Skip to main content
CNS Neuroscience & Therapeutics logoLink to CNS Neuroscience & Therapeutics
. 2016 Mar 1;22(4):275–279. doi: 10.1111/cns.12534

Head Transplants and Personal Identity: A Philosophical and Literary Survey

Giuliano Mori 1,2,
PMCID: PMC6492819  PMID: 27000479

Summary

The criterion of personal identity is clearly called into question by the project to perform a human head transplant. Is identity provided by psychological continuity alone, or does it depend on bodily continuity as well? And how do these different perspectives interface with our notion of mind and mind–body relationship? The reader will be provided with a discussion concerning these problems, together with a philosophical and literary survey about the conception of body–mind relationship from the Greek thought to contemporary philosophy. The analysis will conclude with a discussion concerning the possibility to consider the issue of personal identity from a statistic point of view, which privileges the general perception of identity, so as it has been shaped by the cultural trends of the last four centuries. It could hence be argued that personal identity is not something which can be defined once and for all. On the contrary, the general perception of identity is subject to significant alterations resulting from one's cultural environment. However, the cultural environment itself can be changed by particularly notable events, such as, hypothetically, the successful outcome of a human head transplant.

Keywords: Dualism, Head transplant, Monism, Perception and Personal Identity

Introduction

Aim of this article is to provide a tentative explanation for the sense of uneasiness which has spread throughout the most diverse cultural and professional milieux following the announcement of an upcoming human head transplant. The idea of a person being able to exchange his/her body for somebody else's has been perceived by the large majority of people as rather uncanny, or, in Freud's terms, unheimlich. However, much as this reaction has been produced more or less universally, its rationale seems to be cultural (depending on external factors and influences) rather than natural (depending on the inner qualities of an individual). In other words, such a response does not ensue from our nature of human beings, but from our cultural mindset, and, accordingly, it could have been different had it been elicited in a different cultural environment.

Transmogrification In Literary Works

One of the many ways to gain an insight into different mindsets and world pictures is to look at dreams in different historical and geographical contexts. The domain of dreams stands at the crossing between the natural and the cultural inasmuch as, although dreams obey universal psychological laws, the images conjured by dreamers are always dependent on their culture of provenance 1. The case of Artemidorus of Daldis, a professional interpreter of dreams of the 2nd century AD, is particularly eloquent. Working in a time when oneiromancy was an extremely common practice in the Greek society, Artemidorus' Oneirocritica provide us with an array of typical Greek dreams, which he had been told by his clients. Some of these present characteristic features which are still common nowadays; others would be instead extremely unusual for the present‐day dreamer 2. This is the case with dreams involving bodily metamorphoses, to which Artemidorus devoted a whole chapter of his book (I,50).

Thirteen out of the ninety‐five exemplar dreams listed in the fifth book of the Oneirocritica involve some transformation of one's own body 3. Arms becoming bear's paws (V,49), crops growing upon living chests (V,63), entire bodies being turned into the shape of a tree (V,74) are not only instances of a dream pattern which Artemidorus holds typical, but also of a certain ease which apparently characterized the Greek mentality in imagining one's own body being metamorphosed. Such ease is something we have probably lost. Indeed, we have no reason to doubt George Devereux as he states that “[b]oth my clinical experience and that of the colleagues I consulted, indicate that so radical a disruption of one's own ‘body image’ in dream is found only amongst psychotics—and rarely even amongst them” 2, 4.

If the honesty and accuracy of the clinical experience of the Hungarian–French psychoanalyst and anthropologist is beyond question, some doubts may be raised concerning his conclusions, namely that Artemidorus over‐interpreted the dreams he was told in order to make them meaningful 4. Excluding that Artemidorus' clients might have all been psychotics, Devereux's assumption is not the most probable. As Dodds well understood, it is “plainly hazardous” to apply the principles of modern psychoanalysis to ancient dreams inasmuch as we cannot prove “the universality of dream‐symbols” 5. These symbols are dependent on the dreamer's culture, and what is found only among psychotics nowadays might have been perfectly normal in Artemidorus' time.

This is clearly due to the cultural differences which set us apart from an ancient world in which the notion of bodily metamorphosis did not seem to impinge too much on one's notion of identity, therefore remaining psychologically “controllable.” This is not only proved by Hellenistic dreamers, but also by Latin authors such as Ovid and Apuleius. Ovid's Metamorphoseon libri, influenced by the same Alexandrian culture which would have provided Artemidorus with his interpretative tools, is mostly devoted to the description of mythological transformations.

