Abstract
The National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE) promotes evidence-based medicine throughout contemporary health care. Its guidelines are employed in the United Kingdom and elsewhere, influencing the type and quality of health care provided. NICE considers a range of evidence in the process of creating guidelines; however, the research accepted as evidence greatly relies on positivist methodologies. At times, it is unnecessarily restricted to quantitative methods of data collection. Using the Clinical Guideline 140, opioids in palliative care, as an example, it is demonstrated that the research accepted as evidence is unable to provide answers to complex problems. In addition, several inherent biases are discussed, such as age inequality and pharmaceutical company influence. In order to provide coherent and useful guidelines relevant to complex problems in a real world setting, NICE must move away from focusing on data from randomised controlled trials. Its epistemological foundation must be questioned, paving the way for alternative research paradigms to be considered as evidence and thereby enriching subsequent guidelines.
Keywords: Pain management, palliative care, evidence-based medicine, clinical guidelines, opioids
Introduction
The appearance of evidence-based medicine (EBM) in the 1990s1 heralded a transformation in health care practice. The growing evidence base from clinical trials, published in peer-reviewed medical journals, replaced unproven personal ideas and subjective experience as the foundation of health-related decisions. In the United Kingdom, one response to this shift was the formation in 1999 of the National Institute for Clinical Excellence (NICE). Its aim was to make EBM tools and skills available to the UK’s National Health Service (NHS) in order to permit clinically and cost-effective health care.2 NICE produces clinical guidelines covering disease management and the effectiveness of interventions. In 2013, the name was changed to National Institute for Health and Care Excellence to reflect an extended remit covering the concepts of health promotion and social care.2
In health care, clinical guidelines are produced by multiple organisations at local, regional, national and international levels. They are recommendations to improve patient care, based on either systematic reviews of evidence or consensus of expert opinions.3 Health care professionals often consider several different guidelines to inform their clinical decision making, with some proponents considering NICE clinical guidelines as the benchmark of best management.4 There are, however, concerns that injustice, prejudice and rationing are implicit in the guidelines.5 For example, advocates for certain patient-populations have previously considered NICE guidelines to be the UK government’s justification for withholding expensive treatments, such as in Alzheimer’s disease6 and neuroblastomas in children.7 Others argue that the pre-digested evidence and ready-made guidelines deskill clinicians.8
Clinical Guideline 140 (CG140), ‘Opioids in palliative care: safe and effective prescribing of strong opioids for pain in palliative care of adults’,9 was published in 2012 and updated in 2016. This article will use this guideline as a basis for exploring the positivist, empirical paradigms of EBM and NICE. It will argue that these are insufficient foundations for dealing with the complexities of pain and the decisions relating to better managing it. Finally, the advantages of broadening the paradigmatic approach to CG140, and other NICE guidelines, will be discussed.
Evidence
NICE clinical guidelines are developed using standard processes, with explanations of how decisions and recommendations are made.10 A Guideline Development Group is responsible for writing each guideline and it employs tools, such as the Grading of Recommendations Assessment, Development and Evaluation (GRADE) system to appraise the available evidence. NICE introduced the GRADE system to encourage a fairer and more rigorous weighting of the evidence. It replaced the hierarchy of evidence, which involved scoring evidence on a scale of trustworthiness, or alternatively as expert opinion. Qualitative research and integrative reviews, encompassing both qualitative and quantitative data, have been recognised as credible sources of evidence by NICE.11 However, there appears to remain an ongoing greater respect for methods considered as higher in the hierarchy, such as systematic reviews of randomised controlled trials.8
The philosophical foundations of research
There are two classical ways, or ontologies, in which the world can be viewed. One approach suggests an objective reality exists, independent of people or social situations. Research is able to discover this reality with a direct relationship between the quality and quantity of research, and the accuracy of how that reality is captured. This view describes the ontology labelled ‘positivism’.12 In the second approach, the idea of a single true reality is rejected and posits multiple realities co-existing at the same time, possibly in the same situation, a constructivist ontology. Everyone creates or constructs their own realities, including both the researcher and the researched. A constructivist ontology.13 NICE provides no declaration of its paradigmatic framework; however, this article argues that NICE publications are largely located in a positivist paradigm.14
Clinical guideline: opioids in palliative care
Pain is a common problem in populations with life-limiting illnesses, with over 50% of these patients experiencing pain.15 The World Health Organisation (WHO) considers pain management a global priority and it promotes a three-step guide to providing effective pain relief in adults, with strong opioids, such as morphine at step three.16 CG140 is published by NICE to promote safe effective prescribing of these strong opioids for pain, cognisant of the legislative, patient and prescriber barriers to prescribing.17,18 It, however, contains no definition of pain which is the central concept of the guideline.
