In 1982, the Journal of the Royal College of General Practitioners published Ivan Illich’s article ‘Medicalization in Primary Care’.1 Illich held a paradoxical belief that GPs could contribute to the healthy process of demedicalisation, that is:
‘... to offer their patients the occasion to de-medicalize their own attitude to pain, disability, discomfort, ageing, birth and death.’ 1
In other words, ‘unhooking [patients] from the health system’.1 This article presents WONCA’s definition of Quaternary Prevention (P4) as a unifying framework that organises GPs’ scope on demedicalisation.2
EXPLAINING QUATERNARY PREVENTION
Devised in 1986 by Marc Jamoulle, a Belgian GP, P4 is:
‘... an action taken to identify a patient at risk of over-medicalization, to protect him from new medical invasion, and to suggest to him interventions which are ethically acceptable.’ 3
P4 was initially oriented to those patients who were feeling ill, but who had no clinically established disease: the worried well and those presenting with medically unexplained symptoms.3 The former are concerned about their health status and usually demand check-ups; the latter present with symptoms that lack pathophysiological explanations. Some of these symptoms stem from psychosocial circumstances. Both groups of patients are subjected to overmedicalisation.4
Box 1 provides a framework that organises the scope of P4. Its clockwise-arrow at the centre indicates that P4 impacts the other three preventive levels: primary prevention (P1), secondary prevention (P2), and tertiary prevention (P3). Box 1 also differentiates two demedicalisation scenarios: 1) P1 and P2, which deals with symptomless individuals; and 2) P3 and P4, which comprises disease/illness dimensions, merging clinical care with preventive activities.
Individuals undergoing P1 and P2 might be subjected to overdiagnosis and overtreatment (that is, overmedicalisation). Overdiagnosis is ‘the diagnosis of a condition that would have remained indolent in the patient’s lifetime if left undetected’.5 Thus, patients end up dying from competing diseases and not gaining in longevity.
The main problem of overdiagnosis is overtreatment: treating pseudo-diseases that bear no prospect of benefit.6 This represents harm both to individuals’ wellbeing and to health systems as it generates unnecessary costs and waste of resources. Potential sources of overdiagnosis are disease screening, altering cut-off points for defining a risk factor or a disease, and financial incentives (for example, pay-for-performance schemes).5
FIRST DO NO HARM
An example of controversial P1 is prescription of statins for individuals with 10% cardiovascular mortality risk in 10 years.7 This increases the overdiagnosis effect and offers minimal individual benefit. Regarding P2, there are lots of instances of overmedicalisation due to non-evidence-based screening for thyroid, prostate, and ovarian cancers. Breast cancer screening also needs to be readdressed. After an average of two decades of breast cancer screening in Canada8 and the US,9 there are considerable overdiagnosis rates (roughly 30%), minimal (if any) impacts on mortality,10 but known potential harms such as an increase in heart disease (27%) and lung cancer (78%) mortality.11
Concerning P3, diabetes care provides a good example. The belief in ‘the lower the better’ Hb1Ac levels has potentially done more harm than good due to polypharmacy, reduction in quality of life, and an increase in mortality.12 Therefore, distinction between clinical and preventive activities is essential to circumvent the excesses of biomedicine. In prevention, the bioethical principle of non-maleficence should prevail as we are dealing with healthy or asymptomatic people, and the oath First Do No Harm should guide GPs’ practice.13 P4 implies an attitudinal shift of self-containment, caution, and reassurance of patients’ integrity when dealing with preventive interventions. It requires a critical appraisal of current biomedical knowledge, inviting GPs to be more autonomous, proactive, and to follow protocol less slavishly.
CONCLUSION
Quaternary prevention is a well-devised concept that embeds three main points: risk of overmedicalisation, patients’ protection, and ethical alternatives. This definition is more comprehensive than the recent initiative to redefine it in terms of the harm/benefit ratio.3 P4 provides a platform that may help GPs to realise the vital task of demedicalising by sorting out what can or should be demedicalised in clinical care.
To realise this task, as paradoxically envisioned by Illich, P4 needs support and further research to be globally disseminated in primary care.
REFERENCES
- 1.Illich I. Medicalization and primary care. J R Coll Gen Pract. 1982;32(241):463–470. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 2.Bentzen N. Wonca International Classification Committee. Wonca international dictionary for general/family practice. Copenhagen: 2003. http://www.ph3c.org/PH3C/docs/27/000092/0000052.pdf (accessed 3 Dec 2018). [Google Scholar]
- 3.Martins C, Godycki-Cwirko M, Heleno B, Brodersen J. Quaternary prevention: reviewing the concept. Eur J Gen Pract. 2018;24(1):106–111. doi: 10.1080/13814788.2017.1422177. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4.Norman AH, Tesser CD. Quaternary prevention: the basis for its operationalization in the doctor–patient relationship. Rev Bras Med Família e Comunidade. 2015;10(35):1. [Google Scholar]
- 5.Bulliard J-L, Chiolero A. Screening and overdiagnosis: public health implications. Public Health Rev. 2015;36(1):1–5. doi: 10.1186/s40985-015-0012-1. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6.Welch HG, Schwartz L, Woloshin S. Overdiagnosed: making people sick in the pursuit of health. Boston, MA: Beacon Press; 2011. [Google Scholar]
- 7.Redberg RF, Katz MH. Statins for primary prevention. JAMA Intern Med. 2017;177(1):21. doi: 10.1001/jamainternmed.2016.7585. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8.Miller AB, Wall C, Baines CJ, et al. Twenty five year follow-up for breast cancer incidence and mortality of the Canadian National Breast Screening Study: randomised screening trial. BMJ. 2014;348:g366. doi: 10.1136/bmj.g366. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9.Bleyer A, Welch HG. Effect of three decades of screening mammography on breast-cancer incidence. N Engl J Med. 2012;367(21):1998–2005. doi: 10.1056/NEJMoa1206809. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 10.Welch HG, Black WC. Overdiagnosis in cancer. J Natl Cancer Inst. 2010;102:605–613. doi: 10.1093/jnci/djq099. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 11.Gøtzsche PC, Jørgensen KJ. Screening for breast cancer with mammography. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2013;(6):CD001877. doi: 10.1002/14651858.CD001877.pub5. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 12.Shaughnessy AF, Erlich DR, Slawson DC. Type 2 diabetes: updated evidence requires updated decision making. Am Fam Physician. 2015;92(1):22. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 13.Tesser CD, Norman AH. Differentiating clinical care from disease prevention: a prerequisite for practicing quaternary prevention. Cad Saude Publica. 2016;32(10):e00012316. doi: 10.1590/0102-311X00012316. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]