Spahlinger's and Galinsky's observations according to which Ovid distinguished in the incipit of his work (I,1‐2) between corpora (material bodies), being changed through the metamorphic process, and formas which remain the same, alluding to the psychological essence of the metamorphosed individuals, may be mooted 6, 7, 8. Anyway, this notion is clearly illustrated by many of the metamorphoses described by Ovid. The metamorphosed subjects do not properly die: They survive instead in a different animal, vegetal, or even mineral body which never lacks to preserve the essence of their mens antiqua or mens pristina (original mind) 9, 10. Io, turned into a heifer by Zeus, passes her tongue over her father's hands and weeps 10; Callisto, although metamorphosed into a bear, is still afraid of the wild mountain animals 10; Cadmus and Harmonia, turned into serpents, do not shun nor harm men as they “remember what they were in the past” 10; and Acteon, turned into a stag and hounded by his dogs, tries to shout at them only to discover that his voice is lost, while “only his original mind remained unchanged” 10.

By the same token, roughly in the time of Artemidorus, identity and mind are preserved in Lucius’ metamorphosis into an ass, so as it is recounted by Apuleius in the Asinus aureus. Not unlike Ovid's Io, Apuleius’ Lucius, once deprived of his voice together with his human complexion, looks askance at his beloved Photis, and silently reproaches her for having inadvertently caused his transformation 11. Yet, even though Lucius is turned into a “perfect ass,” as he admits himself, he still is Lucius in that he “retained the human sense and understanding” 11.

This narrative patter which, in ancient instances of bodily transformation, never affects the inner self, the original mind, and, in short, the identity of the transformed individuals, was clearly abandoned by the authors of the last couple of centuries, from Christian Andersen's The Little Marmaid (1837) to George Langelaan's The Fly (1957) 12. The best known example of this change in perspective is offered perhaps by Franz Kafka's Metamorphosis. While Io or Lucius preserved a distinctively human conscience and, in spite of their metamorphosis, were recognized by their beloved ones, witness to the transformation, the destiny that awaits Gregor Samsa is a completely different one. Even though his parents and sister do not doubt the metamorphic process which has turned him into a cockroach, they are unable to consider him to be the Gregor they were used to. He is kept locked in his room, his mother shuns the sight of him with horror, and his father will even attempt at his life 13. Gregor himself begins to think as a cockroach “rapidly consigning his human past to utter oblivion” 13. In the end, even his sister becomes convinced that the cockroach into which her brother transformed has nothing to do with the true Gregor: “I will not utter my brother's name in front of this monster, so I will simply say: we must try to get rid of it…. ‘It has to go,’… ‘You must just try to get rid of the thought that it is Gregor’” 13.

It is certainly not by chance that Kafka's narrative should agree with Devereux's analysis in showing how the modern perception and mentality inextricably link bodily metamorphoses to disturbances of one's self and identity. The ancient nonchalance in accepting the persistence of the mens antiqua in fictional cases of bodily transformation has been substituted, in modern times, with a profound feeling of anxiety which, according to Devereux, can be linked to psychosis and schizophrenia. Should we try to find an explanation for this divergence between ancient and modern thought with respect to bodily metamorphoses, we could address the issue of dualism versus monism, that is, the debate whether the mind/soul (ψυχή) and the body may or may not be considered as two separate entities.

Monism versus Dualism and the Problem of Personal Identity

It can be safely affirmed that Greek philosophy and the Latin thought of the first centuries, which was greatly indebted to it, were generally speaking dualistic, even though not without notable exceptions. Ovid, Apuleius, and Artemidorus were all close to Pythagorean and Platonic philosophical traditions, which advocated the independence of the soul from the body. The former is not only immortal but, in Plato's formulation, is lodged in the body as in a prison or in a grave 14, 15. Men use their body, but are not their body since those who use something cannot be that which is used. On the contrary, man is the immortal soul lodged in the body 16. Therefore, it is clear that, should any bodily metamorphosis take place, the soul, and hence the self and identity, would remain intact.

Through the mediation of Paul and of the Platonic philosophers of the late Antiquity, this dualistic perspective was embraced by the Church Fathers, only to be later integrated by Scholastic philosophers into a generally Aristotelian system of thought which was in its original formulation materialistic and monist. Aristotelian physiology, which comprised Aristotle's doctrine of the soul, was in fact the polemical target of Descarte's De l'homme, where the body is described as a machine to which “God unites a rational soul” 17, 18. In general terms, although they are brought into contact with one another through the pineal gland, soul and body, thought and matter, are for Descartes two utterly diverse and incommensurable substances.