Controversies of CG140: pain
Pain is a subjective, socially constructed phenomenon, embedded in the cultural context, which can best be described through our interpretation of it.19 Scientific positivist approaches are useful in researching the pathophysiology of pain; however, there are challenges measuring its subjective nature. Pain may be perceived as relating to a persons’ guilt or shame, or may be interpreted as a message, full of meaning and significance. It may also be viewed as a meaningless organic symptom to be avoided or a challenge to be surmounted.20 Irrespective of how it is interpreted, pain remains a personalised, idiosyncratic phenomenon, difficult for positivist research to access and measure.21 Researchers employ reductionist methodologies to measure pain, although there is no consensus on the classification of pain in cancer-related clinical trials with extensive use of heterogeneous, non-validated methods of pain assessment.22 The Cancer Pain Assessment and Classification System recommends that there should be at least four domains to pain assessment: pain intensity, pain mechanism, breakthrough pain and psychological distress.23
The critical appraisal of studies in CG140 includes no mention of how pain is defined, and limited consideration of its measurement. Pain intensity and, occasionally, breakthrough pain are the only related outcomes recorded in the evidence tables.24 For example, the literature search for the second review question: ‘What is the most effective first-line opioid treatment in patients with advanced and progressive disease who require strong opioids?’ identified 25 empirical quantitative studies. The respective evidence table recorded that pain intensity was measured through 100 mm visual analogue scales (n = 9), 4-point Likert scales (n = 6), or was not recorded (n = 10).24 The broad concept of pain is reduced to a single numerical score, ready for statistical analysis. The social, psychological and spiritual elements of the experience of pain are ignored.25 There exists more holistic or descriptive pain scales, such as the Brief Pain Inventory; however, these are absent from the included evidence. In the included study by Arkinstall et al.,26 the authors compared a sustained release morphine tablet with immediate release solution. They employed the McGill-Melzack Pain Questionnaire to measure pain however used only the sub-index ‘Present Pain Intensity’. This study was potentially biased as it was supported by a grant from the pharmaceutical company who produced the branded sustained release morphine tablet.
Controversies of CG140: biases
The critical appraisal of individual studies by NICE includes the consideration of certain possible biases, for example the method of randomisation of participants and the accounting for drop-outs in the statistical analysis. This approach is employed in an attempt to provide a just solution for a target population. It is important and appropriate; however, it is limited to the level of the individual studies. It does not question whether there are higher-level biases which prevent the selected evidence base from providing a just solution. For example, older participants and those with co-morbidities are more likely to be excluded from clinical research.27 In the NICE guideline on managing older persons with low back pain, most of the studies accepted as evidence excluded those over 70 years old, and very few reported how the effectiveness of therapies differed by age.28
The funding of clinical trials by pharmaceutical companies is a further example of injustice within clinical research. Industry-influenced research agendas have resulted in much of the current clinical research being focused on patentable treatments such as drugs and drug delivery technologies.29 Furthermore, published industry-sponsored research produces more pro-industry outcomes compared to publicly funded research.30 To counter this bias, NICE recommends an evaluation of the funding sources of research through their inclusion in the generic evidence tables.10 However, this item is absent from the evidence tables employed in CG14024 and as such, there is no record that the source of funding was considered in the critical appraisal of evidence. This is evident in the paper by Arkinstall et al.26 mentioned above, and Davies et al.31 who declared financial ties with the pharmaceutical company producing fentanyl delivered nasally by a patented drug delivery system, the focus of their research.32 The Guideline Development Group made no mention of these potential biases, either in the GRADE profile summaries9 or in the respective evidence tables.24
Controversies of CG140: is the positivist foundation appropriate for the subject matter?
