Gelman SA, Ware EA, Kleinberg F. Effects of generic language on category content and structure. Cognitive Psychology. 2010;61:273–301. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2010.06.001. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gelman S, Wellman H. Insides and essences. Cognition. 1991;38:214–244. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(91)90007-Q. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Gil-White F. Are ethnic groups biological species to the human brain? Essentialism in human cognition of some social groups. Current Anthropology. 2001;42:515–554. doi: 10.1086/321802. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Haslam N, Rothschild L, Ernst D. Essentialist beliefs about social categories. British Journal of Social Psychology. 2000;39:113–127. doi: 10.1348/014466600164363. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Haslam N, Rothschild L, Ernst D. Are essentialist beliefs associated with prejudice? British Journal of Social Psychology. 2002;41:87–100. doi: 10.1348/014466602165072. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hirschfeld LA. Do children have a theory of race? Cognition. 1995;54:209–252. doi: 10.1016/0010-0277(95)91425-R. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Hirschfeld LA. Race in the Making: Cognition, Culture, and the Child’s Construction of Human Kinds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press; 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Hughes D, Chen L. When and what parents tell children about race: An examination of race-related socialization among African American families. Applied Developmental Science. 1997;1:200–214. doi: 10.1207/s1532480xads0104_4. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Hughes D, Rodriguez J, Smith EP, Johnson DJ, Stevenson HC, Spicer P. Parents’ ethnic-racial socialization practices: A review of research and directions for future study. Developmental Psychology. 2006;42:747–770. doi: 10.1037/0012-1649.42.5.747. doi:10/1037/0012-1649.42.5.747. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Jayaratne TE, Ybarra O, Sheldon JP, Brown TN, Feldbaum M, Pfeffer C, Petty EM. White Americans’ genetic lay theories of race differences and sexual orientation: Their relationship with prejudice toward Blacks, and gay men and lesbians. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations. 2006:9. doi: 10.1177/1368430206059863. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Keller J. In genes we trust: The biological component of psychological essentialism and its relationship to mechanisms of motivated social cognition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2005;88:686–702. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.88.4.686. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Kinzler KD, Dautel JB. Children’s essentialist reasoning about language and race. Developmental Science. 2012;15:131–138. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2011.01101.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Lewontin RC. The Apportionment of Human Diversity. In: Dobzhansky T, Hecht MK, Steere WC, editors. Evolutionary Biology. Springer; Boston, MA: 1972. [Google Scholar]
- LoBue V. The Child Affective Facial Expression (CAFE) set. Databrary. 2014 doi: 10.1007/978-1-4684-9063-3_14. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- LoBue V, Thrasher C. The Child Affective Facial Expression (CAFE) set: Validity and reliability from untrained adults. Emotion Science. 2015;5:1532. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2014.01532. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- MacInnis C, Page-Gould E. How can intergroup interaction be bad if intergroup contact is good? Exploring and reconciling an apparent paradox in the science of intergroup relations. Perspectives on Psychological Science. 2015;10:307–327. doi: 10.1177/1745691614568482. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Mandalaywala TM, Amodio DM, Rhodes M. Essentialism promotes racial prejudice by increasing endorsement of social hierarchies. Social Psychological and Personality Science. 2017 doi: 10.1177/1948550617707020. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Markus HR. Pride, prejudice, and ambivalence: Toward a unified theory of race and ethnicity. American Psychologist. 2008;63:651–670. doi: 10.1037/0003-066X.63.8.651. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Martin CL, Parker S. Folk theories about sex and race differences. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 1995;21:45–57. doi: 10.1177/0146167295211006. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Medin D, Ortony A. Psychological essentialism. In: Vosniadou S, Ortony A, editors. Similarity and analogical reasoning. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press; 1989. pp. 179–195. [Google Scholar]
- Nei M, Roychoudhury AK. Genetic relationship and evolution of human races. Evolutionary Biology. 1982;14:1–59. [Google Scholar]
- Pauker K, Apfelbaum EP, Spitzer B. When societal norms and social identity collide: The race talk dilemma for racial minority children. Social Psychological and Personality Science. 2015;6:887–895. doi: 10.1177/1948550615598379. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Pauker K, Ambady N, Apfelbaum EP. Race Salience and Essentialist Thinking in Racial Stereotype Development. Child Development. 2010;81:1799–1813. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2010.01511.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Pauker K, Xu Y, Williams A, Biddle AM. Race essentialism and contextual differences in children’s racial stereotyping. Child Development. 2016;87:1409–1422. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12592. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Raabe T, Beelman A. Development of ethnic, racial, and national prejudice in childhood and adolescence: A multinational meta-analysis of age differences. Child Development. 2011;82:1715–1737. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2011.01668.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Ratner KG, Halim ML, Amodio DM. Perceived stigmatization, ingroup pride, and immune and endocrine activity: Evidence from a Black and Latina community sample. Social Psychological and Personality Science. 2013;4:82–91. doi: 10.1177/1948550612443715. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M. The social allegiance hypothesis. In: Banaji M, Gelman SA, editors. Navigating the Social World: What Infants, Children, and Other Species Can Teach Us. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013. pp. 258–262. [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M, Gelman SA. A developmental examination of the conceptual structure of animal, artifact, and human social categories across two cultural contexts. Cognitive Psychology. 2009;59:294–274. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2009.05.001. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M, Leslie SJ, Bianchi L, Chalik L. The role of generic language in the early development of social categorization. Child Development. 2017 doi: 10.1111/cdev.12714. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M, Leslie SJ, Saunders K, Dunham Y, Cimpian A. How does social essentialism affect the development of inter-group relations. Developmental Science. 2017 doi: 10.1111/desc.12509. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M, Leslie SJ, Tworek C. Cultural transmission of social essentialism. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 2012;109:13526–13531. doi: 10.1073/pnas.1208951109. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rhodes M, Mandalaywala TM. The development and developmental consequences of social essentialism. WIREs Cognitive Science. 2017 doi: 10.1002/wcs.1437. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Rivas-Drake D, Seaton EK, Markstrom C, Quintana S, Syed M, Lee RM, Schwartz SJ, Umana-Taylor AJ, French S, Yip T. Ethnic and racial identity in adolescence: Implications for psychosocial, academic, and health outcomes. Child Development. 2014;85:40–57. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12200. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Roberts SO, Gelman SA. Do children see in black and white? Children’s and adults’ categorizations of multiracial individuals. Child Development. 2015;86:1830–1847. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12410. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Roberts SO, Gelman SA. Can White children grow up to be Black? Children’s reasoning about the stability of emotion and race. Developmental Psychology. 2016;52:887–893. doi: 10.1111/cdev.12410. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Roberts SO, Gelman SA. Now you see race, now you don’t: Verbal cues influence children’s reasoning about the stability of emotion and race. Cognitive Development. 2017;43:129–141. doi: 10.1016/j.cogdev.2017.03.003. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Segall G, Birnbaum D, Deeb I, Diesendruck G. The intergenerational transmission of ethnic essentialism: How parents talk counts the most. Developmental Science. 2015;18:543–555. doi: 10.1111/desc.1223. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Sellers RM, Copeland-Linder N, Martin PP, Lewis RL. Racial identity matters: The relationship between racial discrimination and psychological functioning in African American adolescents. Journal of Research on Adolescence. 2006;16:187–216. doi: 10.1111/j.1532-7795.2006.00128.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Shutts K. Young children’s preferences: Gender, race, and social status. Child Development Perspectives. 2015;9:262–266. doi: 10.1111/cdep.12154. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Smyth K, Feeney A, Eidson R Cole, Coley JD. Development of essentialist thinking about religion categories in Northern Ireland (and the United States) Developmental Psychology. 2017;53:475–496. doi: 10.1037/dev0000253. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Sousa P, Atran S, Medin DL. Essentialism and folkbiology: Evidence from Brazil. Journal of Cognition and Culture. 2002;2:195–223. doi: 10.1163/15685370260225099. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Spencer MB, Markstrom-Adams C. Identity processes among racial and ethnic minority children in America. Child Development. 1990;61:290–310. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.1990.tb02780.x. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Springer K. Young children’s understanding of a biological basis for parent-offspring relations. Child Development. 1996;67:2841–2856. doi: 10.2307/1131755. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Taylor MG. The development of children’s beliefs about social and biological aspects of gender differences. Child Development. 1996;67:1555–1571. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.1996.tb01814.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Taylor MG, Rhodes M, Gelman SA. Boys will be boys, cows will be cows: Children’s essentialist reasoning about human gender and animal development. Child Development. 2009;79:1270–1287. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2009.01272.x. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Tropp LR, Pettigrew TF. Differential relationships between intergroup contact and affective and cognitive dimensions of prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 2005;31:1145–1158. doi: 10.1177/0146167205274854. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Vittrup B. Color blind or color conscious? White American mothers’ approaches to racial socialization. Journal of Family Issues. 2016 doi: 10.1177/0192513X16676858. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Waxman SR. Names will never hurt me? Naming and the development of racial and gender categories in preschool-aged children. European Journal of Social Psychology. 2010;40:593–610. doi: 10.1002/ejsp.732. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
- Waxman SR, Medin DL, Ross N. Folkbiological reasoning from a cross-cultural developmental perspective: Early essentialist notions are shaped by cultural beliefs. Developmental Psychology. 2007;43:294–308. doi: 10.1037/0012-1649.43.2.294. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Williams MJ, Eberhardt JL. Biological conceptions of race and the motivation to cross racial boundaries. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2008;94:1033–1047. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.94.6.1033. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- Wilson JR, Lorenz KA. Modeling binary correlated responses using SAS, SPSS and R. Cham, Suisse: Springer; 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Yzerbyt V, Corneille O, Estrada C. The interplay of subjective essentialism and entitativity in the formation of stereotypes. Personality and Social Psychology Review. 2001;5:141–155. doi: 10.1207/S15327957PSPR0502_5. [DOI] [Google Scholar]
Associated Data
This section collects any data citations, data availability statements, or supplementary materials included in this article.