With the turn of the eighteenth century, dualistic positions became increasingly rare. Eighteenth‐century materialism and in general the whole French Enlightenment are an example of this trend toward monism. Julien Offray de La Mettrie, for instance, believed disembodied soul to be like matter without form—something which cannot even be imagined 19. Soul, in itself, “is merely a vain term of which we have no idea and which a good mind should use only to refer to that part of us which thinks” 20. During the nineteenth century, monist positions were held not only by materialistic philosophers (e.g. Ludwig Feuerbach, Karl Marx), but also, in nonreductionist terms, by spiritualists such as Henri Bergson, who aimed at providing a unitary explanation of both body and mind or, more precisely, matter and memory 21. With the turn of the twentieth century, a monist stance was advocated by many of the American pragmatists. John Dewey, for instance, considered “[t]he idea that matter, life and mind represent separate kinds of Being” a “philosophical error” 22. On the contrary, Dewey believes, there is an utter continuity between body and mind, so that “‘body’ designates the continued and conserved,… while ‘mind’ designates the… features which emerge when ‘body’ is engaged in a wider, more complex and interdependent situation.” This notion proved central for twentieth‐century phenomenology as well, as it clearly results from Maurice Merleau‐Ponty's work, and in particular from the Phénoménologie de la perception, were body is described as our way to be in the world and conscience as the way that the body transcends itself and becomes involved in the world 23.

In recent times, the materialist side of modern neuroscience linked mental states to physical processes occurring in the brain, so that it has become virtually impossible to state that thought and matter are something completely different and mutually independent (although a growing number of neuroscientists believe that “consciousness” is actually distinct from the brain, which merely acts as a filter 24, perhaps via quantum mechanical processes 25). However, what is more interesting for the topic at hand is that a new kind of dualism has gained significance, one which instead of opposing body and mind, concerns the relationship between the mind, embodied in the brain, and the body proper, that is our body, nervous tissue apart.

In these terms, whether one should accept a weak dualist position or not does not automatically orient one's choices toward either a dualist or monist stance with regard to the mind/brain–body proper issue. This is the case, for example, with John Searle. Although Searle rejects both mind–body dualism and monism, he quite clearly embraces a dualist position as far as it concerns the mind/brain–body proper problem 26. With regard to consciousness, his doctrine, which he names ‘biological naturalism’, advocates for instance that consciousness is “entirely caused by lower level neurobiological processes in the brain,” even though it exists only “at a level higher than that of neurons and synapses,” which are not conscious themselves 26. In other words, “consciousness stands to the brain as digestion stands to the movements of the stomach” 27. That said, according to Searle, consciousness has nearly nothing to do with the body proper, because it is entirely caused by processes occurring in the brain.

An opposite point of view about the mind/brain–body proper problem is defended by António Damásio, who believes that “body and brain form an indissociable organism” as they are “indissociably integrated by mutually targeted biochemical and neural circuits” 28. According to Damásio, the mind hence depends on the whole organism as an ensemble: It may not be in the body, but “the body contributes… a content that is part and parcel of the workings of the normal mind” 28.

Our tendency to side with one or the other perspective regarding the mind/brain–body proper relationship would greatly influence our expectations about a head transplant, in particular with regard to the issue of personal identity, which can be seen as a corollary of the mind/brain–body proper problem. If, like Searle, we posit the mind to be relatively independent of the body proper, we would probably assume that, in a Lockean manner, the criterion of personal identity should relate to the continuity of one's psychological experiences (thoughts, memories, etc.). If, like Damásio, we think instead that mind and body proper are indissociably bonded, we will be led to believe that our identity is provided not only by our mind but also by our body as opposed to any body. Our self and our sense of the self would then be granted not only by the continuity of our mental states, but also by the continuity of our body.