The construction of the CG140’s review questions highlights the value-driven assumptions and the ontological foundation. The following review question illustrates this, ‘What information do patients with advanced and progressive disease who require strong opioids, or their carers, need to consent to opioid treatment, and monitor the effectiveness and side effects of the opioid?’9 This question is defined as ‘qualitative’ and therefore, evidence was restricted to qualitative studies. Qualitative research methods are an appropriate choice to understand participants’ feelings and fears at a deeper level. These methods, such as focus group discussions and in-depth interviews, are commonly based in a constructivist approach, in which the perspectives of the research participants are regarded as equally valid and real, even if conflicting.12 However, the review question is phrased in a closed way which implies that there exists a single answer, true for all patients and their families. This is in line with the underlying positivist framework, which we argue is not in harmony with the ethos behind much of qualitative research. It would be preferable to use an alternative, more open question, such as ‘how do patients with advanced and progressive disease requiring strong opioids, or their carers, perceive opioid treatment?’. This would better facilitate the inclusion of data from the perspective of the patient and their family, rather than that of the health care professional. Examples of such data and their suitability are discussed below.
The place for alternative philosophies
Pain is a complex subjective phenomenon; however, there is no acknowledgement within CG140 of the limitations of quantitative measurements of health, which reduce rich descriptions to a single numerical score. This reductionist approach to knowledge creation is framed within the concept of value-free interpretation of research findings. This is a flawed concept as there is an unbridgeable chasm between evidence and theory, labelled the Gap Argument.33 This gap is not free of values and prejudices, rather it is filled with cultural, social and political values, and it is this value-ladened environment that functions as a lens through which knowledge is created.34 These values influence, not only, how policy makers, researchers and clinicians interpret data, but also how data are created: which topics are researched, the choice of research questions, the selection of methods and the level of integration of the patients in research.27
Patient-centred care is central to EBM.1 For it to be practiced, the health care professional needs to journey to the patient’s world and understand their feelings, thoughts and experiences.35 We suggest that research approaches aligned to constructivism are inherently complementary to this approach. The rejection of an objective reality and the acceptance of multiple co-existing realities denotes the importance of individual patients’ views. Patient-centred care is acknowledged in the section on patient information and communication. It is not, however, carried over to the other sections, which maintain a symptom or disease- centred approach. This genre of research could enrich CG140, through increasing the individuality, broadening the evidence base and challenging the objectives of the guidelines:36
Individuality versus generic population. NICE guidelines are designed to be applied at an individual patient level; however, this purpose can be over-shadowed by the population-based evidence. The individual prescriber should be encouraged to consider the best fit for the patient in front of them, rather than the right response.37
Evidence base. The patient’s lifeworld, their understanding and experience of illness are valid and important sources of evidence.34
Goal. The central tenet of CG140 is the provision of pain relief in an empirical biomedical context; however, the patient-centred goal of management is the reintegration of the patient into their own lifeworld.34 Patients do not consider a reduction of their pain on a numerical rating scale as helpful. Rather, they are interested in whether their pain is sufficiently controlled so that they can perform their desired activities and maintain their relationships.38
Synthesis of research
The reliance of CG140 upon scientific data to improve skills and practice reflects the predominance of ‘techne’, the technical skill in arts and crafts. ‘Techne’ is one of several intellectual virtues described by Aristotle, traditionally ascribed to medicine.39 The complementary virtue of ‘phronesis’ or practical wisdom is little represented in CG140. This genre of knowledge is learned through practical life-experience, and not through the understanding of theory.35 This virtue, like intuition, is complex and not easily measured or quantified. However, these challenges do not negate its importance, as it is naïve to accept that being able to measure something equates to understanding it. For CG140 to be most useful and applicable to its readers, it requires elements of phronesis to complement the already present techne.40 One approach to this is through the use of integrative reviews, which allow both quantitative and qualitative research to be synthesised to give a better understanding of the researched topic. Qualitative research should not be relegated to the ‘qualitative’ question, rather its integration with quantitative data can facilitate a better understanding of the wider subject area, making guidelines more patient-centred, while still being clinically and cost-effective. There are several approaches for the systematic review of qualitative studies and the integrative review of qualitative and quantitative studies.41 However, the integration of qualitative research into the production of guidelines has been slower.42,43 For example, such findings are limited to the section on information and communication in the present structure of CG140. An alternative approach is the mapping of qualitative data onto guidelines’ recommendations.18 An example of such is provided in Table 1, with qualitative data cited in this article mapped to the recommendation 1.1.13 of CG140, which relates to the initiation of subcutaneous opioids.
Table 1.
