The United Nations (UN) Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD)1 was received with high expectations by all those concerned with the protection of the human rights of people with mental disorders and psychosocial disabilities. For most sectors of the mental health community, it appeared to be a unique opportunity to take a leap forward in the development of laws promoting the rights of this group of people and facilitating the development of community‐based and human rights‐oriented mental health care.
Is it possible that the UN Committee's General Comment No. 1 on Article 12 of the Convention2 has created a situation in which all these expectations are in danger? Unfortunately, the danger is real. A large number of States Parties that have ratified the Convention have also expressed their disagreement with the Committee's interpretation, in particular regarding the absolute prohibition of substitute decision‐making. An increasing number of human rights experts, scholars and clinicians have stated their conviction that this interpretation, if accepted, would result in serious adverse consequences for people with mental health disorders and psychosocial disabilities, and would undermine some of the hard‐won critical rights of these people3. Although many mental health service users’ organizations support the prohibition of involuntary admission and treatment, there are indicators showing that this view is not shared by all people with mental disorders nor by the majority of family members. In this context, we have to conclude that the possibility that governments will change their mental health laws in accordance with the directives of the Committee seems rather remote.
How did we get into this situation? The limited involvement of some relevant sectors (e.g., clinicians) in the drafting of the Committee's Comment, and an insufficient debate about the implications and the implementation of the CRPD, were important factors. However, in my opinion, the ambiguity of the text of clause 4 of Article 12, pointed out by Szmukler4, has certainly had a very strong influence in this process. It was this ambiguity, in which it is difficult not to see an imperfect compromise between conflicting approaches, that the Committee has tried to overcome, alas, at the cost of a radical and reductionist interpretation, that is not compatible with the complexity of the issue at stake.
According to the Committee's interpretation, any form of substitute decision‐making is considered a violation of the Convention's guarantee of legal capacity on an equal basis. This means that, faced with a person with a mental disorder who does not accept a treatment considered indispensable and has a severe lack of decision‐making skills, a psychiatrist would not be allowed to resort to involuntary treatment in any circumstance. Because, in order to preserve legal capacity, it is necessary to respect the person's rights, will and preferences, in such a situation the psychiatrist would have to rely solely on the support that the State is obliged to provide for the person to become able to express his/her will and preferences.
This approach suffers from several fragilities and contradictions. One of these has to do with the arguments used by the Committee to justify why the lack of decision‐making skills cannot be the basis for any form of substitute decision. In fact, one of these arguments – that the assessment of these skills would be impossible – is not confirmed by the available evidence5, while the other – that its determination would be discriminatory – has been refuted by several experts, who have argued that the assessment of decision‐making capacity does not need to be discriminatory in nature and can be applied to all people equally4, 6.
Another example is the idea according to which, with the appropriate support, most persons with disabilities will be able to express their will and preferences, a presumption which ignores the fact that, in many situations, it is not possible to guarantee this support, while in many other situations this support will not be effective. Finally, denying persons with severe mental disorders the treatment they need, in cases where it has been proved that they lack the ability to make decisions regarding their treatment needs, and doing so in the name of “the freedom to take risks” , is, in my opinion, highly debatable from the ethical point of view.
Despite all the objections that may be leveled against the Committee's Comment, we should not forget, as Szmukler4 rightly underlines, that the publication of this Comment has had several important merits. It has stimulated a debate, although this has been manifestly insufficient so far. It has called attention to the fact that, for many people with mental disorders and psychosocial disabilities, involuntary admission and treatment may be a very painful and traumatic experience. Finally, it has represented a strong challenge to be met by the development of new contributions that may help to build a much‐needed consensus.
The proposal of Szmukler and Dawson4, 7 goes in that direction and proves that it is possible to formulate a law that is generic, non‐discriminatory towards people with mental health disabilities, based on decision‐making ability in relation to a particular treatment decision at a particular time, and that permits involuntary treatment when all attempts at support have failed in helping the person to make a decision that could be considered autonomous.
The proposal of a more subjective approach to both the concept of best interests and the assessment of the person's decision‐making ability could also help to ensure that the deep beliefs and values (in other words, the will and preferences) of the person are taken into consideration4. Although differing from this approach in several specific aspects, the proposals put forward by Freeman et al3 and Scholten and Gather8 share some of its principles.
Important differences remain between these proposals and the Committee's view. However, they all represent valuable contributions to the construction of a formulation that will take into account the complexity of what is at stake and will have real chances of being incorporated into the mental health laws of most countries.
For this to happen, several things are necessary: a) to promote all forms of debate that may help to build a new consensus; b) to ensure the participation in the discussion of a much broader range of stakeholders (e.g., different groups of people with mental disabilities, family members, mental health professionals with clinical experience, and experts in mental health legislation and policy); c) to clarify the definition of and the relations between relevant concepts (e.g., mental disorders, disabilities, psychosocial disabilities); d) to admit that, rather than concentrating our efforts on “an absolute prohibition on involuntary treatment (that) is, at least at present, not credible”4, we should “devote more time to thinking about how to make the essential practice of substitute decision‐making as respectful as possible”9; and e) to invest more on the reform of services and practices, without which no meaningful change in protection of the human rights of people with mental disorders will ever occur.
References
- 1. United Nations . Convention on the rights of persons with disabilities. New York: United Nations, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- 2. Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities . General Comment No. 1 on Article 12: Equal recognition before the law. CRPD/C/GC/1. 2014.
- 3. Freeman MC, Kolappa K, Caldas de Almeida JM et al. Lancet Psychiatry 2015;2:844‐50. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 4. Szmukler G. World Psychiatry 2019;18: 34‐41. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed]
- 5. Appelbaum PS. N Engl J Med 2007;357:1834‐40. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 6. Szmukler G, Daw R, Callard F. Int J Law Psychiatry 2014;37:245‐52. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 7. Dawson J, Szmukler G. Br J Psychiatry 2006;188:504‐9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 8. Scholten M, Gather J. J Med Ethics 2018;44:226‐33. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
- 9. Burch M. J Appl Philos 2017;34:389‐402. [Google Scholar]