This last notion is clearly displayed in Damásio's monograph on self and identity, The Feeling of What Happens 29. Similar perspectives have been advocated by a number of scholars who have approached the issue of personal identity from a variety of different philosophical stances (e.g. Gallagher 30, Svenaeus 31, 32). The most ‘extreme’ position, among those who are inclined to believe personal identity to be inextricably linked to the body proper is the animalist one, which is best exampled in Erik Olson's What Are We? Olson's answer to this question is apparently simple: We are human animals. Hence, what we are is an animal body that encompasses nervous tissue in the same way that it encompasses epithelial or muscle tissue too. As a consequence, our identity, Olson believes, is provided by bodily rather than psychological continuity: indeed, we identify ourselves with the embryo we once were, even though “there is no psychological continuity between the embryo as it started out and the full‐grown animal,” since “the adult animal's mental properties cannot derive in any way from those of the embryo, for the embryo had none” 33.

The assumption according to which there is no psychological continuity between the embryo and the adult is perhaps contestable, in particular since it heavily depends on one's notion of ‘continuity,’ however, head transplant‐wise, it is to be noted that, for the animalist, the person resulting from a head transplant would be the body donor rather than the head donor. From Olson's point of view, brain/head transplant is ontologically no more relevant than kidney or liver transplant: we lose an organ, albeit a particularly interesting one.

Opposite to this view is the position of the so‐called psychological theorists, who generally depart from a dualistic stance with regard to the mind/brain–body proper relationship.1 In contrast to animalist theories, these philosophers believe that what matters in personal identity is psychological rather than bodily continuity. Besides, more or less implicitly assuming that the mind is lodged in the brain and does not significantly involve the body proper, psychological theorists claim that, were somebody's brain transplanted in somebody else's body, the resulting person would be the head/brain donor. This is, for instance, the opinion held by Sydney Shoemaker's, who wrote about hypothetical brain transplants in his 1963 book Self‐Knowledge and Self‐Identity, concluding that the criterion of personal identity is the continuity of one's own memories (or quasi‐memories, that is, in the transplant case, memories of actions which one's new body has never performed) 36, 37.

Similar, yet perhaps more complicated, is Derek Parfit's theory. Parfit believes that “a person is an entity that is distinct from his brain or body,” although it involves the existence of both 38. Personal identity would hence concern the persistence of both brain and body and, in particular, it would require the preservation of one's psychological continuity. That being said, Parfit continues, personal identity is not what matters in survival 38. On the contrary, what matters in survival is psychological continuity alone. In other words, in the hypothetical case that somebody's brain were transplanted into somebody else's body, the resulting person would be continuous with the head donor: “[i]f all of my brain continues both to exist and to be the brain of one living person, who is psychologically continuous with me, I continue to exist” 38, 39.

Personal Identity Reconsidered

Once stripped bare of its most rigorous and analytic demonstrative apparatus, Parfit's theory might seem slightly sophistical. However, these and similar doubts might be intrinsic to the purely theoretical nature of both Parift's and Olson's positions. Indeed, both animalists and psychological theorists have made extensive use in their works of the thought experiment concerning head/brain transplant, which has been named transplant intuition, since it tends to elicit an intuitively true conclusion on the part of the audience. Unsurprisingly, both animalists and psychological theorists have succeeded in formulating the transplant intuition in such a way as to force the reader to accept either the animalist or the psychological point of view 33, 36, 39. This possibility has also been proved by Bernard Williams, in his 1970 article The Self and the Future, in which two parallel thought experiments are formulated so as to elicit intuitively animalist or psychological conclusions 40.

In light of this, one of the undoubtedly praiseworthy effects which the Heaven project has yielded on the public opinion is that it has shown that, when the transplant intuition ceases to be purely theoretical it also ceases to be as intuitive as its name would lead us to believe. In other words, these thought experiments, which have been criticized by Daniel Dennett, who called them ‘intuition pumps,’ prove to be rather inefficient pumps when an actual patient lies on the operating table. This is not to say, of course, that the issue of personal identity is not a central point in the debate regarding head transplants. Rather, we may try to think about it in a way that is not purely theoretical and intuition‐inducing.

As gross and naïve this may sound, the way personal identity is generally perceived has little to do, in fact, with either Parfit's or Olson's theories. This conclusion may have motivated the recent work of some scholars who have undertaken a statistic inquiry on the perception of personal identity 41, 42. Although these authors have understandably failed to disentangle themselves from the chains of thought experiments, their works implicitly suggest that since personal identity, unlike issues of purely academic nature, is something which is sensed by everybody, we may conclude that a good enough definition of what personal identity in fact is may be provided by the way in which it is generally perceived, statistically speaking. In other terms, given the character of the notion of personal identity, and given in particular the fact that the way people perceive personal identity clearly influences personal identity itself, we may want to choose a more simplistic and commonplace definition over a sophisticated one.