Findings relating to initiating subcutaneous opioids | |
---|---|
Author | Recommendation 1.1.13: ‘Consider initiating subcutaneous opioids with the lowest acquisition cost for patients in whom oral opioids are not suitable and analgesic requirements are unstable, supported by specialist advice where needed’ |
Flemming18 | Patients may perceive unstable pain as a sign of worsening health, disease progression and impending death |
Flemming18 | Patients and families may fear that any increased dose of morphine will lead to sedation and a hastened death, especially when given through a syringe-drivers |
Gibbins et al.38 | Patients want their pain to be controlled to allow them to keep up their usual activities and social relationships. They may prefer choices of pain management and administration which can best maintain their mobility and independence |
Conclusion
This article argues that the positivist framework adopted by CG140 is inappropriate for the subject matter. It does not, however, suggest that quantitative research is without value. Rather, it highlights some of its weaknesses, unacknowledged within CG140, and how it can be complemented with research from alternative philosophies. Much of CG140’s reductionist approach to pain management results in disease-centred health care and does not give credence to the experience of the patient. It is important that health care professionals do not ignore how pain is experienced and what it means to an individual patient. We argue that more space for intuition and alternative philosophical approaches would lead to improved patient-centred care, in line with the objectives of EBM.
Footnotes
Conflict of interest: The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship and/or publication of this article.
Funding: The author(s) received no financial support for the research, authorship and/or publication of this article.
ORCID iD: David Fearon https://orcid.org/0000-0002-0295-3118
Sean Hughes https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2264-8479
References
- 1. Sackett DL, Rosenberg W, Gray JA, et al. Evidence based medicine: what it is and what it isn’t. BMJ 1996; 312: 71–72. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2. National Institute for Health and Care Excellence. Who we are, www.nice.org.uk/about/who-we-are (2016, accessed 17 April 2016).
- 3. Deng Y, Luo L, Hu Y, et al. Clinical practice guidelines for the management of neuropathic pain: a systematic review. BMC Anesthesiol 2016; 16: 12. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4. Streeter EH, Brewster SF. NICE guidelines on Prostate Cancer Active Surveillance: is UK practice leading the world? BJU Int 2015; 115: 12–13. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 5. Harris J. It’s not NICE to discriminate. J Med Ethics 2005; 31: 373–375. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6. Hunt N. Alzheimer’s society replies to Iain Chalmers. BMJ 2007; 335: 541.17855322 [Google Scholar]
- 7. Bernstein J. Restricting access to hope: a parent’s perspective on the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE) preliminary guidance for dinutuximab. Pediatr Blood Cancer 2016; 63: 964–965. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. Hutchison KJ, Rogers WA. Challenging the epistemological foundations of EBM: what kind of knowledge does clinical practice require? J Eval Clin Pract 2012; 18: 984–991. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9. National Institute for Health and Care Excellence. Palliative care for adults: strong opioids for pain relief. Clinical Guideline 140, http://www.nice.org.uk/guidance/CG140 (2016, accessed 19 October 2017). [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10. National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence. The guidelines manual. London: National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- 11. National Institute for Health and Care Excellence. Developing NICE guidelines: the manual, www.nice.org.uk/process/pmg20/chapter/reviewing-research-evidence (2017, accessed 19 October 2017). [PubMed]
- 12. Bryman A. Social research methods. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- 13. Ellingson LL. Engaging crystallization in qualitative research. London: SAGE, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- 14. Wilmot S. Evidence, ethics and inclusion: a broader base for NICE. Med Health Care Philos 2011; 14: 111–121. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 15. Moens K, Higginson IJ, Harding R, et al. Are there differences in the prevalence of palliative care-related problems in people living with advanced cancer and eight non-cancer conditions? A systematic review. J Pain Symptom Manage 2014; 48: 660–677. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 16. World Health Organization. WHO’s cancer pain ladder for adults, www.who.int/cancer/palliative/painladder/en/ (2017, accessed 19 October 2017).
- 17. Nguyen LM, Rhondali W, De la Cruz M, et al. Frequency and predictors of patient deviation from prescribed opioids and barriers to opioid pain management in patients with advanced cancer. J Pain Symptom Manage 2013; 45: 506–516. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 18. Flemming K. The use of morphine to treat cancer-related pain: a synthesis of quantitative and qualitative research. J Pain Symptom Manage 2010; 39: 139–154. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 19. Best S. The social construction of pain: an evaluation. Disabil Soc 2007; 22: 161–171. [Google Scholar]
- 20. Renqvist AL. An apology for pain. Comp Continent Philos 2015; 4: 179–193. [Google Scholar]
- 21. Morris DB. The culture of pain. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- 22. Haugen DF, Hjermstad MJ, Hagen N, et al. Assessment and classification of cancer breakthrough pain: a systematic literature review. Pain 2010; 149: 476–482. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 23. Kaasa S, Apolone G, Klepstad P, et al. Expert conference on cancer pain assessment and classification – the need for international consensus: working proposals on international standards. BMJ Support Palliat Care 2011; 1: 281–287. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 24. National Institute for Health and Care Excellence. Clinical Guideline 140: palliative care for adults: strong opioids for pain relief (Appendix E) www.nice.org.uk/guidance/cg140/evidence/opioids-in-palliative-care-appendix-e-evidence-table-pdf-186485295 (2016, accessed 30 October 2017). [PubMed]
- 25. Morrissey MB. Phenomenology of pain and suffering at the end of life: a humanistic perspective in gerontological health and social work. J Soc Work End Life Palliat Care 2011; 7: 14–38. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 26. Arkinstall WW, Goughnour BR, White JA, et al. Control of severe pain with sustained-release morphine tablets v. oral morphine solution. CMAJ 1989; 140: 653–657. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 27. Kelly MP, Heath I, Howick J, et al. The importance of values in evidence-based medicine. BMC Med Ethics 2015; 16: 69. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 28. Von Spannenberg SS, Jones GT, Macfarlane GJ. The evidence base for managing older persons with low back pain. Br J Pain 2012; 6: 166–169. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 29. Rogers W, Ballantyne A. Justice in health research: what is the role of evidence-based medicine? Perspect Biol Med 2009; 52: 188–202. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 30. Bhandari M, Busse JW, Jackowski D, et al. Association between industry funding and statistically significant pro-industry findings in medical and surgical randomized trials. CMAJ 2004; 170: 477–480. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 31. Davies A, Sitte T, Elsner F, et al. Consistency of efficacy, patient acceptability, and nasal tolerability of fentanyl pectin nasal spray compared with immediate-release morphine sulfate in breakthrough cancer pain. J Pain Symptom Manage 2011; 41: 358–366. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 32. Watts P, Smith A. PecSys: in situ gelling system for optimised nasal drug delivery. Expert Opin Drug Deliv 2009; 6: 543–552. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 33. Goldenberg MJ. How can feminist theories of evidence assist clinical reasoning and decision-making? Soc Epistemol 2014; 29: 3–30. [Google Scholar]
- 34. Goldenberg MJ. On evidence and evidence-based medicine: lessons from the philosophy of science. Soc Sci Med 2006; 62: 2621–2632. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 35. Svenaeus F. Hermeneutics of medicine in the wake of Gadamer: the issue of phronesis. Theor Med Bioeth 2003; 24: 407–431. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 36. Greenhalgh T, Snow R, Ryan S, et al. Six ‘biases’ against patients and carers in evidence-based medicine. BMC Med 2015; 13: 200. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 37. Kotzee B, Paton A, Conroy M. Towards an empirically informed account of phronesis in medicine. Perspect Biol Med 2016; 59: 337–350. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 38. Gibbins J, Bhatia R, Forbes K, et al. What do patients with advanced incurable cancer want from the management of their pain? A qualitative study. Palliat Med 2014; 28: 71–78. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 39. Landes DA. Phronēsis and the art of healing: Gadamer, Merleau-Ponty, and the phenomenology of equilibrium in health. Hum Stud 2015; 38: 261–279. [Google Scholar]
- 40. Petersén AC, Olsson JI. Calling evidence-based practice into question: acknowledging phronetic knowledge in social work: Table 1. Br J Soc Work 2015; 45: 1581–1597. [Google Scholar]
- 41. Joanna Briggs Institute. Joanna Briggs Institute reviewers’ manual: 2014 edition. Adelaide, SA, Australia: The University of Adelaide, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- 42. Munoz-Plaza CE, Parry C, Hahn EE, et al. Integrating qualitative research methods into care improvement efforts within a learning health system: addressing antibiotic overuse. Health Res Pol Syst 2016; 14: 63. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 43. Utens CM, Dirksen CD, van der Weijden T, et al. How to integrate research evidence on patient preferences in pharmaceutical coverage decisions and clinical practice guidelines: a qualitative study among Dutch stakeholders. Health Policy 2016; 120: 120–128. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]