The question arises, then, of how personal identity is generally perceived. My guess is that the general perception of personal identity generally involves our body proper, as I hope to have demonstrated through my analysis of ancient and modern metamorphoses 28. Otherwise, it would be difficult to explain the feeling of uneasiness which the Heaven project has generated in a nonmedical public. More precisely, I am under the impression that unlike the ancients, today's public, which is mirrored in Kafka's and Devereux's accounts, tends toward a roughly monist perspective. However, unsurprisingly, this monism, in its general conception, does not seem to resemble the sophisticated brain–mind monism embraced by virtually all contemporary neuroscientists and philosophers of mind. On the contrary, it still appears to approximate the simpler and more ancient ontological body–mind monism, hence proving extremely problematic with regard to the head/brain transplant issue.

A variety of sociological and psychological reasons could be cited to explain the nature of what I think to be today's general monism. Besides, from a cultural point of view, it is to be noted that, while I do not think that philosophical theories as such produce the general notion of personal identity, the general, viz., cultural perception of philosophical theories does undoubtedly influence it. And, as discussed earlier in this article, from the eighteenth century onwards, and up to the 1960s at least, most philosophical positions which have influenced our culture up to the present time have embraced a roughly speaking body–mind monist perspective.

If it be true that over the last centuries, these philosophical traditions have influenced our culture so much as to link the general perception of personal identity to a notion of body–mind relationship which is essentially monist in the ontological sense, one last doubt could be voiced with concern to the Heaven project. Indeed, one may think that the head anastomosis venture patient himself, being a man of our time, would surely encounter problems regarding personal identity. However, it is to be considered that the patient, that is, someone who is willing to undergo the head transplant procedure, certainly does not embrace the common perspective on the issue concerning body–mind monism and bodily continuity as a standard for personal identity. In the end, personal identity, or at least the perception of personal identity, is a personal matter, and provided the successful outcome of the transplant, the patient will or will not perceive himself to be the same person he was before regardless of the general notion of personal identity and regardless of Parfit's or Olson's theories. To put in different terms: “there are good reasons to leave it to the individual undergoing the transformation to negotiate the parameters of his or her identity, on her own terms and at her own pace” 35.

What is really interesting about this all is, then, a last question which, for the time being, is to be left open. If the head transplant patient recovers and experiences no major personality‐related issues, will this factual experience be enough to change the general conception of personal identity and to do so in a way unprecedented by thought experiments of any kind?

Note

1

It is to be noted that some philosophers have come to conclusions which somehow straddle the divide between animalists and psychological theorists. According to them, in the case of a brain/head transplant, the resulting person would not be the head nor the body donor, but a third person altogether 34, 35.

References

  • 1. Guidorizzi G. Introduction In: Guidorizzi G, editor. Il sogno in Grecia. Rome‐Bari: Laterza, 1988;vii–xxxviii. [Google Scholar]
  • 2. Guidorizzi G. Il compagno dell'anima: I Greci e il sogno. Milan: Cortina, 2013. [Google Scholar]
  • 3. Aretemidorus . Onirocriticon libri v Pack RA, editor. Leipzig: Teubner, 1963. [Google Scholar]
  • 4. Devereux G. Dreams in greek tragedy: An ethno‐psycho‐analytical study. Berkeley: U of California P, 1976. [Google Scholar]
  • 5. Dodds ER. The greeks and the irrational. Berkeley: U of California P, 1951. [Google Scholar]
  • 6. Spahlinger L. Ars latet arte sua: Untersuchungen zur Poetologie in den Metamorphosen Ovids. Leipzig: Teubner, 1996. [Google Scholar]
  • 7. Galinsky K. Ovid's Metamorphoses and Augustan Cultural Thematics In: Hardie P, et al., editors. Ovidian transformations: Essays on the metamorphoses and Its reception. Cambridge: Cambridge Philological Society, 1999;103–111. [Google Scholar]
  • 8. Feldherr A. Playing Gods: Ovid's Metamorphoses and the politics of fiction. Princeton UP: Princeton, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  • 9. Bernardini Marzolla P. Introduction In: Ovidio. Metamorfosi. Turin: Einaudi, 1994;vii–lxvii. [Google Scholar]
  • 10. Ovid . Metamorphoses In: Merkel R, editor. P. Ovidius Naso, Vol. 2. Leipzig: Teubner, 1863. [Google Scholar]
  • 11. Apuleius . Metamorphoseon libri In: Helm R, editor. Opera quae supersunt, Vol. 1. Leipzig: Teubner, 1907. [Google Scholar]
  • 12. Fusillo M. Metamorfosi In: Ceserani R, et al., editors. Dizionario dei temi letterari, vol. 2 Turin: Utet, 2007;1493–1497. [Google Scholar]
  • 13. Kafka F. The Metamorphosis In: Robertson R, editor. The metamorphosis and other stories. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2009;29–74. [Google Scholar]
  • 14. Plato . Phaedo In: Burnet J, editor. Platonis opera. Vol. 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1900;57–118. [Google Scholar]
  • 15. Plato . Gorgias In: Burnet J, editor. Platonis opera. Vol. 3. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1903;447–527. [Google Scholar]
  • 16. Plato . Alciabiades I In: Burnet J, editor. Platonis opera, Vol. 2. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1901;103–135. [Google Scholar]
  • 17. Descartes R. Treatise on Man In: Gaukroger S, editor. The world and other writings. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2004;99–169. [Google Scholar]
  • 18. Scribano E. Macchine con la mente: Fisiologia e metafisica tra Cartesio e Spinoza. Rome: Carocci, 2015. [Google Scholar]
  • 19. de La Mettrie JO. Histoire naturelle de l’âme. The Hague: Jean Neaulme, 1745. [Google Scholar]
  • 20. de La Mettrie JO. Machine Man In: Thomson A, editor. Machine man and other writings. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1996;1–39. [Google Scholar]
  • 21. Bergson H. Matière et mémoire: Essais sur la relation du corps à l'esprit. Paris: Félix Alcan, 1896. [Google Scholar]
  • 22. Dewey J. Experience and nature. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1929. [Google Scholar]
  • 23. Merleau‐Ponty M. Phénoménologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard, 1945. [Google Scholar]
  • 24. Penfield W. The mystery of the mind Princeton. Princeton UP: Princeton, 1975. [Google Scholar]
  • 25. Hameroff S, Penrose R. Consciousness in the universe: An updated review of the ‘ORCH OR’ THEORY In: Poznanski RR, Tuszynski J, Feiberg TE, editors. Biophysics of consciousness: A foundational approach. Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Co, 2016;Forthcoming. [Google Scholar]
  • 26. Searle JR. Mind: A brief introduction. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2004. [Google Scholar]
  • 27. Rust J. John searle. London: Continuum Press, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  • 28. Damásio AR. Descartes' error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Avon Books, 1994. [Google Scholar]
  • 29. Damásio AR. The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  • 30. Gallagher S. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005. [Google Scholar]
  • 31. Svenaeus F. Organ transplantation and personal identity: How does loss and change of organs affect the self? J Med Philos 2012;37:139–158. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  • 32. Svenaeus F. The Lived Body and Personal identity: The Ontology of Exiled Body Parts In: Malmqvist E, Zeiler K, editors. Bodily exchanges, bioethics and border crossing: Perspectives on giving, selling and sharing bodies. London: Routledge, 2016;19–34. [Google Scholar]
  • 33. Olson ET. What Are We? a study in personal ontology. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  • 34. Wiggins D. Sameness and substance renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2001. [Google Scholar]
  • 35. Pascalev A, Pascalev M, Giordano J. Head transplants, personal identity and neuroethics. Neuroethics 2015;8:1–8. [Google Scholar]
  • 36. Shoemaker S. Self‐knowledge and self‐identity. Ithaca: Cornell UP, 1963. [Google Scholar]
  • 37. Shoemaker S. Persons and their pasts. Am Phil Quart 1970;7:269–285. [Google Scholar]
  • 38. Parfit D. Reason and person. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984. [Google Scholar]
  • 39. Parfit D. We are not human beings. Philosophy 2012;87:5–28. [Google Scholar]
  • 40. Williams B. The self and the future. Philos Rev 1970;79:161–180. [Google Scholar]
  • 41. Blok S, Newman G, Rips LJ. Individuals and Their Concepts In: Ahn W‐K, et al., editors. Categorization inside and outside the laboratory. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association, 2005;127–149. [Google Scholar]
  • 42. Nichols S, Bruno M. Intuitions about personal identity: An empirical study. Philos Psychol 2010;23:293–312. [Google Scholar]

Articles from CNS Neuroscience & Therapeutics are provided here courtesy of Wiley

RESOURCES